Outlines of Louis F. Post's
Lectures
on The Single Tax ~
Absolute Free Trade ~
The Labor Question ~
Progress and Poverty ~
The Land Question ~
The Elements of Political Economy ~
Socialism ~ Hard Times
with Illustrative Notes & Charts
and FAQ
copyright 1894
Prefatory Note
I. The Single Tax Defined
II. The Single Tax as a Fiscal Reform
1. Direct and Indirect Taxation
2. The Two Kinds of Direct Taxation
(1) In proportion to ability to pay;
and (2) in proportion to benefits received.
3. The Single Tax Falls in Proportion to Benefits
4. Conformity to General Principles of Taxation
(a) Interference with Production
(b) Cheapness of Collection
(c) Certainty
(d) Equality
III. The Single Tax as a Social
Reform
1. The Source of Wealth (Charts)
2. The Production of Wealth
(a) Division of Labor
(Charts)
(b) Trade (Charts)
(c) The Law of Division of Labor
and Trade (Charts)
Note
72. Mechanism of Trade (Charts)
(d) Dependence of Labor Upon Land
(Chart)
3. The Distribution of Wealth
(a) Explanation of Wages and
Rent
(b) Normal Effect of Social
Progress upon Wages and Rent
(c) Significance of the Upward
Tendency of Rent
(d) Effect of Confiscating Rent
to Private Use
(e) Effect of Retaining Rent for
Common Use
Conclusion
FAQ
PREFATORY NOTE
These "Outlines," while giving neither the
substance nor the arrangement of any of the lectures named
in the title, contain the leading points of all. But to
make the points consecutive they have been woven into one
of the lectures — that on the Single Tax. This,
however, is not arbitrary, for the philosophy of the single
tax involves the elementary principles of absolute free
trade, of the labor question, of poverty with progress, of
the land question, and of political economy; and while
exposing the fallacies of socialism it explains the problem
of hard times.
The "Outlines" do not take the place of the lectures.
They are published merely to prepare the mind of the reader
in advance to more fully appreciate the lectures during
delivery, and to assist afterward in recalling and
deliberately considering and criticizing what is advanced
from the platform. To this end the principal charts of all
the lectures are reproduced.
The text in large type is a connected explanation. It
may be read and fully understood without reference to the
notes. But the notes elaborate and illustrate points which
from the conciseness of their statement in the text may
seem obscure to readers who are unaccustomed to economic
thought.
I. THE SINGLE TAX
DEFINED
The practical form in which Henry George puts the idea
of appropriating economic rent to common use is "To
abolish all taxation save that upon land
values."1
1.
"Progress and Poverty," book viii,
ch. ii.
This is now generally known as "The Single
Tax."2 Under its operation all
classes of workers, whether manufacturers, merchants,
bankers, professional men, clerks, mechanics, farmers,
farm-hands, or other working classes, would, as
such, be wholly exempt. It is only as men own land
that they would be taxed, the tax of each being in
proportion, not to the area, but to value of his land. And
no one would be compelled to pay a higher tax than others
if his land were improved or used while theirs was not, nor
if his were better improved or better used than theirs.3
The value of its improvements would not be considered in
estimating the value of a holding; site value alone would
govern.4 If a site rose in the market the tax would
proportionately increase; if that fell, the tax would
proportionately diminish.
2.
In "Progress and Poverty," book viii,
ch. iv, Henry George speaks of "the effect of
substituting for the manifold taxes now imposed, a
single tax on the value of land; but the term did
not become a distinctive name until 1888.
The first general movement along the lines
of "Progress and Poverty" began New York City election of
1886, when Henry George polled 68,110 votes as an
independent candidate for mayor, and was defeated by the
Democratic candidate, Abram S. Hewitt, by a plurality of
only 22,442, the Republican, Theodore Roosevelt, polling
but 60,435. Following that election the United Labor
Party was formed, the Syracuse Convention in August,
1887, by the exclusion of the Socialists, came to present
the central idea of "Progress and Poverty" as
distinguished from the Socialistic propaganda which until
then was identified with it. Coincident with the
organization of the United Labor Party the Anti-Poverty
Society was formed; and the two bodies, one representing
the political and the other the religious phase of the
idea, worked together until President Cleveland's tariff
message of 1887 appeared. In this message Mr. George saw
the timid beginnings of that open struggle between
protection and free trade to which he had for years
looked forward as the political movement that must
culminate in the abolition of all taxes save those upon
land values, and he responded at once to the sentiments
of the message. But many protectionists, who had followed
him because they supposed he was a land nationalizer, now
broke away from his leadership, and the United Labor
Party and the Anti-Poverty Society were soon practically
dissolved. Those who understood Mr. George's real
position regarding the land question readily acquiesced
in his views as to political policy, and a considerable
movement resulted, which, however, for some time lacked
an identifying name. This was the situation when Thomas
G. Shearman, Esq., wrote for the Standard an
article on taxation in which he illustrated and advocated
the land value tax as a fiscal measure. The article had
been submitted without a caption, and Mr. George, then
the editor of the Standard, entitled it "The
Single Tax." This title was at once adopted by the
"George men," as they were often called, and has ever
since served as the name of the movement it
describes.
Though "the single tax" is the English form
of "l'impot unique" the name of the French
physiocratic doctrine of the eighteenth century, the
names have no historical connection, and they stand for
different ideas.
3. When it is remembered that some land in
cities is worth millions of dollars an acre, that a small
building lot in the business center of even a small
village is worth more than a whole field of the best
farming land in the neighborhood, that a few acres of
coal or iron land are worth more than great groups of
farms, that the right of way of a railroad company
through a thickly settled district or between important
points is worth more than its rolling stock, and that the
value of workingmen's cottages in the suburbs is trifling
in comparison with the value of city residence sites, the
absurdity, if not the dishonesty, of the plea that the
single tax would discriminate against farmers and small
home owners and in favor of the rich is apparent. The bad
faith of this plea is emphasized when we consider that
under existing systems of taxation the farmer and the
poor home owner are compelled to pay in taxes upon
improvements, food, clothing, and other objects of
consumption, much more than the full annual value of
their bare land.
4. The difference between site value and
improvement value is much more definite than it is often
supposed to be. Even in what would seem at first to be
most confusing cases, it is easily distinguished. If in
any example we imagine the complete destruction of all
the improvements, we may discover in the remaining value
of the property — in the price it would after such
destruction fetch in the real estate market — the
value of the site as distinguished from the value of the
improvements. This residuum of value would be the basis
of computation for levying the single tax.
The distinction is frequently made in
business life. Whenever in the course of ordinary
business affairs it becomes necessary to estimate the
value of a building lot, or to fix royalties for mining
privileges, no difficulty is experienced, and substantial
justice is done. And though the exigencies of business
seldom require the site value of an improved farm to be
distinguished from the value of its improvements, yet it
could doubtless be done as easily and justly as with city
or mining property. Unimproved land attached to any farm
in question, or unimproved land in the neighborhood, if
similar in fertility and location, would furnish a
sufficiently accurate measure. If neither existed, the
value of the contiguous highway would always be
available.
It should not be forgotten that land for
which the demand is so weak that its site value cannot be
easily distinguished from the value of its improvements,
is certain to be land of but little value, and almost
certain to have no value at all.
The objection that the value of land cannot
be distinguished from the value of its improvements is
among the most frivolous of the objections that have been
raised to the single tax by people with whom the wish
that it may be impracticable is father to the thought
that it really is so.
The single tax may be concisely described as a tax upon
land alone, in the ratio of value, irrespective of
improvements or use.
II. THE SINGLE TAX AS A FISCAL REFORM
1. DIRECT AND INDIRECT TAXATION
Taxes are either direct or indirect;
or, as they have been aptly described, "straight" or
"crooked." Indirect taxes are those that may be shifted by
the first payer from himself to others; direct taxes are
those that cannot be shifted.5
5. "Taxes are either direct or indirect. A
direct tax is one which is demanded from the very persons
who, it is intended or desired, should pay it. Indirect
taxes are those which are demanded from one person in the
expectation and intention that he shall indemnify himself
at the expense of another." — John Stuart
Mill's Prin. of Pol. Ec., book v, ch. iii, sec.
I.
"Direct taxes are those which are levied on
the very persons who it is intended or desired should pay
them, and which they cannot put off upon others by
raising the prices of the taxed article.. . . Indirect
taxes on the other hand are those which are levied on
persons who expect to get back the amount of the tax by
raising the price of the taxed article." —
Laughlin's Elements, par. 249.
Taxes are direct "when the payment is made
by the person who is intended to bear the sacrifice."
Indirect taxes are recovered from final purchasers.
— Jevons's Primer, sec. 96.
"Indirect taxes are so called because they
are not paid into the treasury by the person who really
bears the burden. The payer adds the amount of the tax to
the price of the commodity taxed, and thus the taxation
is concealed under the increased price of some article of
luxury or convenience." — Thompson's Pol.
Ec., sec. 175.
The shifting of indirect taxes is accomplished by means
of their tendency to increase the prices of commodities on
which they fall. Their magnitude and incidence 6 are
thereby disguised. It was for this reason that a great
French economist of the last century denounced them as "a
scheme for so plucking geese as to get the most feathers
with the least squawking."7
6. Jevons defines the incidence of a tax as
"the manner in which it falls upon different classes of
the population." — Jevons's Primer, sec.
96.
Sometimes called "repercussion," and refers "to the real
as opposed to the nominal payment of taxes." —
Ely's Taxation, p. 64.
7. Though his language was blunt, the
sentiment does not essentially differ from that of
"statesmen" of our day who meet all the moral and
economic objections to indirect taxation with the one
reply that the people would not consent to pay enough or
the support of government if public revenues were
collected from them directly. This means nothing but that
the people are actually hoodwinked by indirect taxation
into sustaining a government that they would not support
if they knew it was maintained at their expense; and
instead of being a reason for continuing indirect
taxation, would, if true, be one of the strongest of
reasons for abolishing it. It is consistent neither with
the plainest principles of democracy nor the simplest
conceptions of morality.
Indirect taxation costs the real tax-payers much more
than the government receives, partly because the middlemen
through whose hands taxed commodities pass are able to
exact compound profits upon the tax,8 and partly on account
of extraordinary expenses of original collection;9 it
favors corruption in government by concealing from the
people the fact that they contribute to the support of
government; and it tends, by obstructing production, to
crush legitimate industry and establish monopolies.10 The
questions it raises are of vastly more concern than is
indicated by the sum total of public expenditures.
8. A tax upon shoes, paid in the first
instance by shoe manufacturers, enters into
manufacturers' prices, and, together with the usual rate
of profit upon that amount of investment, is recovered
from wholesalers. The tax and the manufacturers' profit
upon it then constitute part of the wholesale price and
are collected from retailers. The retailers in turn
collect the tax with all intermediate profits upon it,
together with their usual rate of profit upon the whole,
from final purchasers — the consumers of shoes.
Thus what appears on the surface to be a tax upon shoe
manufacturers proves upon examination to be an indirect
tax upon shoe consumers, who pay in an accumulation of
profits upon the tax considerably more than the
government receives.
The effect would be the same if a tax upon
their leather output were imposed upon tanners. Tanners
would add to the price of leather the amount of the tax,
plus their usual rate of profit upon a like investment,
and collect the whole, together with the cost of hides,
of transportation, of tanning and of selling, from shoe
manufacturers, who would collect with their profit from
retailers, who would collect with their profit from shoe
consumers. The principle applies also when taxes are
levied upon the stock or the sales of merchants, or the
money or credits of bankers; merchants add the tax with
the usual profit to the prices of their goods, and
bankers add it to their interest and discounts.
For example; a tax of $100,000 upon the
output of manufacturers or importers would, at 10 per
cent as the manufacturing profit, cost wholesalers
$110,000; at a profit of 10 per cent to wholesalers it
would cost retailers $121,000, and at 20 percent profit
to retailers it would finally impose a tax burden of
$145,200 — being 45 per cent more than the
government would get. Upon most commodities the number of
profits exceeds three, so that indirect taxes may
frequently cost as much as 100 per cent, even when
imposed only upon what are commercially known as finished
goods; when imposed upon materials also, the cost of
collection might well run far above 200 percent in
addition to the first cost of maintaining the machinery
of taxation.
It must not be supposed, however, that the
recovery of indirect taxes from the ultimate consumers of
taxed goods is arbitrary. When shoe manufacturers, or
tanners, or merchants add taxes to prices, or bankers add
them to interest, it is not because they might do
otherwise but choose to do this; it is because the
exigencies of trade compel them. Manufacturers,
merchants, and other tradesmen who carry on competitive
businesses must on the average sell their goods at cost
plus the ordinary rate of profit, or go out of business.
It follows that any increase in cost of production tends
to increase the price of products. Now, a tax upon the
output of business men, which they must pay as a
condition of doing their business, is as truly part of
the cost of their output as is the price of the materials
they buy or the wages of the men they hire. Therefore,
such a tax upon business men tends to increase the price
of their products. And this tendency is more or less
marked as the tax is more or less great and competition
more or less keen.
It is true that a moderate tax upon
monopolized products, such as trade-mark goods,
proprietary medicines, patented articles and copyright
publications is not necessarily shifted to consumers. The
monopoly manufacturer whose prices are not checked by
cost of production, and are therefore as a rule higher
than competitive prices would be, may find it more
profitable to bear the burden of a tax that leaves him
some profit, by preserving his entire custom, than to
drive off part of his custom by adding the tax to his
usual prices. This is true also of a moderate import tax
to the extent it falls upon goods that are more cheaply
transported from the place of production to a foreign
market where the import tax is imposed than to a home
market where the goods would be free of such a tax
— products, for instance, of a farm in Canada near
to a New York town, but far away from any Canadian town.
If the tax be less than the difference in the cost of
transportation the producer will bear the burden of it;
otherwise he will not. The ultimate effect would be a
reduction in the value of the Canadian land. Examples
which may be cited in opposition to the principle that
import taxes are indirect, will upon examination prove to
be of the character here described. Business cannot be
carried on at a loss — not for long.
9. "To collect taxes, to prevent and punish
evasions, to check and countercheck revenue drawn from so
many distinct sources, now make up probably
three-fourths, perhaps seven-eighths, of the business of
government outside of the preservation of order, the
maintenance of the military arm, and the administration
of justice." — Progress and Poverty, book iv,
ch: v
10. For a brief and thorough exposition of
indirect taxation read George's "Protection or Free
Trade," ch. viii, on " Tariffs for Revenue."
Whoever calmly reflects and candidly decides upon the
merits of indirect taxation must reject it in all its
forms. But to do that is to make a great stride toward
accepting the single tax. For the single tax is a form of
direct taxation; it cannot be shifted.11
11. This is usually a stumbling block to
those who, without much experience in economic thought,
consider the single tax for the first time. As soon as
they grasp the idea that taxes upon commodities shift to
consumers they jump to the conclusion that similarly
taxes upon land values would shift to the users. But this
is a mistake, and the explanation is simple. Taxes upon
what men produce make production more difficult and so
tend toward scarcity in the supply, which stimulates
prices; but taxes upon land, provided the taxes be levied
in proportion to value, tend toward plenty in supply
(meaning market supply of course), because they make it
more difficult to hold valuable land idle, and so depress
prices.
"A tax on rent falls wholly on the
landlord. There are no means by which he can shift the
burden upon anyone else. . . A tax on rent, therefore,
has no effect other than its obvious one. It merely takes
so much from the landlord and transfers it to the state."
— John Stuart Mill's Prin. of Pol. Ec., book v,
ch. iii, sec. 1.
"A tax laid upon rent is borne solely by
the owner of land." — Bascom's Tr.,
p.159.
"Taxes which are levied on land . . .
really fall on the owner of the land." — Mrs.
Fawcett's Pol. Ec. for Beginners, pp.209, 210.
"A land tax levied in proportion to the
rent of land, and varying with every variation of rents,
. . . will fall wholly on the landlords." —
Walker's Pol. Ec., ed. of 1887, p. 413, quoting
Ricardo.
"The power of transferring a tax from the
person who actually pays it to some other person varies
with the object taxed. A tax on rents cannot be
transferred. A tax on commodities is always transferred
to the consumer." — Thorold Rogers's Pol. Ec.,
ch. xxi, 2d ed., p. 285.
"Though the landlord is in all cases the
real contributor, the tax is commonly advanced by the
tenant, to whom the landlord is obliged to allow it in
payment of the rent." — Adam Smith's Wealth of
Nations, book v, ch. ii, part ii, art. i.
"The way taxes raise prices is by
increasing the cost of production and checking supply.
But land is not a thing of human production, and taxes
upon rent cannot check supply. Therefore, though a tax
upon rent compels land-owners to pay more, it gives them
no power to obtain more for the use of their land, as it
in no way tends to reduce the supply of land. On the
contrary, by compelling those who hold land on
speculation to sell or let for what they can get, a tax
on land values tends to increase the competition between
owners, and thus to reduce the price of land." —
Progress and Poverty, book viii, ch. iii, subd.
i.
Sometimes this point is raised as a
question of shifting the tax in higher rent to the
tenant, and at others as a question of shifting it to the
consumers of goods in higher prices. The principle is the
same. Merchants cannot charge higher prices for goods
than their competitors do, merely because they pay higher
ground rents. A country storekeeper whose business lot is
worth but few dollars charges as much for sugar, probably
more, than a city grocer whose lot is worth thousands.
Quality for quality and quantity for quantity, goods sell
for about the same price everywhere. Differences in price
are altogether in favor of places where land has a high
value. This is due to the fact that the cost of getting
goods to places of low land value, distant villages for
example, is greater than to centers, which are places of
high land value. Sometimes it is true that prices for
some things are higher where land values are high.
Tiffany's goods, for instance, may be more expensive than
goods of the same quality at a store on a less expensive
site. But that is not due to the higher land value; it is
because the dealer has a reputation for technical
knowledge and honesty (or has become a fad among rich
people), for which his customers are willing to pay
whether his store is on a high priced-lot or a low-priced
one.
Though land value has no effect upon the
price of good, it is easier to sell goods in some
locations than in others. Therefore, though the price and
the profit of each sale be the same, or even less, in
good locations than in poorer ones, aggregate receipts
and aggregate profits are much greater at the good
location. And it is out of his aggregate, and not out of
each profit, that rent is paid, For example: A cigar
store on a thoroughfare supplies a certain quality of
cigar for fifteen cents. On a side street the same
quality of cigar can be bought no cheaper. Indeed, the
cigars there are likely to be poorer, and therefore
really dearer. Yet ground rent on the thoroughfare is
very high compared with ground rent on the sidestreet.
How, then, can the first dealer, he who pays the high
ground rent, afford to sell as good or better cigars for
fifteen cents than his competitor of the low priced
location? Simply because he is able to make so many more
sales with a given outlay of labor and capital in a given
time that his aggregate profit is greater. This is due to
the advantage of his location, and for that advantage he
pays a premium in higher ground rent. But that premium is
not charged to smokers; the competing dealer of the side
street protects them. It represents the greater ease, the
lower cost, of doing a given volume of business upon the
site for which it is paid; add if the state should take
any of it, even the whole of it, in taxation, the loss
would be finally borne by the owner of the advantage
which attaches to that site — by the landlord. Any
attempt to shift it to tenant or buyer would be promptly
checked by the competition of neighboring but cheaper
land.
"A land-tax, levied in proportion to the
rent of land, and varying with every variation of rent,
is in effect a tax on rent; and as such a tax will not
apply to that land which yields no rent, nor to the
produce of that capital which is employed on the land
with a view to profit merely, and which never pays rent;
it will not in any way affect the price of raw produce,
but will fall wholly on the landlords." —
McCulloch's Ricardo (3d ed.), p. 207
2. THE TWO KINDS OF DIRECT
TAXATION
Direct taxes fall into two general classes: (1) Taxes that
are levied upon men in proportion to their ability to
pay, and (2) taxes that are levied in proportion to
the benefits received by the tax-payer from the
public. Income taxes are the principal ones of the first
class, though probate and inheritance taxes would rank
high. The single tax is the only important one of the
second class.
There should be no difficulty in choosing between the
two. To tax in proportion to ability to pay, regardless of
benefits received, is in accord with no principle of just
government; it is a device of piracy. The single tax,
therefore, as the only important tax in proportion to
benefits, is the ideal tax.
But here we encounter two plausible objections. One
arises from the mistaken but common notion that men are not
taxed in proportion to benefits unless they pay taxes upon
every kind of property they own that comes under the
protection of government; the other is founded in the
assumption that it is impossible to measure the value of
the public benefits that each individual enjoys. Though the
first of these objections ostensibly accepts the doctrine
of taxation according to benefits,12 yet, as it leads to
attempts at taxation in proportion to wealth, it, like the
other, is really a plea for the piratical doctrine of
taxation according to ability to pay. The two objections
stand or fall together.
12. It is often said, for instance, by its
advocates, that house owners should in justice contribute
to the support of the fire departments that protect them
and it is even gravely argued that houses are more
appropriate subjects of taxation than land; because they
need protection, whereas land needs none. Read note
8.
Let it once be perceived that the value of the service
which government renders to each individual would be justly
measured by the single tax, and neither objection would any
longer have weight. We should then no more think of taxing
people in proportion to their wealth or ability to pay,
regardless of the benefits they receive from government
than an honest merchant would think of charging his
customers in proportion to their wealth or ability to pay,
regardless of the value of the goods they bought of him."
13
13. Following is an interesting computation
of the cost and loss to the city of Boston of the present
mixed system of taxation as compared with the single tax;
The computation was made by James R. Carret, Esq., the
leading conveyancer of Boston:
Valuation of Boston, May 1,
1892 Land... ... . .. ...
.. ... .. $399,170,175 Buildings ... ... ... ... ..$281,109,700
Total assessed value of real estate
$680,279,875 Assessed value
of personal estate $213,695,829
.... .... ... ... ... ... ... ...
.... .... .... ... .... ... $893,975,704
Rate of taxation, $12.90 per $1000
Total tax levy, May 1, 1892 $11,805,036
Amount of taxes levied in respect of the
different subjects of taxation and percentages of the
same:
Land .... .... .... .... $5,149,295 43.62%
Buildings .... .... .. $3,626,295 30.72%
Personal estate .. $2,756,676 23.35%
Polls ... .... ... .... .... ...272,750
2.31%
But to ascertain the total cost to the
people of Boston of the present system of taxation for
the taxable year, beginning May 1, 1892, there should be
added to the taxes assessed upon them what it cost them
to pay the owners of the land of Boston for the use of
the land, being the net ground rent, which I estimate at
four per cent on the land value.
Total tax levy, May 1, 1892 ... ...
... ... .... .... .... .... .... ..... .... .... ....
.... .... .... ..$11,805,036 Net ground rent, four percent, on the land value
($399,170,175)..... ... ... ...$15,966,807
Total cost of the present system to the
people of Boston for that year ... $27,771,843
To contrast this with what the single tax
system would have cost the people of Boston for that
year, take the gross ground rent, found by adding to the
net ground rent the taxation on land values for that
year, being $12.90 per $1000, or 1.29 per cent added to 4
per cent = 5.29 per cent.
Total cost of present system as above
.. .... .... .... .... .... .... .... ....
....$27,771,843 Single tax,
or gross ground rent, 5.29 per cent on $399,170,175 ...
..$21,116,102 Excess cost
of present system, which is the sum of
taxes in respect of buildings, personal
property, and polls .... ...... .. $6,655,741
But the present system not only costs the
people more than the single tax would, but produces less
revenue:
Proceeds of single tax ... ... ...
... ..... .... .... ..... .... .... .... ..... ..... ....
$21,116,102 Present tax
levy ... ... ... ... ... .... .... .... ..... .... ....
.... .... .... .... .... ....$11,805,036
Loss to public treasury by present
system ... .... .... .... .... .. .....
..$9,311,066
This, however, is not a complete contrast
between the present system and the single tax, for large
amounts of real estate are exempt from taxation, being
held by the United States, the Commonwealth, by the city
itself, by religious societies and corporations, and by
charitable, literary, and scientific institutions. The
total amount of the value of land so held as returned by
the assessors for the year 1892 is $60,626,171.
Reasons can be given why all lands within
the city should be assessed for taxation to secure a just
distribution of the public burdens, which I cannot take
the space to enter into here. There is good reason to
believe also that lands in the city of Boston are
assessed to quite an appreciable extent below their fair
market value. As an indication of this see an editorial
in the Boston Daily Advertiser for October 3,
1893, under the title, "Their Own Figures."
The vacant lands, marsh lands, and flats in
Boston were valued by the assessors in 1892 (page 3 of
their annual report) at $52,712,600. I believe that this
represents not more than fifty per cent of their true
market value.
Taking this and the undervaluation of
improved property and the exemptions above mentioned into
consideration, I think $500,000,000 to be a fair estimate
of the land values of Boston. Making this the basis of
contrast, we have:
Proceeds of single tax 5.29 per cent
on $500,000,000 ... .... .... ....
$26,450,000 Present tax
levy ... .... ... .... .... .... .... .... ..... ....
.... .... .... ..... .... .... ..$11,805,036
Loss to public treasury by present
system ... ... ... ... .... .... ....
....$14,644,974
3. THE SINGLE TAX FALLS IN PROPORTION TO
BENEFITS
To perceive that the single tax would justly measure the
value of government service we have only to realize that
the mass of individuals everywhere and now, in paying for
the land they use, actually pay for government service in
proportion to what they receive. He who would enjoy the
benefits of a government must use land within its
jurisdiction. He cannot carry land from where government is
poor to where it is good; neither can he carry it from
where the benefits of good government are few or enjoyed
with difficulty to where they are many and fully enjoyed.
He must rent or buy land where the benefits of government
are available, or forego them. And unless he buys or rents
where they are greatest and most available he must forego
them in degree. Consequently, if he would work or live
where the benefits of government are available, and does
not already own land there, he will be compelled to rent or
buy at a valuation which, other things being equal, will
depend upon the value of the government service that the
site he selects enables him to enjoy. 14 Thus does he pay
for the service of government in proportion to its value to
him. But he does not pay the public which provides the
service; he is required to pay land-owners.
14. Land values are lower in all countries
of poor government than in any country of better
government, other things being equal. They are lower in
cities of poor government, other things being equal, than
in cities of better government. Land values are lower,
for example, in Juarez, on the Mexican side of the Rio
Grande, where government is bad, than in El Paso, the
neighboring city on the American side, where government
is better. They are lower in the same city under bad
government than under improved government. When Seth Low,
after a reform campaign, was elected mayor of Brooklyn,
N.Y., rents advanced before he took the oath of office,
upon the bare expectation that he would eradicate
municipal abuses. Let the city authorities anywhere pave
a street, put water through it and sewer it, or do any of
these things, and lots in the neighborhood rise in value.
Everywhere that the "good roads" agitation of wheel men
has borne fruit in better highways, the value of adjacent
land has increased. Instances of this effect as results
of public improvements might be collected in abundance.
Every man must be able to recall some within his own
experience.
And it is perfectly reasonable that it
should be so. Land and not other property must rise in
value with desired improvements in government, because,
while any tendency on the part of other kinds of property
to rise in value is checked by greater production, land
can not be reproduced.
Imagine an utterly lawless place, where
life and property are constantly threatened by
desperadoes. He must be either a very bold man or a very
avaricious one who will build a store in such a community
and stock it with goods; but suppose such a man should
appear. His store costs him more than the same building
would cost in a civilized community; mechanics are not
plentiful in such a place, and materials are hard to get.
The building is finally erected, however, and stocked.
And now what about this merchant's prices for goods?
Competition is weak, because there are few men who will
take the chances he has taken, and he charges all that
his customers will pay. A hundred per cent, five hundred
per cent, perhaps one or two thousand per cent profit
rewards him for his pains and risk. His goods are dear,
enormously dear — dear enough to satisfy the most
contemptuous enemy of cheapness; and if any one should
wish to buy his store that would be dear too, for the
difficulties in the way of building continue. But
land is cheap! This is the type of community in
which may be found that land, so often mentioned and so
seldom seen, which "the owners actually can't give away,
you know!"
But suppose that government improves. An
efficient administration of justice rids the place of
desperadoes, and life and property are safe. What about
prices then? It would no longer require a bold or
desperately avaricious man to engage in selling goods in
that community, and competition would set in. High
profits would soon come down. Goods would be cheap
— as cheap as anywhere in the world, the cost of
transportation considered. Builders and building
materials could be had without difficulty, and stores
would be cheap, too. But land would be dear!
Improvement in government increases the value of that,
and of that alone.
Now, the economic principle pursuant to which
land-owners are thus able to charge their fellow-citizens
for the common benefits of their common government points
to the true method of taxation. With the exception of such
other monopoly property as is analogous to land titles, and
which in the purview of the single tax is included with
land for purposes of taxation, 15 land is the only kind of
property that is increased in value by government; and the
increase of value is in proportion, other influences aside,
to the public service which its possession secures to the
occupant. Therefore, by taxing land in proportion to its
value, and exempting all other property, kindred monopolies
excepted — that is to say, by adopting the single tax
— we should be levying taxes according to
benefits.16
15. Railroad franchises, for example, are
not usually thought of as land titles, but that is what
they are. By an act of sovereign authority they confer
rights of control for transportation purposes over narrow
strips of land between terminals and along trading
points. The value of this right of way is a land
value.
16. Each occupant would pay to his landlord
the value of the public benefits in the way of highways,
schools, courts, police and fire protection, etc., that
his site enabled him to enjoy. The landlord would pay a
tax proportioned to the pecuniary benefits conferred upon
him by the public in raising and maintaining the value of
his holding. And if occupant and owner were the same, he
would pay directly according to the value of his land for
all the public benefits he enjoyed, both intangible and
pecuniary.
And in no sense would this be class taxation. Indeed,
the cry of class taxation is a rather impudent one for
owners of valuable land to raise against the single tax,
when it is considered that under existing systems of
taxation they are exempt. 17 Even the poorest and the most
degraded classes in the community, besides paying
land-owners for such public benefits as come their way, are
compelled by indirect taxation to contribute to the support
of government. But landowners as a class go free. They
enjoy the protection of the courts, and of police and fire
departments, and they have the use of schools and the
benefit of highways and other public improvements, all in
common with the most favored, and upon the same specific
terms; yet, though they go through the form of paying
taxes, and if their holdings are of considerable value pose
as "the tax-payers" on all important occasions,
they, in effect and considered as a class, pay no taxes,
because government, by increasing the value of their land,
enables them to recover back in higher rents and higher
prices more than their taxes amount to. Enjoying the same
tangible benefits of government that others do, many of
them as individuals and all of them as a class receive in
addition a tangible pecuniary benefit which government
confers upon no other property-owners. The value of their
property is enhanced in proportion to the benefits of
government which its occupants enjoy. To tax them alone,
therefore, is not to discriminate against them; it is to
charge them for what they get.18
17. While the landholders of the City of
Washington were paying something less than two per cent
annually in taxes, a Congressional Committee (Report
of the Select Committee to Investigate Tax Assessments in
the District of Columbia, composed of Messrs. Johnson, of
Ohio, Chairman, Wadsworth, of New York, and Washington,
of Tennessee. Made to the House of Representatives, May
24, 1892. Report No. 1469), brought out the fact
that the value of their land had been increasing at a
minimum rate of ten per cent per annum. The Washington
land-owners as a class thus appear to have received back
in higher land values, actually and potentially, about
ten dollars for every two dollars that as land-owners
they paid in taxes. If any one supposes that this
condition is peculiar to Washington let him make similar
estimates for any progressive locality, and see if the
land-owners there are not favored in like manner.
But the point is not dependent upon
increase in the capitalized value of land. If the land
yields or will yield to its owner an income in the nature
of actual or potential ground rent, then to the extent
that this actual or possible income is dependent upon
government the landlord is in effect exempt from
taxation. No matter what tax he pays on account of his
ownership of land, the public gives it back to him to
that extent.
18. Take for illustration two towns, one of
excellent government and the other of inefficient
government, but in all other respects alike. Suppose you
are hunting for a place of residence and find a suitable
site in the town of good government. For simplicity of
illustration let us suppose that the land there is not
sold outright but is let upon ground rent. You meet the
owner of the lot you have selected and ask him his terms.
He replies:
"Two hundred and fifty dollars a year."
"Two hundred and fifty dollars a year!" you
exclaim. "Why, I can get just as good a site in that
other town for a hundred dollars a year."
"Certainly you can," he will say. "But if
you build a house there and it catches fire it will burn
down; they have no fire department. If you go out after
dark you will be 'held up' and robbed; they have no
police force. If you ride out in the spring, your
carriage will stick in the mud up to the hubs, and if you
walk you may break your legs and will be lucky if you don
t break your neck; they have no street pavements and
their sidewalks are dangerously out of repair. When the
moon doesn't shine the streets are in darkness, for they
have no street lights. The water you need for your house
you must get from a well; there is no water supply there.
Now in our town it is different. We have a splendid fire
department, and the best police force in the world. Our
streets are macadamized, and lighted with electricity;
our sidewalks are always in first class repair; we have a
water system that equals that of New York; and in every
way the public benefits in this town are unsurpassed. It
is the best governed town in all this region. Isn't it
worth a hundred and fifty dollars a year more for a
building site here than over in that poorly governed
town?"
You recognize the advantages and agree to
the terms. But when your house is built and the assessor
visits you officially, what would be the conversation if
your sense of the fitness of things were not warped by
familiarity with false systems of taxation? Would it not
be something like what follows?
"How much do you regard this house as
worth? " asks the assessor.
"What is that to you?" you inquire.
"I am the town assessor and am about to
appraise your property for taxation."
"Am I to be taxed by this town? What
for?"
"What for?" echoes the assessor in
surprise. "What for? Is not your house protected from
fire by our magnificent fire department? Are not you
protected from robbery by the best police force in the
world? Do not you have the use of macadamized pavements,
and good sidewalks, and electric street lights, and a
first class water supply? Don't you suppose these things
cost something? And don't you think you ought to pay your
share?"
"Yes," you answer, with more or less
calmness; "I do have the benefit of these things, and I
do think that I ought to pay my share toward supporting
them. But I have already paid my share for this year. I
have paid it to the owner of this lot. He charges me two
hundred and fifty dollars a year -- one hundred and fifty
dollars more than I should pay or he could get but for
those very benefits. He has collected my share
of this year's expense of maintaining town improvements;
you go and collect from him. If you do not, but insist
upon collecting from me, I shall be paying twice for
these things, once to him and once to you; and he won't
be paying at all, but will be making money out of them,
although he derives the same benefits from them in all
other respects that I do."
4. CONFORMITY TO GENERAL PRINCIPLES OF
TAXATION
The single tax conforms most closely to the essential
principles of Adam Smith's four classical maxims, which are
stated best by Henry George 19 as follows:
The best tax by which public revenues can be raised is
evidently that which will closest conform to the following
conditions:
- That it bear as lightly as possible upon production
— so as least to check the increase of the general
fund from which taxes must be paid and the community
maintained. 20
- That it be easily and cheaply collected, and fall as
directly as may be upon the ultimate payers — so as
to take from the people as little as possible in addition
to what it yields the government. 21
- That it be certain — so as to give the least
opportunity for tyranny or corruption on the part of
officials, and the least temptation to law-breaking and
evasion on the part of the tax-payers. 22
- That it bear equally — so as to give no citizen
an advantage or put any at a disadvantage, as compared
with others. 23
19. "Progress and Poverty," book viii.
ch.iii.
20. This is the second part of Adam Smith's
fourth maxim. He states it as follows: "Every tax ought
to be so contrived as both to take out and to keep out of
the pockets of the people as little as possible over and
above what it brings into the public treasury of the
state. A tax may either take out or keep out of the
pockets of the people a great deal more than it brings
into the public treasury in the four following ways: . .
. Secondly, it may obstruct the industry of the people,
and discourage them from applying to certain branches of
business which might give maintenance and employment to
great multitudes. While it obliges the people to pay, it
may thus diminish or perhaps destroy some of the funds
which might enable them more easily to do so."
21. This is the first part of Adam Smith's
fourth maxim, in which he condemns a tax that takes out
of the pockets of the people more than it brings into the
public treasury.
22. This is Adam Smith's second maxim. He
states it as follows: "The tax which each individual is
bound to pay ought to be certain and not arbitrary. The
time of payment, the manner of payment, the quantity to
be paid, ought all to be clear and plain to the
contributor and to every other person. Where it is
otherwise, every person subject to the tax is put more or
less in the power of the tax gatherer."
23. This is Adam Smith's first maxim. He
states it as follows: "The subjects of every state ought
to contribute towards the support of the government as
nearly as possible in proportion to their respective
abilities, that is to say, in proportion to the revenue
which they respectively enjoy under the protection of the
state. The expense of government to the individuals of a
great nation is like the expense of management to the
joint tenants of a great estate, who are all obliged to
contribute in proportion to their respective interests in
the estate. In the observation or neglect of this maxim
consists what is called the equality or inequality of
taxation."
In changing this Mr. George says
("Progress and Poverty," book viii, ch. iii, subd.
4): "Adam Smith speaks of incomes as enjoyed 'under
the protection of the state'; and this is the ground upon
which the equal taxation of all species of property is
commonly insisted upon — that it is equally
protected by the state. The basis of this idea is
evidently that the enjoyment of property is made possible
by the state — that there is a value created and
maintained by the community; which is justly called upon
to meet community expenses. Now, of what values is this
true? Only of the value of land. This is a value that
does not arise until a community is formed, and that,
unlike other values, grows with the growth of the
community. It only exists as the community exists.
Scatter again the largest community, and land, now so
valuable, would have no value at all. With every increase
of population the value of land rises; with every
decrease it falls. This is true of nothing else save of
things which, like the ownership of land, are in their
nature monopolies."
Adam Smith's third maxim refers only to
conveniency of payment, and gives countenance to indirect
taxation, which is in conflict with the principle of his
fourth maxim. Mr. George properly excludes it.
a. Interference with Production
Indirect taxes tend to check production and cause scarcity,
by obstructing the processes of production. They fall upon
men as they work, as they do business,
as they invest capital productively. 24 But the
single tax, which must be paid and be the same in amount
regardless of whether the payer works or plays, of whether
he invests his capital productively or wastes it, of
whether he uses his land for the most productive purposes
25 or in lesser degree or not at all, removes fiscal
penalties from industry and thrift, and tends to leave
production free. It therefore conforms more closely than
indirect taxation to the first maxim quoted above.
24. "Taxation which falls upon the
processes of production interposes an artificial obstacle
to the creation of wealth. Taxation which falls upon
labor as it is exerted, wealth as it is used as capital,
land as it is cultivated, will manifestly tend to
discourage production much more powerfully than taxation
to the same amount levied upon laborers whether they work
or play, upon wealth whether used productively or
unproductively, or upon land whether cultivated or left
waste" — Progress and Poverty, book viii, ch.
iii, subd. I.
25. It is common, besides taxing
improvements, as fast as they are made, to levy higher
taxes upon land when put to its best use than when put to
partial use or to no use at all. This is upon the theory
that when his land is used the owner gets full income
from it and can afford to pay high taxes; but that he
gets little or no income when the land is out of use, and
so cannot afford to pay much. It is an absurd but
perfectly legitimate illustration of the pretentious
doctrine of taxation according to ability to pay.
Examples are numerous. Improved building
lots, and even those that are only plotted for
improvement, are usually taxed more than contiguous
unused and unplotted land which is equally in demand for
building purposes and equally valuable. So coal land,
iron land, oil land, and sugar land are as a rule taxed
less as land when opened up for appropriate use than when
lying idle or put to inferior uses, though the land value
be the same. Any serious proposal to put land to its
appropriate use is commonly regarded as a signal for
increasing the tax upon it.
b. Cheapness of Collection
Indirect taxes are passed along from first payers to
final consumers through many exchanges, accumulating
compound profits as they go, until they take enormous sums
from the people in addition to what the government
receives.26 But the single tax takes nothing from the
people in excess of the tax. It therefore conforms more
closely than indirect taxation to the second maxim quoted
above.
26. "All taxes upon things of unfixed
quantity increase prices, and in the course of exchange
are shifted from seller to buyer, increasing as they go.
If we impose a tax on money loaned, as has been often
attempted, the lender will charge the tax to the
borrower, and the borrower must pay it or not obtain the
loan. If the borrower uses it in his business, he in his
turn must get back the tax from his customers, or his
business becomes unprofitable. If we impose a tax upon
buildings, the users of buildings must finally pay it,
for the erection of buildings will cease until building
rents become high enough to pay the regular profit and
the tax besides. If we impose a tax upon manufactures or
imported goods, the manufacturer or importer will charge
it in a higher price to the jobber, the jobber to the
retailer. and the retailer to the consumer. Now, the
consumer, on whom the tax thus ultimately falls, must not
only pay the amount of the tax, but also a profit on this
amount to everyone who has thus advanced it — for
profit on the capital he has advanced in paying taxes is
as much required by each dealer as profit on the capital
he has advanced in paying for goods." —
Progress and Poverty, book viii, ch. iii, subd.
2.
c. Certainty
No other tax, direct or indirect, conforms so closely to
the third maxim. "Land lies out of doors." It cannot be
hidden; it cannot be "accidentally" overlooked. Nor can its
value be seriously misstated. Neither under-appraisement
nor over-appraisement to any important degree is possible
without the connivance of the whole community. 27 The land
values of a neighborhood are matters of common knowledge.
Any intelligent resident can justly appraise them, and
every other intelligent resident can fairly test the
appraisement. Therefore, the tyranny, corruption, fraud,
favoritism, and evasions that are so common in connection
with the taxation of imports, manufactures, incomes,
personal property, and buildings — the values of
which, even when the object itself cannot be hidden, are so
distinctly matters of minute special knowledge that only
experts can fairly appraise them — would be out of
the question if the single tax were substituted for
existing fiscal methods. 28
27. The under-appraisements so common at
present, and alluded to in note 25, are possible because
the community, ignorant of the just principles of
taxation, does connive at them. Under-appraisements are
not secret crimes on the part of assessors; they are
distinctly recognized, but thoughtlessly disregarded when
not actually insisted upon, by the people themselves. And
this is due to the dishonest ideas of taxation that are
taught. Let the vicious doctrine that people ought to pay
taxes according to their ability give way to the honest
principle that they should pay in proportion to the
benefits they receive, which benefits, as we have already
seen, are measured by the land values they own, and
underappraisement of land would cease. No assessor can
befool the community in respect of the value of the land
within his jurisdiction.
And, with the cessation of general
under-appraisement, favoritism in individual
appraisements also would cease. General
under-appraisement fosters unfair individual
appraisements. If land were generally appraised at its
full value, a particular unfair appraisement would stand
out in such relief that the crime of the assessor would
be exposed. But now if a man's land is appraised at a
higher valuation than his neighbor's equally valuable
land, and he complains of the unfairness, he is promptly
and effectually silenced with a warning that his land is
worth much more than it is appraised at, anyhow, and if
he makes a fuss his appraisement will be increased. To
complain further of the deficient taxation of his
neighbor is to invite the imposition of a higher tax upon
himself.
28. If you wish to test the merits in point
of certainty of the single tax as compared with other
taxes, go to a real estate agent in your community, and,
showing him a building lot upon the map, ask him its
value. If he inquires about the improvements, instruct
him to ignore them. He will be able at once to tell you
what the lot is worth. And if you go to twenty other
agents their estimates will not materially vary from his.
Yet none of the agents will have left his office. Each
will have inferred the value from the size and location
of the lot.
But suppose when you show the map to the
first agent you ask him the value of the land and its
improvements. He will tell you that he cannot give an
estimate until he examines the improvements. And if it is
the highly improved property of a rich man he will engage
building experts to assist him. Should you ask him to
include the value of the contents of the buildings, he
would need a corps of selected experts, including artists
and liverymen, dealers in furniture and bric-a-brac,
librarians and jewelers. Should you propose that he also
include the value of the occupant's income, the agent
would throw up his hands in despair.
If without the aid of an army of experts
the agent should make an estimate of these miscellaneous
values, and twenty others should do the same, their
several estimates would be as wide apart as ignorant
guesses usually are. And the richer the owner of the
property the lower as a proportion would the guesses
probably be.
Now turn the real estate agent into an
assessor, and is it not plain that he would appraise the
land values with much greater certainty and cheapness
than he could appraise the values of all kinds of
property? With a plot map before him he might fairly make
every appraisement without leaving his desk at the town
hall.
And there would be no material difference
if the property in question were a farm instead of a
building lot. A competent farmer or business man in a
farming community can, without leaving his own door-yard,
appraise the value of the land of any farm there; whereas
it would be impossible for him to value the improvements,
stock, produce, etc., without at least inspecting
them.
d. Equality
In respect of the fourth maxim the single tax bears more
equally— that is to say, more justly — than any
other tax. It is the only tax that falls upon the taxpayer
in proportion to the pecuniary benefits he receives from
the public; 29 and its tendency, accelerating with the
increase of the tax, is to leave every one the full fruit
of his own productive enterprise and effort. 30
29 The benefits of government are not the
only public benefits whose value attaches exclusively to
land. Communal development from whatever cause produces
the same effect. But as it is under the protection of
government that land-owners are able to maintain
ownership of land and through that to enjoy the pecuniary
benefits of advancing social conditions, government
confers upon them as a class not only the pecuniary
benefits of good government but also the pecuniary
benefits of progress in general.
30. "Here are two men of equal incomes
— that of the one derived from the exertion of his
labor, that of the other from the rent of land. Is it
just that they should equally contribute to the expenses
of the state? Evidently not. The income of the one
represents wealth he creates and adds to the general
wealth of the state; the income of the other represents
merely wealth that he takes from the general stock,
returning nothing." — Progress and Poverty,
book viii, ch. iii, subd. 4.
III. THE SINGLE TAX AS A SOCIAL
REFORM.
But the single tax is more than a revenue system. Great
as are its merits in this respect, they are but incidental
to its character as a social reform.31 And that some social
reform, which shall be simple in method but fundamental in
character, is most urgently needed we have only to look
about us to see.
31. There are two classes of single tax
advocates. Those who advocate it as a reform in taxation
alone, regardless of its effects upon social adjustments,
are called "single tax men limited"; those who advocate
it both as a reform in taxation and as the mode of
securing equal rights to land, are called "single tax men
unlimited."
Poverty is widespread and pitiable. This we know. Its
general manifestations are so common that even good men
look upon it as a providential provision for enabling the
rich to drive camels through needles' eyes by exercising
the modern virtue of organized giving.32 Its occasional
manifestations in recurring periods of "hard times"33 are
like epidemics of a virulent disease, which excite even the
most contented to ask if they may not be the next victims.
Its spasms of violence threaten society with anarchy on the
one hand, and, through panic-stricken efforts at restraint,
with loss of liberty on the other. And it persists and
deepens despite the continuous increase of wealth producing
power.34
32. Not all charity is contemptible. Those
charitable people, who, knowing that individuals suffer,
hasten to their relief, deserve the respect and affection
they receive. That kind of charity is neighborliness; it
is love. And perhaps in modern circumstances organization
is necessary to make it effective. But organized charity
as a cherished social institution is a different thing.
It is not love, nor is it inspired by love; it is simply
sanctified selfishness, at the bottom of which will be
found the blasphemous notion that in the economy of God
the poor are to be forever with us that the rich may gain
heaven by alms-giving.
Suppose a hole in the sidewalk into which
passers-by continually fall, breaking their arms, their
legs, and sometimes their necks. We should respect
charitable people who, without thought of themselves,
went to the relief of the sufferers, binding the broken
limbs of the living, and decently burying the dead. But
what should we say of those who, when some one proposed
to fill up the hole to prevent further suffering, should
say, "Oh, you mustn't fill up that hole! Whatever in the
world should we charitable people do to be saved if we
had no broken legs and arms to bind, and no broken-necked
people to bury?"
Of some kinds of charity it has been well
said that they are "that form of self-righteousness which
makes us give to others the things that already belong to
them." They suggest the old nursery rhyme:
"There was once a considerate
crocodile,
Which lay on a bank of the river Nile.
And he swallowed a fish, with a face of woe,
While his tears flowed fast to the stream below.
'I am mourning,' said he, 'the untimely fate
Of the dear little fish which I just now ate.'"
Read Chapter viii of "Social Problems," by
Henry George, entitled, "That We All Might Be Rich."
33. Differences between "hard times" and
"good times" are but differences in degrees of poverty
and in the people who suffer from it. Times are always
hard with the multitude. But the voice of the multitude
is too weak to be heard at ordinary times through the
ordinary trumpets of public opinion. They are not
regarded nor do they regard themselves as people of any
importance in the industrial world, so long as the
general wheels of business revolve. It is only when
poverty has eaten its way up through the various strata
of struggling and pinching and squeezing and squirming
humanity, and with its cancerous tentacles touched the
superincumbent layers of manufacturing nabobs, merchant
princes, railroad kinds, great bankers and great
landowners that we hear any general complain of "hard
times."
34. "Could a man of the last century
— a Franklin or a Priestley — have seen, in a
vision of the future, the steamship taking the place of
the sailing vessel, the railroad train of the wagon, the
reaping machine of the scythe, the threshing machine of
the flail; could he have heard the throb of the engines
that in obedience to human will, and for the satisfaction
of human desire, exert a power greater than that of all
the men and all the beasts of burden of the earth
combined; could he have seen the forest tree transformed
into finished lumber — into doors, sashes, blinds,
boxes or barrels, with hardly the touch of a human hand;
the great workshops where boots and shoes are turned out
by the case with less labor than the old-fashioned
cobbler could have put on a sole; the factories where,
under the eye of a girl, cotton becomes cloth faster than
hundreds of stalwart weavers could have turned it out
with their hand-looms; could he have seen steam hammers
shaping mammoth shafts and mighty anchors, and delicate
machinery making tiny watches; the diamond drill cutting
through the heart of the rocks, and coal oil sparing the
whale; could he have realized the enormous saving of
labor resulting from improved facilities of exchange and
communication — sheep killed in Australia eaten
fresh in England and the order given by the London banker
in the afternoon executed in San Francisco in the morning
of the same day; could he have conceived of the hundred
thousand improvements which these only suggest, what
would he have inferred as to the social condition of
mankind?
"It would not have seemed like an
inference; further than the vision went, it would have
seemed as though he saw; and his heart would have leaped
and his nerves would have thrilled, as one who from a
height beholds just ahead of the thirst-stricken caravan
the living gleam of rustling woods and the glint of
laughing waters. Plainly, in the sight of the
imagination, he would have beheld these new forces
elevating society from its very foundations, lifting the
very poorest above the possibility of want, exempting the
very lowest from anxiety for the material needs of life
... And out of these bounteous material conditions he
would have seen arising, as necessary sequences, moral
conditions realizing the golden age of which mankind have
always dreamed. ... More or less vague or clear, these
have been the hopes, these the dreams born of the
improvements which give this wonderful century its
preeminence. ... It is true that disappointment has
followed disappointment, and that discovery upon
discovery, and invention after invention, have neither
lessened the toil of those who most need respite, nor
brought plenty to the poor. But there have been so many
things to which it seemed this failure could be laid,
that up to our time the new faith has hardly weakened.
... Now, however, we are coming into collision with facts
which there can be no mistaking. ... And, unpleasant as
it may be to admit it, it is at last becoming evident
that the enormous increase in productive power which has
marked the present century and is still going on with
accelerating ratio, has no tendency to extirpate poverty
or to lighten the burdens of those compelled to toil. It
simply widens the gulf between Dives
and Lazarus, and makes the struggle for existence
more intense. The march of invention has clothed mankind
with powers of which a century ago the boldest
imagination could not have dreamed. But in factories
where labor-saving machinery has reached its most
wonderful development, little children are at work;
wherever the new forces are anything like fully utilized,
large classes are maintained by charity or live on the
verge of recourse to it; amid the greatest accumulations
of wealth, men die of starvation, and puny infant suckle
dry breasts; while everywhere the greed of gain, the
worship of wealth, shows the force of the fear of want.
— Progress and Poverty, Introduction.
That much of our poverty is involuntary may be proved,
if proof be necessary, by the magnitude of charitable work
that aims to help only the "deserving poor"; and as to
undeserving cases — the cases of voluntary poverty
— who can say but that they, if not due to birth and
training in the environs of degraded poverty, 35 are the
despairing culminations of long-continued struggles for
respectable independence? 36 How can we know that they are
not essentially like the rest — involuntary and
deserving? It is a profound distinction that a clever
writer of fiction 37 makes when he speaks of "the hopeful
and the hopeless poor." There is, indeed, little difference
between voluntary and involuntary poverty, between the
"deserving" and the "undeserving" poor, except that the
"deserving" still have hope, while from the "undeserving"
all hope, if they ever knew any, has gone.
35. The leader of one of the labor strikes
of the early eighties, a hard-working, respectable, and
self-respecting man, told me that the deprivations which
he himself suffered as a workingman were as nothing
compared with the fear for the future of his children
that he felt whenever he thought of the repulsive
surroundings, physical and moral, in which, owing to his
poverty, he was compelled to bring them up.
Professor Francis Wayland, Dean of the Yale
law school, wrote in the Charities Review for
March, 1893: "Under our eyes and within our reach,
children are being reared from infancy amid surroundings
containing every conceivable element of degradation,
depravity and vice. Why, then, should we be surprised
that we are surrounded by a horde of juvenile
delinquents, that the police reports in our cities teem
with the exploits of precocious little villains, that
reform schools are crowded with hopelessly abandoned
young offenders? How could it be otherwise? What else
could be expected from such antecedents, from such
ever-present examples of flagrant vice? Short of a
miracle, how could any child escape the moral contagion
of such an environment? How could he retain a single
vestige of virtue, a single honest impulse, a single
shred of respect for the rights of others, after passing
through such an ordeal of iniquity? What is there left on
which to build up a better character?
In the Arena of July, 1893, Helen
Campbell says, "It would seem at times as if the workshop
meant only a form of preparation for the hospital, the
workhouse and the prison, since the workers therein
become inoculated with trade diseases, mutilated by trade
appliances, and corrupted by trade associates till no
healthy fiber, mental, moral or physical, remains."
Such testimony is abundant. But no further
citation is necessary to arouse the conscience of the
merciful and the just, and any amount of proof would not
affect those self-satisfied mortals whom Kipling
describes when he says that "there are men who, when
their own front doors are closed, will swear that the
whole world's warm."
36. Some years ago a gentleman, now well
and favorably known in New York public life, told me of a
ragged tramp whom he had brought, more to gratify a whim
perhaps than in any spirit of philanthropy, from a
neighboring camp of tramps to his house for breakfast.
After breakfast the host asked his guest, in the course
of conversation, why he lived the life of a tramp. This
in substance was the tramp's reply:
"I am a mechanic and used to be a good one,
though not so exceptionally good as to be safe from the
competition of the great class of average workers. I had
a family — a wife and two children. In the hard
times of the seventies I lost my job. For a while we
lived upon our little savings; but sickness came and our
savings were used up. My wife and children died.
Everything was gone but self-respect. Then I traveled,
looking for work which could not be had at home. I
traveled afoot; I could afford no other way. For days I
hunted for work, begging food and sleeping in barns or
under trees; but no work could I get. Once or twice I was
arrested as a vagrant. Then I fell in with a party of
tramps and with them drifted into the city. Winter came
on. I still had a desire to regain my old place as a
self-respecting man, but work was scarce and nothing that
I could do could I find to do, except some little job now
and then which was given to me as pennies are given to
beggars. I slept mostly in station houses. Part of the
time I was undergoing sentence for vagrancy. In the
spring I tramped again. But now I did not hunt for work.
My self-respect was gone so completely that I had no
ambition to regain it. I was a loafer and a jail-bird. I
had no family to support, and I had found that, barring
the question of self-respect, I was about as well off as
were average workmen. After years of tramping this
opinion is unchanged. I am always sure of enough to eat
and a place to sleep in — not very good often, but
good enough. I should not be sure of that if I were a
workingman. I might lose my job and go hungry rather than
beg. I might be unable to pay my rent and so be turned
upon the street. I might marry again and have a family
which would be condemned to the hard life of the average
workingman's family. And as for society, why, I have
society. Tramps are good fellows — sociable
fellows, bright fellows many of them. Life as a tramp is
not half bad when you compare it with the workingman's
life, leaving out the question of self-respect, of
course. You must leave that out. No man can be a tramp
for good until he loses that. But a period of hard times
makes many a chap lose it. And as I have lost it I would
rather be a tramp than a workingman. I have tried both.
By the way, Mr. ——, this is a very good cigar
— this brand of yours. I seldom smoke much better
cigars."
The facts in detail of this man's story may
have been false; they probably were. But so were the
facts in detail of Bunyan's "Pilgrim's Progress." There
is, however, a distinction between fact and
truth, and no matter how false the man's facts
may have been, his story, like Bunyan's, was essentially
true. Much of the poverty that upon the surface seems to
be voluntary and undeserving comes from a growing feeling
among those who work hardest that, as Cowper describes
it, they are
"Letting down buckets into empty
wells,
And growing old with drawing nothing up."
At Victoria, B.C., in the spring of 1894, I
witnessed a canoe race in which there were two
contestants and but one prize. Long before the winner had
reached the goal his adversary, who found himself far
behind, turned his canoe toward the shore and dropped out
of the race. Was it because he was too lazy to paddle?
Not at all. It was because he realized the hopelessness
of the effort.
37. H. C. Bunner, editor of
Puck.
But it is not alone to objects of charity that the
question of poverty calls our attention. There is a keener
poverty, which pinches and goes hungry, but is beyond the
reach of charity because it never complains. And back of
all and over all is fear of poverty, which chills the best
instincts of men of every social grade, from recipients of
out-door relief who dread the poorhouse, to millionaires
who dread the possibility of poverty for their children if
not for themselves.38
38. A well known millionaire is quoted as
saying: "I would rather leave my children penniless in a
world in which they could at all times obtain employment
for wages equal to the value of their work as measured by
the work of others, than to leave them millions of
dollars in a world like this, where if thy lose their
inheritance, they may have no chance of earning am decent
living."
It is poverty and fear of poverty that prompt men of
honest instincts to steal, to bribe, to take bribes, to
oppress, either under color of law or against law, and
— what is worst than all, because it is not merely a
depraved act, but a course of conduct that implies a state
of depravity — to enlist their talents in crusades
against their convictions. 39 Our civilization cannot long
resist such enemies as poverty and fear of poverty breed;
to intelligent observers it already seems to yield. 40
39. "From whence springs this lust for
gain, to gratify which men tread everything pure and
noble under their feet; to which they sacrifice all the
higher possibilities of life; which converts civility
into a hollow pretense, patriotism into a sham, and
religion into hypocrisy; which makes so much of civilized
existence an Ishmaelitish warfare, of which the weapons
are cunning and fraud? Does it not spring from the
existence of want? Carlyle somewhere says that poverty is
the hell of which the modern Englishman is most afraid.
And he is right. Poverty is the openmouthed, relentless
hell which yawns beneath civilized society. And it is
hell enough. The Vedas declare no truer thing than when
the wise crow Bushanda tells the eagle-bearer of Vishnu
that the keenest pain is in poverty. For poverty is not
merely deprivation; it means shame, degradation; the
searing of the most sensitive parts of our moral and
mental nature as with hot irons; the denial of the
strongest impulses and the sweetest affections; the
wrenching of the most vital nerves. You love your wife,
you love your children; but would it not be easier to see
them die than to see them reduced to the pinch of want in
which large classes in every highly civilized community
live? ... From this hell of poverty, it is but natural
that men should make every effort to escape. With the
impulse to self-preservation and self-gratification
combine nobler feelings, and love as well as fear urges
in the struggle. Many a man does a mean thing, a
dishonest thing, a greedy and grasping and unjust thing,
in the effort to place above want, or the fear of want,
mother or wife or children." — Progress and
Poverty, book ix, ch iv.
40. "There is just now a disposition to
scoff at any implication that we are not in all respects
progressing ... Yet it is evident that there have been
times of decline, just as there have been times of
advance; and it is further evident that these epochs of
decline could not at first have been generally
recognized.
"He would have been a rash man who, when
Augustus was changing the Rome of brick to the Rome of
marble, when wealth was augmenting and magnificence
increasing, when victorious legions were extending the
frontier, when manners were becoming more refined,
language more polished, and literature rising to higher
splendors — he would have been a rash man who then
would have said that Rome was entering her decline. Yet
such was the case.
"And whoever will look may see that though
our civilization is apparently advancing with greater
rapidity than ever, the same cause which turned Roman
progress into retrogression is operating now.
"What has destroyed every previous
civilization has been the tendency to the unequal
distribution of wealth and power. This same tendency,
operating with increasing force, is observable in our
civilization today, showing itself in every progressive
community, and with greater intensity the more
progressive the community. ... The conditions of social
progress, as we have traced the law, are association and
equality. The general tendency of modern development,
since the time when we can first discern the gleams of
civilization in the darkness which followed the fall of
the Western Empire, has been toward political and legal
equality ... This tendency has reached its full
expression in the American Republic, where political and
legal rights are absolutely equal ... it is the
prevailing tendency, and how soon Europe will be
completely republican is only a matter of time, or rather
of accident. The United States are therefore in this
respect, the most advanced of all the great nations, in a
direction in which all are advancing, and in the United
States we see just how much this tendency to personal and
political freedom can of itself accomplish. ... It is now
... evident that political equality, coexisting with an
increasing tendency to the unequal distribution of
wealth, must ultimately beget either the despotism of
organized tyranny or the worse despotism of anarchy.
"To turn a republican government into a
despotism the basest and most brutal, it is not necessary
formally to change its constitution or abandon popular
elections. It was centuries after Cæsar before the
absolute master of the Roman world pretended to rule
other than by authority of a Senate that trembled before
him.
"But forms are nothing when substance has
gone, and the forms of popular government are those from
which the substance of freedom may most easily go.
Extremes meet, and a government of universal suffrage and
theoretical equality may, under conditions which impel
the change, most readily become a despotism. For there
despotism advances in the name and with the might of the
people. ... And when the disparity of condition
increases, so does universal suffrage make it easy to
seize the source of power, for the greater is the
proportion of power in the hands of those who feel no
direct interest in the conduct of government; who,
tortured by want and embruted by poverty, are ready to
sell their votes to the highest bidder or follow the lead
of the most blatant demagogue; or who, made bitter by
hardships, may even look upon profligate and tyrannous
government with the satisfaction we may imagine the
proletarians and slaves of Rome to have felt, as they saw
a Caligula or Nero raging among the rich patricians. ...
Now this transformation of popular government into
despotism of the vilest and most degrading kind, which
must inevitably result from the unequal distribution of
wealth, is not a thing of the far future. It has already
begun in the United States, and is rapidly going on under
our eyes. ... The type of modern growth is the great
city. Here are to be found the greatest wealth and the
deepest poverty. And it is here that popular government
has most clearly broken down. ... In theory we are
intense democrats. ... But is there not growing up among
us a class who have all the power without any of the
virtues of aristocracy? ... Industry everywhere tends to
assume a form in which one is master and many serve. And
when one is master and the others serve, the one will
control the others, even in such matters as votes. ...
There is no mistaking it — the very foundations of
society are being sapped before our eyes ... It is shown
in greatest force where the inequalities in the
distribution of wealth are greatest, and it shows itself
as they increase. ... Though we may not speak it openly,
the general faith in republican institutions is, where
they have reached their fullest development, narrowing
and weakening. It is no longer that confident belief in
republicanism as the source of national blessings that it
once was. Thoughtful men are beginning to see its
dangers, without seeing how to escape them; are beginning
to accept the view of Macaulay and distrust that of
Jefferson. And the people at large are becoming used to
the growing corruption. The most ominous political sign
in the United States today is the growth of a sentiment
which either doubts the existence of an honest man in
public office or looks on him as a fool for not seizing
his opportunities. That is to say, the people themselves
are becoming corrupted. Thus in the United States to-day
is republican government running the course it must
inevitably follow under conditions which cause the
unequal distribution of wealth." — Progress and
Poverty, book x, ch. iv.
But how is the development of these social enemies to be
arrested? Only by tracing poverty to its cause, and, having
found the cause, deliberately removing it. Poverty cannot
be traced to its cause, however, without serious thought;
not mere reading and school study and other tutoring, but
thought. 41 To jump at a conclusion is very likely
to jump over the cause, at which no class is more apt than
the tutored class.42 We must proceed step by step from
familiar and indisputable premises.
41. "The power to reason correctly on
general subjects is not to be learned in schools, nor
does it come with special knowledge. It results from care
in separating, from caution in combining, from the habit
of asking ourselves the meaning of the words we use, and
making sure of one step before building another upon it
— and above all, from loyalty to truth." —
Henry George's Perplexed Philosopher, p. 9
42. "Harold Frederic, the London
correspondent of the New York Times, reports Mr.
Gladstone as having said, in substance, in one of his
campaign speeches, that the older he grew the more he
began to conclude that the highly educated classes were
in public affairs rather more conspicuously foolish than
anybody else. Mr. Frederic thinks that the Tories have
since done much to 'breed a suspicion that therein
Gladstone touched the outskirts of a great and solemn
truth.' But it needed not the action of the Tories to
breed that suspicion. In this country as well as in
England it is patent to any close observer that the
highly educated classes, or to speak with more exactness,
the highly tutored classes, when compared with
the common people, are in public affairs but little
better than fools. The explanation is simple. The common
people are philosophers unencumbered with useless
knowledge, who look upon public affairs broadly, and
moralists who pry beneath the surface of custom and
precedent into the heart of public questions. The minds
of the tutored classes, on the contrary, are dwarfed by
close attention to particulars to the exclusion of
generals, and distorted by such false morality as is
involved in tutorial notions regarding vested rights.
— The Standard, July 27, 1892.
The tendency of tutoring to elevate mere
authority above observation and thought is well
illustrated by the story of two classes in a famous
school. The primary class, being asked if fishes have
eyelids, went to the aquarium and observed; the senior
class being asked the same question, went to the library
and consulted authorities.
"One may stand on a box and look over the
heads of his fellows, but he no better sees the stars.
The telescope and the microscope reveal depths which to
the unassisted vision are closed. Yet not merely do they
bring us no nearer to the cause of suns and animalcula,
but in looking through them the observer must shut his
eyes to what lies about him ... A man of special learning
may be a fool as to common relations." —
Perplexed Philosopher, Introduction.
1. THE SOURCE OF WEALTH
The first demand upon us is to make sure that we know
the source of the things that satisfy want.43 But it is
quite unnecessary to tediously specify these and trace them
to their origin in detail. In searching for the source of
one we shall discover the source of all.
43. For it is ability or inability to
satisfy his wants that determines whether or not a man is
poor. He who has the power to procure what he wants, as
he wants it, and in satisfactory quality and quantity, is
not poor. No matter how he gets the power, provided he
keeps out of the penitentiary, he is accounted rich.
As a common object of this kind, the production of which
is a familiar process, bread is probably the best example
for our purpose. Let us, then, carefully trace bread to its
source. To make the results of our work clear to the eye as
well as to the ear we will construct a chart as we proceed.
The chart should begin with a classification of Bread with
reference to Man, for it is as an object for satisfying the
wants of man that we consider bread at all. Is Bread a part
of the personality of Man? or is it an object external to
him? That is our first question. The answer is so obvious
that a child could make no mistake. Bread is external to
Man. It should, therefore, be classified with what for
brevity we will call "External Objects." It is also a
product having certain constituents.
Let us so arrange the chart as to indicate these facts
and also to provide a place for particularizing the
constituents of bread as we ascertain them. Thus:
Chart 1 (page 28)
Now let the necessary constituents of bread be inserted.
Any housewife, any kitchen girl, knows what they are as
well as does the most expert baker or learned chemist. They
are named in the place reserved for them in the chart:
Chart 2, page 29
In respect of Man the constituents of Bread all fall
into two general classes: Man, and objects that are
external to him — or, briefly, External Objects.
Thus:
Chart 3, page 29
While all these External Objects are alike in the one
particular that they are external to Man, some of them may
differ from others in respects which, for clear thinking,
must be distinguished. Compare the first two External
Objects — the lot of land and the oven — and a
radical difference at once appears. The lot of land is a
natural object. The oven is an artificial object. The lot
exists independently of man's art; the oven can have no
existence whatever as an oven but for man's art. 44 And
when the remaining External Objects are considered the same
difference appears. Objects are considered the same
difference appears. All of them, Bread included, differ
from the lot of land precisely as the oven does; they are
artificial.45 Let us note this difference upon our
chart:
Chart 4, page 30
44. This difference is frequently ignored,
even by political economists; but it is plain to any
intelligent mind that no reasoning can be trusted which
does not distinguish a difference so radical.
45. As to the flour and the yeast, there is
no doubt of this. And though not so obvious, it is
equally true of the fire, which but for the art of man
would not exist in the oven; of the water, which but for
that would not be at hand; and of the salt, which without
man's art would be neither in proper form nor place. It
follows that, either as to form or place or both, all the
external objects, except the lot of land, are artificial.
The bread itself is of course artificial.
It is no longer necessary to name the specific
constituents of Bread, and we may simplify the chart by
erasing them, together with the word "bread" itself,
retaining only the class names. It will be more
appropriate, too, if we substitute the term "factors" for
the term "classification." Thus:
Chart 5, page 31
Grave danger of confusion here arises. Artificial
Objects, it will be seen, are classified both as the
"product" and as a "factor." Yet it cannot be that any
factor of a product is exactly the same as the product;
there is surely some difference which we should try to
discover.
Turn to the chart on page 30, which specifies the
artificial constituents of Bread, namely: oven, fire,
flour, yeast, salt, water. How do these artificial factors
differ from the artificial product, bread? Simply in this,
that the artificial factors are unfinished bread,
while the product is finished bread. 46 The
difference, then, between artificial objects as a factor,
and artificial objects as a final product, is that the
former are unfinished and the latter are finished. Let us
note the distinction:
Chart 6, page
32
46. It is because man desires bread that he
constructs ovens, builds fires in them, grinds flour,
digs or evaporates salt, prepares yeast, or carries water
to the doughtrough. And going farther back, it is because
he desires bread that he raises grain, erects mills, and
produces machinery for bread-making. This is plain enough
in a community of one like that of Robinson Crusoe. But
it is just as true in a community of millions. In the
community of one the solitary individual performs all the
steps necessary to produce bread because he wants bread.
In the great society individuals divide their work, some
doing one part and others other parts; but the motive,
still the same, is the desire of the community for bread.
All the processes of industry to the extent that they are
directed to the production of bread, whether they be in
the departments of mining, of lumbering, of railroading,
of navigation, of engineering, of farming, of
storekeeping, of baking, or what not, are steps or stages
in bread-making; and every artificial object produced for
the purpose of facilitating bread-making is to that
extent unfinished bread. But bread itself, from the time
it comes into the possession of the consumer (for it is
not complete until the final deliverer has accomplished
his work regarding it), is a finished object. The
essential difference, then, between the artificial
objects that are classified as product,' and those that
are classified as "factors" is that the former are
finished and the latter are unfinished.
Professor Marshall (Marshall’s
Prin., Book ii, ch iii) divides artificial objects
into "goods of the first order, which satisfy wants
directly, such as food, clothing, etc.; goods of the
second order, such as flour mills, which satisfy wants,
not directly but indirectly, by contributing toward the
production of goods of the first order; and "goods of the
third order," under which he arranges all things that are
used for making goods of the second order, such as the
machinery for making milling machinery." He says we might
carry the analysis further if necessary, And so we might.
We might drag it out into an interminable catalogue; but
every item would be an unfinished artificial object, and
for all purposes of economic reasoning nothing else. His
own classification into “consumers’
goods” (finished artificial objects), and
“producers’ goods” (unfinished
artificial objects) is complete.
The language of the chart may now be supplemented with
the technical terms that political economists adopt, which,
when comprehended and used with discrimination, distinguish
the differences we have discovered with equal precision and
greater brevity than the more cumbrous terms upon which we
have so far relied. 47 Thus:
Chart 7, page 33
47 It makes no difference what terms are
adopted, for they serve only as symbols; but it is of
vital importance that the same terms shall never
symbolize things that essentially differ. As the
technical terms that usage forces upon us in connection
with our subject are also loose colloquial words, they
are especially liable to abuse in this respect. The term
"wealth" is a bewildering example. It has been used to
symbolize as of one class such diverse things as building
lots, houses, farm sites, farm improvements, deeds,
mortgages, promissory notes, warehouse receipts and the
goods they call for, book accounts, and slaves, thus
confusing three or four different kinds of things,
instead of distinguishing one kind from all others. Made
to include building lots and farm sites, the term is a
symbol for natural objects; made to include houses, farm
improvements, and goods, it is a symbol for artificial
objects; by including slaves it symbolizes man; and by
including deeds, promissory notes, warehouse receipts,
and book accounts, it symbolizes nothing but evidences of
legal title as between individual men. When the same term
is used to include things so essentially different as
natural objects external to man, artificial objects
external to man, man himself, and indicia of
title, it is hopeless to attempt to reason about the
mutual relations of those things.
At this point we find all essential differences
distinguished. Every factor of industry and every material
object of desire that can be imagined falls into one or
another of the four classes of the chart. 48 And from mere
inspection of the chart we may see, what was promised when
we began its construction, that in searching for the source
of one of the objects that satisfy human wants we have
discovered the source of all. For it is self-evident that
the material wants of men are satisfied in no other way
than by the consumption of finished artificial objects,
technically called Wealth; and the chart shows that such
objects have their source in a combination of the three
"factors," namely: (1) the activities of man, technically
termed "Labor;" (2) natural objects external to man,
technically termed Land; and (3) unfinished artificial
objects, technically termed Capital.
48. For example: Flour, which is unfinished
bread, and therefore unfinished wealth — Capital,
appears upon analysis to be a compound of grain, a mill
site, and a miller. The mill site and the miller are
respectively land and labor; but the grain and the mill
are unfinished wealth — Capital, and may be further
analyzed. Passing the mill for the moment to analyze the
grain, we find it composed of a farmer, a farm site, and
farming improvements and implements. The farm site, like
the mill site, is land; and the farmer, like the miller,
is labor; but the improvements and implements, like the
mill and the grain, are unfinished wealth —
Capital, and may be still further analyzed. And so
on.
If analyzed to the last, every constituent
of bread, and every constituent of that constituent,
would resolve into labor and land. To follow them step by
step would be tedious work and require much special
knowledge. It would involve consideration of factories
and factory sites, stores and store sites, railroads and
railroad sites, mining and mines, lumbering and forests,
rivers, docks, oceans, and ships. But analysis in full
detail is not necessary. The conclusion is self-evident
the moment it is understood.
But while these three factors combined produce all the
material objects that tend to satisfy human wants, they do
not constitute the ultimate source of those
objects. Our analysis is not yet ended; our chart is still
incomplete.
Reflection assures us that all artificial objects,
finished and unfinished, resolve upon final analysis into
the two factors, the activities of man and natural external
objects; or, in technical language, all Wealth, finished
and unfinished, resolves upon final analysis into Labor and
Land. Therefore, Capital is in final analysis eliminated as
a factor of production. It expresses nothing which the two
remaining factors do not imply; for it is by the
conjunction of those two factors that Capital itself is
produced. 49 Unfinished artificial objects and their
technical term, Capital, should, therefore, be erased from
the chart. Following is the result:
Chart 8, page 35
49. The primary error in all forms of
socialism consists in ignoring the fact that Capital is
but a product of labor and land; or what in effect is the
same thing, in disregarding the necessary inference that
land is the only implement of labor. Intelligent
socialists insist that they do not ignore it; but that,
while acknowledging land to be the primary implement of
labor, they see in this only an abstract formula, having
at the present stage of civilization no practical
importance. Society, they urge, is impossible without
Capital; and he who would live in society must have
Capital, or be the slave of those who do have it.
Therefore, they, argue, Capital is in the social state as
indispensable as land. Their reasoning hinges upon the
mistaken assumption that Capital is an accumulation of
the past instead of being a product of the present. As
one socialistic author puts it, "Though labor may
originally have preceded Capital, yet it is now as absurd
to place one before the other as it is to attempt to say
whether the hen originates the egg or the egg the hen."
The explanation of division of labor and trade. the
effect of which is overlooked by socialistic
philosophies, affords a better opportunity than the
present for considering this elementary error of
socialism, and a brief discussion of the subject will be
given in that connection. See post, note 81.
Thus all artificial objects external to man —
Wealth, are found to have their ultimate source in the
conjunction of man's activities — Labor, with natural
objects external to man — Land.
Finally, by dropping the cumbrous language altogether, and
using only the technical terms, we complete our chart. 50
Thus:
Chart 9, page 36
The chart may be read as follows:
Wealth is produced solely by the application of
Labor to Land.51
50. It may at first seem like a great waste
of time and space to have gone through this long analysis
for no other purpose at last than to demonstrate the
self-evident fact that land and labor are the sole
original factors in the production of Wealth. But it will
have been no waste if it enables the reader to firmly
grasp the fact. Nothing is more obvious, to be sure.
Nothing is more readily assented to. Yet by layman and
college professor and economic author alike, this simple
truth is cast adrift at the very threshold of argument or
investigation, with results akin to what might be
expected in physics if after recognizing the law of
gravitation its effects should be completely ignored.
51. There is ample authority among economic
writers for this conclusion.
Professor Ely enumerates Nature, Labor, and
Capital as the factors of production, but he describes
Capital as a combination of Nature and Labor —
Ely's Introduction, part ii, ch. iii.
Say describes industry as " nothing more or
less than human employment of natural agents." —
Say's Trea., book i, ch. ii.
And though John Stuart Mill and numerous
others speak of Land, Labor, and Capital as the three
factors of production, as does Professor Jevons, most of
them, like Jevons, recognize the fact, though in their
reasoning they often fail to profit by it, that Capital
is not a primary but a secondary requisite. See
Jevons's Pol. Ec., secs. 16, 19.
Henry George says: "Land, labor, and
capital are the factors of production. The term land
includes all natural opportunities or forces; the term
labor, all human exertion; and the term capital, all
wealth used to produce more wealth. . . Capital is not a
necessary factor in production. Labor exerted upon land
can produce wealth without the aid of capital, and in the
necessary genesis of things must so produce wealth before
capital can exist." — Progress and Poverty,
book iii, ch. i.
Also : "The complexities of production in
the civilized state, in which so great a part is borne by
exchange, and so much labor is bestowed upon materials
after they have been separated from the land, though they
may to the unthinking disguise, do not alter the fact
that all production is still the union of the two
factors, land and labor."— Id., ch.
viii.
By intelligent observers no authority is
needed. In all the phenomena of human life, whether
primitive or civilized, the lesson of the chart stands
out in bold relief. Nothing can be produced without Labor
and Land, and nothing can be named which under any
circumstances enters into productive processes that is
not resolvable into either the one or the other. To
satisfy all human wants mankind requires nothing but
human labor and natural material, and each of them is
indispensable.
This is the final analysis. In the union of Labor, which
includes all human effort,52 with Land, which includes the
whole material universe outside of man,53 we discover the
ultimate source of Wealth, which includes all the material
things that satisfy want.54 And that is the first great
truth upon which the single tax philosophy is built.
52. The term labor includes all human
exertion in the production of wealth." —
Progress and Poverty, book i, ch. ii.
53. "The term land necessarily includes,
not merely the surface of the earth as distinguished from
the water and the air, but the whole material universe
outside of man himself, for it is only by having access
to land, from which his very body is drawn, that man can
come in contact with or use nature." — Progress
and Poverty, book i, ch. ii.
54. "As commonly used the word 'wealth ' is
applied to anything having exchange value. But ...
wealth, as alone the term can be used in political
economy, consists of natural products that have been
secured, moved, combined, separated, or in other ways
modified by human exertion, so as to fit them for the
gratification of human desires." — Progress and
Poverty, book i, ch ii.
2. THE PRODUCTION OF WEALTH
When considered in connection with primitive modes of
production, the vital importance of this truth is
self-evident. 55 If those modes prevailed, involuntary
poverty would be readily traced either to direct
enslavement through ownership of Labor, or to indirect
enslavement through ownership of Land. 56 There could be no
other cause. If both causes were absent, every individual
might, if he wished, enjoy all the Wealth that his own
powers were capable of producing in the primitive modes of
production and under the limitations of common knowledge
that belonged to his environment.57
55. If we imagine upon a lonely island a
solitary man, without capital, without clothing, without
adequate shelter, what would be our explanation of his
poverty? We certainly should not say that it was caused
by a superabundance of goods — by over-production;
nor should we be any more likely to attribute it to
scarcity of money. We should first ask if the land of the
island were barren. Upon being assured that it would
yield far more than the solitary inhabitant could
consume, we should ask if he were physically or mentally
incapable of producing the things he required. If told
that not only was he quite capable, but that in the years
he had been upon the island he had continually improved
in industrial knowledge, in inventive acuteness, in
manual dexterity, and in muscular power, and yet that he
was scarcely if any better able to satisfy his wants than
when first cast ashore, we might ask if he were lazy. If
informed that he was not lazy, that he worked almost as
many hours as ever and quite as hard and far more
productively, we should ask if he were the chattel slave
of an exacting master. Satisfied that this was not the
case, we should then say:
"The only explanation left is that in some
way that man's opportunities to use the island are
restricted — the Labor of the island and the Land
of the island do not freely meet."
And if we were thereupon advised that a
neighboring cannibal chief, who claimed the island as his
private property, had granted the lone inhabitant
permission to live, upon the sole condition that he yield
tribute for the land, and that the tribute had a way of
advancing as the worker's productive power increased, we
should understand the cause of his poverty. And we should
advise him to find a way at once of throwing off the
land-owner's yoke, and to postpone all such secondary
questions as the money supply until their proper
settlement could operate for his own benefit instead of
for the benefit of the proprietor of the island.
56. The ownership of the land is
essentially the ownership of the men who must use it.
"Let the circumstances be what they may
— the ownership of land will always give the
ownership of men to a degree measured by the necessity
(real or artificial) for the use of land. Place one
hundred men on an island from which there is no escape,
and whether you make one of these men the absolute owner
of the other ninety-nine, or the absolute owner of the
soil of the island, will make no difference either to him
or to them." — Progress and Poverty, book vii,
ch. ii.
Let us imagine a shipwrecked sailor who,
after battling with the waves, touches land upon an
uninhabited but fertile island. Though hungry and naked
and shelterless, he soon has food and clothing and a
house — all of them rude, to be sure, but
comfortable. How does he get them? By applying his Labor
to the Land of the island. In a little while he lives as
comfortably as an isolated man can.
Now let another shipwrecked sailor be
washed ashore. As he is about to step out of the water
the first man accosts him:
"Hello, there! If you want to come ashore
you must agree to be my slave."
The second replies: "I can't. I come from
the United States, where they don't believe in
slavery."
"Oh, I beg your pardon. I didn't know you
came from the United States. I had no intention of
hurting your feelings, you know. But say, they believe in
owning land in the United States, don't they?"
"Yes."
"Very well; you just agree that this island
is mine, and you may come ashore a free man."
"But how does the island happen to be
yours? Did you make it?"
"No, I didn't make it."
"Have you a title from its maker?"
"No, I haven't any title from its
maker."
"Well, what is your title, anyhow?"
"Oh, my title is good enough. I got here
first."
Of course he got there first. But he didn't
mean to, and he wouldn't have done it if he could have
helped it. But the newcomer is satisfied, and says:
"Well, that's a good United States title,
so I guess I'll recognize it and come ashore. But
remember, I am to be a free man."
"Certainly you are. Come right along up to
my cabin."
For a time the two get along well enough
together. But on some fine morning the proprietor
concludes that he would rather lie abed than scurry
around for his breakfast and not being in a good humor,
perhaps, he somewhat roughly commands his "brother man"
to cook him a bird.
"What?" exclaims the brother.
"I tell you to go and kill a bird and cook
it for my breakfast."
"That sounds big," sneers the second free
and equal member of the little community; "but what am I
to get for doing this?"
"Oh," the first replies languidly, "if you
kill me a fat bird and cook it nicely, then after I have
had my breakfast off the bird you may cook the gizzard
for your own breakfast. That's pay enough. The work is
easy."
"But I want you to understand that I am not
your slave, and I won't do that work for that pay. I'll
do as much work for you as you do for me, and no
more."
"Then, sir," the first comer shouts in
virtuous wrath, "I want you to understand that my charity
is at an end. I have treated you better than you deserved
in the past, and this is your gratitude. Now I don't
propose to have any loafers on my property. You will work
for the wages I offer or get off my land! You are
perfectly free. Take the wages or leave them. Do the work
or let it alone. There is no slavery here. But if you are
not satisfied with my terms, leave my island!"
The second man, if accustomed to the usages
of the labor unions, would probably go out and, to the
music of his own violent language about the "greed of
capital," destroy as many bows and arrows as he could, so
as to paralyze the bird-shooting industry; and this
proceeding he would call a strike for honest wages and
the dignity of labor. If he were accustomed to social
reform notions of the namby-pamby variety, he would
propose an arbitration, and be mildly indignant when told
that there was nothing to arbitrate — that he had
only to accept the other's offer or get off his property.
But if a sensible man, he would notify his comrade that
the privilege of owning islands in that latitude had
expired.
57. While in the Pennsylvania coal regions
a few years ago I was told of an incident that
illustrates the power of perpetuating poverty which
resides in the absolute ownership of land.
The miners were in poverty. Despite the
lavish protection bestowed upon them by tariff laws at
the solicitation of monopolies which dictate our tariff
policy, the men were afflicted with poverty in many
forms. They were poor as to clothing, poor as to shelter,
poor as to food, and to be more specific, they were in
extreme poverty as to ice. When the summer months came
they lacked this thing because they could not afford to
buy, and they suffered.
Owing to the undermining of the ground and
the caving in of the surface here and there, there were
great holes into which the snow and the rain fell in
winter and froze, forming a passable quality of ice. Now
it is frequently said that intelligence, industry, and
thrift will abolish poverty. But these virtues were not
successful among the men of whom I speak. They were
intelligent enough to see that this ice if they saved it
would abolish their poverty as to ice, and they were
industrious enough and thrifty enough not only to be
willing to save it, but actually to begin the work.
Preparing little caves to preserve the ice in, they went
into the holes after a long day's work in the mines, and
gathered what so far as the need of ice was concerned was
to abolish their poverty in the ensuing summer. But the
owner of this part of the earth — a man who had
neither made the earth, nor the rain, nor the snow, nor
the ice, nor even the hole — telegraphed his agent
forbidding the removal of ice except upon payment of a
certain sum per ton.
The miners couldn't afford the condition.
They controlled the necessary Labor, and were willing to
give it to abolish their poverty; but the Land was placed
beyond their reach by an owner, and in consequence of
that, and not from any lack of intelligence, industry, or
thrift on their own part, their poverty as to ice was
perpetuated.
But in the civilized state this principle is so
entangled in the complexities of division of labor and
trade as to be almost lost in the maze. Many, even of those
who recognize it, fail to grasp it as a fundamental truth.
Yet it is no less vital in civilized than in primitive
modes of production.
a. Division of Labor
The essential difference between primitive and civilized
modes of production is not in the accumulation of capital
which characterizes the latter, but in the greater scope
and minuteness of its division of labor.58 Capital is an
effect of division of labor rather than a cause. Division
of labor, by enhancing labor power and relieving man from
the perpetual pursuit of mere subsistence, utilizes capital
and makes civilization possible.59
58. It is his failure to realize this that
accounts for the theory of the socialist that laborers in
the civilized state are dependent upon accumulated
capital as well as upon land for opportunities to
produce. See ante, note 49, and post, note 81.
59. Here are two men at a given point. Each
has an errand to do a mile to the east, and each has one
to do a mile to the west. If each goes upon his own
errand each will travel a mile out and a mile back in one
direction and the same in the other, making four miles'
travel apiece, or eight miles in all. But if one does
both errands to the east and the other does both to the
west, they will travel but two miles apiece, or four in
all. By division of labor they free half their energy and
half their time for devotion to other work, or to study,
or to play, as their inclinations dictate.
The productive power of division of labor may be
illustrated by considering it as a means for utilizing
differences of soil and climate. If, for example, the soil
and the climate of two sections of a country, or of two
different countries (for the effects of division of labor
are not dependent upon political geography 60), differ
inversely, one being better adapted to the production of
corn than of sugar, and the other, on the contrary, being
better adapted to the production of sugar than of corn,
they will yield more wealth in corn and sugar with division
of labor than without it.
6o. No more than are the effects of a
healthful climate. Protectionists who argue that there
should be free trade between villages, cities, counties
and states in the same nation, but protection for
nations, thus making the effect of trade to depend upon
the invisible political boundary line that separates
communities, are like the colored woman who, when her
house, without being physically removed, had been
politically shifted from North Carolina to Virginia by a
change of the boundary line, expressed her satisfaction
in the remark that she was very glad of it, because she
"allus yearn tail dot dat yah Nof Kline was an a'mighty
sickly State," and she was glad that she didn't "live
dyeah no me'!"
Let us imagine a Mainland and an Island, which, as to
the adaptability of their soil and climate to the
production of corn and sugar, so differ that if the people
of each should raise their own corn and their own sugar
they would produce, with a given unit of labor force, but
22 of Wealth — 11 in corn and 11 in sugar. Thus:
Chart 10, page 41
Production in that manner would ignore the opportunities
afforded by nature to man for utilizing differences of soil
and climate; but by such a wise division as Labor would
adopt in similar circumstances, if unrestrained, the same
unit of labor force almost doubles the product. Thus:
Chart 11, page 42
Nor is it alone because it utilizes
differences of soil and climate that division of labor is
so effective. Its effectiveness is enhanced in still higher
degree by its lessening of the labor force necessary to
accomplish any industrial result, whether in mining,
manufacturing, transporting, store-keeping, professional
employments, agriculture, or the incidental occupations.
Minute division of labor, instead of accounting for poverty
in the civilized state, makes it all the more
unaccountable.
b. Trade
But division of labor is dependent upon trade. If trade
were wholly stopped there would be no division of labor; 61
if it be interfered with, division of labor is obstructed.
62 In the last preceding chart, which illustrates the
effect of division of labor without trade, the Mainland
gets 20 of corn, but no sugar, and the Island gets 20 of
sugar, but no corn. Yet each wants both sugar and corn; and
if they freely trade, their wants in these respects will be
better satisfied than if each raises its own corn and
sugar.
61. Men who devoted themselves to
specialties, unable to exchange their products for the
objects of their desire, which alone would be the motive
for their special labor, would abandon specialties and
resort to less civilized methods of supplying their
wants.
62. Division of labor, whether adopted to
take advantage of the different varieties of land or to
secure the benefits of special skill in labor, cannot
continue without trade; and to the degree that trade is
impeded, to that degree division of labor will languish.
It is only under absolute free trade between all people
and in respect of all products that division of labor can
flourish. Any interference with it is economically an
enslavement of labor in a degree proportioned to the
degree of interference.
Compare the first chart of this series with the
following: 63
Chart 12, page 43
The comparison 64 illustrates the advantage to each
individual, community and country, of division of labor and
trade over more primitive modes of production. It is like
the difference between raising weights by direct
application of power, and by means of block and
tackle.65
63. It will be seen from this chart that
the people of the two places, by dividing their given
expenditure of labor in such a manner as to utilize the
natural advantage peculiar to each place, secure a clear
profit of 18. And this is a substantial profit,
consisting not merely of figures upon paper, but of real
wealth — artificial external objects which serve to
satisfy human desires.
64. The people of the Mainland have now
sent 10 of their corn to the Island, and the people of
the Island have paid for it by sending 10 of their sugar
to the Mainland.
For simplicity, the cost of effecting the
trade is omitted. It does not affect the principle. If
the cost were so high that more sugar and corn could be
got without division of labor than with, division of
labor would be abandoned as unprofitable; if low enough
to admit of any profit at all, the trading would go on,
unless restrained, precisely as if it involved no cost.
It may be well to state, however, that the nearer we get
to no cost in trading, the better are we off. Hence, any
tariff on trading, whether domestic or foreign, like
railroad and shipping rates for freight, is prejudicial;
for tariffs add to the cost of trading just as freight
rates do. Protection has that for its object. When it
does not add enough to the price of a foreign product to
prevent importation it fails of its purpose. And though
revenue tariffs have no such object they produce the same
effect, only in minor degree.
65. If every man were obliged, unassisted
by the co-operation of others, to supply his own needs
directly by his own labor, few could more than meagerly
satisfy even the simplest of those desires which we have
in common with lower animals. Though each labored
diligently the aggregate of wealth would be exceedingly
small compared with the necessities of those who wished
to consume it, while in variety it would be very limited
and in quality of the poorest kind. But by division of
labor, which has been carried to marvelous lengths and is
still developing, productive power is so enormously
increased that the annual wealth products of the present
time, in quantity and quality, in variety, usefulness and
beauty, almost appear to be the work of giants and
fairies.
And what this series of charts illustrates regarding two
places and two forms of wealth, is true in principle of all
places and all forms of wealth. That every one is better
served when each does for others what relatively he does
best, in exchange for what relatively they do best, is as
true of communities and nations as it is of individuals.
Indeed, it is true of communities and nations
because it is true of individuals; for it is
individuals that trade, and not communities or nations as
such.66
66. Mankind as a whole may be likened to a
great man, with eyes to see, brain to invent and direct,
nerves for intercommunication, and various muscles for
various actions. As different parts of the bodies of men
do different things, each part contributing
co-operatively to a general result, so it is with the
body politic, whose different parts — individual
men — contribute in different ways to the common
good. Trade is to the body politic what digestion is to
the physical body. To prohibit it is to deprive the great
man of his stomach; to restrict it is to give him
dyspepsia.
Says Emerson in the "American Scholar," an
oration delivered at Cambridge in 1837: "It is one of
those fables which out of an unknown antiquity convey an
unlocked-for wisdom, that the gods, in the beginning,
divided man into men, that he might be more helpful to
himself; just as the hand was divided into fingers, the
better to answer its ends."
Reflection upon the labor-saving power of
trade makes it clear that the notion of protectionists
that free trade is prejudicial to home industry has no
foundation. It would interfere with "home industries"
that could be better conducted elsewhere; but by that
very fact it would strengthen the industries that
belonged at home.
When we decide to buy foreign goods we do
not thereby decide to employ foreign labor instead of
American labor; we decide that the American labor shall
be employed in making things to trade for what we buy,
instead of making the things that we buy. And we get a
better net result or we wouldn't do it.
Free trade and labor-saving machinery,
which belong in the same industrial category, increase
the aggregate wealth of the country where they flourish.
Whether or not they tend to impoverish individuals or
classes, depends upon the manner in which the increased
wealth is distributed. If they do so tend, the remedy
surely does not lie in the direction of obstructing trade
and smashing machines so that less wealth may be produced
with given labor, but in altering the conditions that
promote unjust distribution.
c. The Law of Division of Labor and
Trade
Now, what is it that leads men to conform their conduct
to the principle illustrated by the last chart? Why do they
divide their labor, and trade its products? A simple,
universal and familiar law of human nature moves them.
Whether men be isolated, or be living in primitive
communities, or in advanced states of civilization, their
demand for consumption determines the direction of
Labor in production.67 That is the law. Considered in
connection with a solitary individual, like Robinson Crusoe
upon his island, it is obvious. What he demanded for
consumption he was obliged to produce. Even as to the goods
he collected from stranded ships — desiring to
consume them, he was obliged to labor to produce them to
places of safety. His demand for consumption always
determined the direction of his labor in production.68 And
when we remember that what Robinson Crusoe was to his
island in the sea, civilized man as a whole is to this
island in space, we may readily understand the application
of the same simple law to the great body of labor in the
civilized world.69 Nevertheless, the complexities of
civilized life are so likely to obscure its operation and
disguise its relations to social questions like that of the
persistence of poverty as to make illustration
desirable.
67. The term "production" means not
creation but adaptation. Man cannot add an atom to the
universe of matter; but he can so modify the condition of
matter, both in respect of form and of place, as to adapt
it to the satisfaction of human desires. To do this is to
produce wealth.
"Consumption" is the ultimate object of all
production. We produce because we desire to consume. But
consumption does not mean destruction. Man has no more
power to destroy than to create. His power in
consumption, like his power in production, is limited to
changing the condition of things. As by production man
changes things from natural to artificial conditions to
satisfy his desires, so by consumption he changes things
from artificial to natural conditions in the process of
satisfying his desires.
Production is the drawing forth of desired
things, of Wealth, from the Land; consumption is the
returning back of those things to the Land.
"All labor is but the movement of particles
of matter from one place to another." — Dick's
Outlines, p. 25.
Production consists merely in changing
things — Ely's Intro., part ii, ch. i; Mill's
Prin., book i, ch. i, sec. 2.
"As man creates no new matter but only
utilities, so he destroys no matter, but only utilities.
Consumption means the destruction of a utility." —
Ely's Intro., part v. ch. i., p. 268.
Production means "drawing forth." —
Jevons's Primer, sec. 17.
"Man cannot create material things. . . His
efforts and sacrifices result in changing the form or
arrangement of matter to adapt it better for the
satisfaction of wants." — Marshall's Prin.,
book ii, ch. iii, sec. i.
"It is sometimes said that traders do not
produce; that while the cabinet maker produces furniture,
the furniture dealer merely sells what is already
produced. But there is no scientific foundation for this
distinction." — Id.
"As his [man's] production of material
products is really nothing more than a rearrangement of
matter which gives it new utilities, so his consumption
of them is nothing more than a disarrangement of matter
which diminishes or destroys its utilities." —
Id.
"In like manner as by production is meant
the creation not of substance but of utility, so by
consumption is meant the destruction of utility and not
of substance or matter." — Say's Trea., book
ii, ch. i.
"All that man can do is to reproduce
existing materials under another form, which may give
them a utility they did not before possess, or merely
enlarge one they may have before presented. So that in
fact there is a creation not of matter but of utility ;
and this I call production of wealth. . . There is no
actual production of wealth without a creation or
augmentation of utility."— Say's Trea., book i,
ch. i.
68. It is highly significant that while
Robinson Crusoe had unsatisfied wants he was never out of
a job.
69. Demand for consumption is satisfied not
from hoards of accumulated wealth, but from the stream of
current production. Broadly speaking there can be no
accumulation of wealth in the sense of saving up wealth
from generation to generation. Imagine a man's satisfying
his demand for eggs from the accumulated stores of his
ancestors! Yet eggs do not differ in this respect from
other forms of wealth, except that some other forms will
keep a little longer, and some not so long.
The notion that a saving instinct must be
aroused before the great and more lasting forms of wealth
can be brought forth is a mistake. Houses and
locomotives, for example, are built not because of any
desire to accumulate wealth, but because we need houses
to live in and locomotives to transport us and our goods.
It is not the saving, but the serving, instinct that
induces the production of these things; the same instinct
that induces the production of a loaf of bread.
Artificial things do not save. No sooner
are the processes of production from land complete than
the products are on their way back to the land. If man
does not return them by means of consumption, then
through decay they return themselves. Mankind as a whole
lives literally from hand to mouth. What is demanded for
consumption in the present must be produced by the labor
of the present. From current production, and from that
alone, can current consumption be satisfied.
"Accumulated wealth" is, in fact, not
wealth at all in any great degree. It is merely titles to
wealth yet to be produced. A share in a mining company,
for example, is but a certificate that the owner is
legally entitled to a proportion of the wealth to be
produced in the future from a certain mine.
Titles to future wealth may be both morally
and legally valid. This is so when they represent past
labor or its products loaned in free contract for future
labor or its products; for example, a contract for the
delivery of goods of any kind today to be paid for next
week or next month, or next year, or in ten years, or
later.
They may be legally but not morally valid.
This is so when they represent the product of a franchise
(whether paid for in labor or not) to exact tribute from
future labor; for example, a franchise to confiscate a
man's labor through ownership of his body, as in slavery,
or a franchise to confiscate the products of labor in
general through ownership of land.
Or they may be both legally and morally
invalid, as when they are obtained by illegal force or
fraud from the rightful owner.
The following chart classifies about every kind of
wealth that man requires, and also "personal services,"
which, though as useful as wealth, do not crystallize in
material products — such services as those of
lawyers, barbers, doctors, teachers, actors, and so on:
Chart 13, page 47
The circle of variegated colors represents the
commercial reservoir into which Wealth is poured by
production, and from which it is drawn for consumption,
each color typifying the kind of wealth or service named in
it. Now, let us suppose that Personal Servants tap the
commercial reservoir for food.70 They do it by applying at
retail stores for what will relieve their poverty as to
food, and food flows out to them" as indicated by the blue
arrow, which we now insert in the chart:
70. If it be asked how Personal Servants
can draw this food out of the retail stores unless they
have money, let the questioner inform himself as to the
ways in which business is done. No man, unless he be a
notorious cheat, needs money in order to obtain goods at
retail stores, provided he has or can presently get
profitable employment. All he needs is employment, or an
early prospect of employment, and a reputation for
honesty. There is therefore no unwarranted assumption in
the example, even if we exclude the use of money from
consideration. See post, note 72.
Chart 14, page 48
How would the outflow of food affect managers of retail
stores? Every merchant's office-boy knows. It would
admonish them to order further supplies from wholesalers.
Wholesalers would fill these orders, and replenish their
stock by ordering from manufacturers. Manufacturers would
thereupon send all over the world for materials; would call
for new machinery and better machinery; would order new
buildings and repair old ones, and would scour the country
for workingmen to come into their factories and renew their
lowered stock of goods. Thus all kinds and grades of labor
that could assist in producing food, from farm hands to
inventors, from bookkeepers to sailors, would feel the
influence of the demand for food in a demand for their
labor. What Personal Servants really do in demanding food
is to direct the expenditure of labor to the production of
food and food-producing implements and materials.
Let us indicate this point upon the chart by running a
blue arrow from Food-makers to the food reservoir:
Chart 15, page 49
No complaint may now arise of lack of work in
food-producing lines.71 But work is only a means to an end.
It is done for the compensation it yields. And how are
Food-makers to be compensated? In services from Personal
Servants? Suppose they are not in want of services. But
they must be in want of something; if they need nothing
they have no poverty to relieve. Let it be clothing that
they lack. Then they are compensated for making food by
taking clothing from retail stores in exchange for their
unpaid claim against Personal Servants. Clothing thereupon
flows out of the commercial reservoir to them as food
flowed out to Personal Servants; and with similar effect,
namely, the setting to work of all clothing-making labor,
from sheep-raisers and cotton-growers to sewing-women and
salesmen.
71. Farmers, millers, bakers, ranchers,
butchers, fishermen, hunters, makers of food-producing
implements, food merchants, railroad men, sailors,
draymen, coal miners, metal miners, builders, bankers who
by exchanging commercial paper facilitate trade. together
with clerks, bookkeepers, foremen, journeymen, common
laborers, seeking for them instead of their seeking for
work. To specify the labor that would be profitably
affected by this demand would involve the cataloguing of
all workmen, all business men, and all professional men
who either directly or indirectly are connected with food
industries, and the naming of every grade of such labor,
from the newest apprentice to the largest supervising
employer.
Would not this be putting an end to "hard
times"? For what is the most striking manifestation of
"hard times"? Is it not "scarcity of work"? Is it not
that there are more men seeking work than there are jobs
to do? Certainly it is. And to say that, is not to limit
"hard times" to hired men. The real trouble with the
business man when he complains of "hard times" is that
people do not employ him as much as he expects to be
employed. Work is scarce with him, just as with those he
employs, or as he would phrase it, "business is
slack."
Let there be ten men and but nine jobs, and
you have "hard times." The tenth man will be out of work.
He may be a good union man who abhors a "scab" and will
not take work away from his brother workman. So he hunts
for a job which does not exist, until all his savings are
gone. Still he will not be a "scab," and he suffers
deprivation. But after a while hunger gets the better of
him, and he takes one of the nine jobs away from another
man by underbidding. He becomes a "scab." And who can
blame him? any one would rather be a "scab" than a
corpse. Then the man who has lost his place becomes a
"scab" too, and turns out some one else by underbidding.
And so it goes again and again until wages fall so low
that they but just support life. Then the poorhouse or a
charitable institution takes care of the tenth man, who
thereafter serves the purpose of preventing arise in
wages. Meanwhile, diminished purchasing power, due to low
wages, bears down upon business generally.
But let there be ten jobs and but nine men.
Conditions would instantly reverse, Instead of a man all
the time seeking for a job, a job would be all the time
seeking for a man; and wages would rise until they
equaled the value of the work for which they were paid.
And as wages rose purchasing power would rise, and
business in general would flourish.
If demand freely directed production, there
would always be ten jobs for nine men, and no longer only
nine jobs for ten men. It could not be otherwise while
any wants were unsatisfied.
The yellow arrows denote this:
Chart 16, page 51
The poverty of Food-makers as to clothing is thus removed.
They are working all they care to at food-making, their own
chosen employment, and they are paid in clothing, their own
chosen compensation. So long as Personal Servants withdraw
food and Clothing-makers supply clothing, Food-makers
cannot be poor. With them business will be brisk, labor
will be in demand, and wages will be high. That all the
other workers may enjoy the same prosperity we shall see in
a moment. Clothing-makers pour clothing into the commercial
reservoir because they wish to take something out, and know
that in this way they can get a larger quantity and better
quality of what they require than if they undertake to make
it themselves. They are skilled in making clothing; they
are not skilled in other ways. Accordingly they utilize the
claim against Personal Servants, which has passed to their
credit in exchange for clothing, by drawing from the
commercial reservoir the particular commodity they desire.
Suppose it to be shelter. They proceed as Personal Servants
and Food-makers have already done, and so set
Shelter-makers at work. Shelter-makers in turn utilize the
claim against Personal Servants which has now been credited
to them, by taking luxuries out of the reservoir. This sets
Luxury-makers at work. Luxury-makers then pass the claim
over in exchange for services, and Personal Servants redeem
it by rendering such services as Luxury-makers demand.72
Everybody is now paid for his own products with the
products of others; and by demanding more food, Personal
Servants may perpetuate the interchange indefinitely.73 And
Personal Servants will continue to demand more food until
their wants as to food are wholly and finally
satisfied.74
72. The mechanism of these exchanges should
be explained.
Personal Servants upon demanding food may
pay money for it. The retailers might thereupon pass the
money along, and it would ultimately return to Personal
Servants. Or the Personal Servants may give notes payable
at a future time, which being endorsed over would at last
be redeemed by them in services. Or they may give checks
on banks, which assumes previous work done by them or the
discounting of their notes by the banks. As the world's
exchanges are almost wholly adjusted by means of checks,
and other commercial paper which is in economic effect
the same as checks, let us illustrate that mode by a
series of charts adapted from Jevons.
We will begin with two traders, A and B.
They have no money, but every time that one demands
anything of the other he must offer in exchange something
that the other wants. There must be what is called "a
double coincidence" of demand and supply; each must want
what the other has. This is primitive barter. It may be
represented by the following chart :
Chart 17, page 52
In the civilized state, even in its
beginnings, primitive barter must be obstructive to
trade, and it gives way to the use of currency —
some common medium which is taken for goods not because
the taker wants it but because he knows that be can
readily exchange it for the goods that he does want. With
currency in use, when A wants anything of B he is not
obliged to find something that B wants. All he needs is
currency. Thus currency reduces the friction of
trading.
But as the volume of trade augments, demand
for currency increases; and because it is scarce, or
troublesome or dangerous to transmit, or all together,
easier means of exchange are resorted to, and bookkeeping
takes the place of currency as currency took the place of
primitive barter. At this stage, when A wants anything of
B, B charges him; and when B wants anything of A, A
charges him. Their mutual accounts being adjusted, the
small balance is paid with currency. Thus the demand for
currency is greatly lowered by bookkeeping, and the
friction of trading is correspondingly reduced.
Now let us bring in two more traders, C and
D:
Chart 18, page 53
Though all four of these traders keep
mutual accounts, the settlement of balances requires more
currency than before, and scarcity of currency, together
with the danger and expense of transmission, evolves an
extension of bookkeeping. A common bookkeeper, called a
"Bank," is employed, and all need for currency
disappears:
Chart 19, page 53
Balances are now settled by checks, and all
accounts are adjusted in the central ledger at the
bank.
But the introduction of another group of
traders, another community, renews the demand for
currency, and another bank appears. Thus:
Chart 20, page 53
And now the two banks are in the same
position that A and B were in before any bank came. They
keep mutual accounts, but they must have currency to
settle their balances. And if we bring in more
communities the demand for currency further increases.
Thus:
Chart 21, page 53
Now the four banks are in the same
situation that A, B, C and D were in before there were
any banks. This evolves a bank of banks — a
clearing-house.
All necessity for currency once more disappears.
These charts illustrate the principle by
which mutual trading is effected. In practice, the need
of currency is never wholly done away with, but the
tendency is constantly in the direction of doing away
with it. And it is said that over ninety per cent of the
trading transactions of the world are adjusted in this
manner, and less than ten per cent by means of
currency.
The clearing-house principle extends over
the civilized world. In illustration of this, observe the
following chart:
Chart 23, page 54
These five cities are like the five banks.
The bookkeeping of each city is conducted by local banks
and clearing-houses, and the central bookkeeping by those
of the market town of the world, which at present is
London.
In this way the mobility of labor is in
effect enormously increased. Labor in every corner of the
world is brought into close trading relations with labor
everywhere else, so that only war, pestilence,
protection, and land monopoly interfere with the full
freedom of its movement.
73. Personal Servants, on the basis of
their employment by Luxury-makers, demand more food,
which keeps Food-makers at work; Food-makers demand more
clothing, which keeps Clothing-makers at work;
Clothing-makers demand more shelter, which keeps
Shelter-makers at work; Shelter-makers demand more
luxuries, which keeps Luxury-makers at work;
Luxury-makers demand more services, which keeps Personal
Servants at work. And so on indefinitely.
If now we add progressive invention, so
that every one produces more and more wealth with less
and less labor, instead of finding poverty upon the
increase, instead of being harried by periodical "hard
times," we shall find business brisk and every one
becoming richer and richer. That is to say, though all
labor less than before, each obtains better results from
others while giving better results in exchange.
And should we improve the verisimilitude of
the illustration by bringing in the fact that all workers
in civilized society are specialists in a much more
minute degree than the division into Clothing-makers,
Food-makers, etc., would imply — that every one who
works does over and over some one thing in one of these
branches, as the making of shoes or the baking of bread,
or even only part of a thing, as the cutting of shoe
soles, and that while giving out a great deal of his own
product he demands in pay a little of every other kind of
product — the same effect would naturally
result.
Every man who demands anything for
consumption thereby determines the direction of labor
toward the production not only of that thing, but also of
all the artificial materials and implements, from the
simplest tool to the most expensive and complex machine,
that are used in its production. The actual process is
much more intricate than that of the charts, but the
charts illustrate the principle so that any intelligent
person who understands them can apply — it to the
most complex affairs of industrial life.
"This principle is so simple and obvious
that it needs no further illustration, yet in its light
all the complexities of our subject disappear, and we
thus reach the same view of the real objects and rewards
of labor in the intricacies of modern production that we
rained by observing in the first beginnings of society
the simpler forms of production and exchange. We see that
now, as then, each laborer is endeavoring to obtain by
his exertions the satisfaction of his own desires; we see
that although the minute division of labor assigns to
each producer the production of but a small part, or
perhaps nothing at all, of the particular things he
labors to get, yet, in aiding in the production of what
other producers want, he is directing other labor to the
production of the things he wants — in effect,
producing them himself. And thus, if he makes jackknives
and eats wheat, the wheat is really as much the produce
of his labor as if he had grown it for himself and left
wheat-growers to make their own jackknives." —
Progress and Poverty. book i, ch. iv.
74. There is no end to man's wants.
"The demand for quantity once satisfied, he
seeks quality. The very desires that he has in common
with the beast become extended, refined, exalted. It is
not merely hunger, but taste, that seeks gratification in
food; in clothes, he seeks not merely comfort, but
adornment; the rude shelter becomes a house; the
undiscriminating sexual attraction begins to transmute
itself into subtle influences, and the hard and common
stock of animal life to blossom and to bloom into shapes
of delicate beauty." — Progress and Poverty,
book ii, ch. iii.
A labor agitator was arguing the labor
question with a rich man, the judge of his county, when
the judge as a clincher asked:
"what do workingmen want, anyway, that they
haven't got?"
Promptly the agitator replied with the
counter-question
"Judge, what have you got that you don't
want?"
Let the chart be now advanced to show, in accordance
with the text, the perpetual flow of trade which this
action and reaction of demand and supply maintain:
Chart 24, page 56:
Thus each class of workers by its demands for
consumption determines the direction of the labor of some
other class. And in final analysis every person by his own
demands for consumption determines the direction of his own
labor in production as truly as Crusoe determined his; for
the demands of Personal Servants for food, of Food-makers
for clothing, of Clothing-makers for shelter, of
Shelter-makers for luxuries, and of Luxury-makers for
services, by enabling all to procure what they require in
exchange for what is demanded of them, determine each as to
the kind of employment to adopt.75
75. Regarding society as a unit, the operation of the
law is no less indisputable in social than in solitary
conditions. The demands of society as a whole determine
the degree of activity for each department of production,
much as Robinson Crusoe's demand for baskets imposed
greater activity upon his arms than upon his legs, or as
his demand for goats imposed greater activity upon his
legs than upon his arms.
But it is not necessary to regard society as a unit in
order to see that in the social as in the solitary state,
labor in production is expended in the direction of
demand for consumption. Each individual, in the social as
in the solitary state, produces the identical wealth that
he demands for consumption. The man, for example, who
wants a coat, and to get it makes shoes that he does not
want, but with which he hires some one to make him a
coat, really produces the coat; while he who wants shoes,
and to get them makes coats which he does not want but
which lie trades for shoes, really produces shoes.
Similarly, through the whole range of industry, each
individual hires other individuals to do what he wants
done, and pays for it by doing for others what they want
done. The condition is one of reciprocal hiring, and
under the common-sense legal maxim, qui facit per
alium facit per se (what one does by another he does
himself), as sound in economics as in jurisprudence, each
laborer, by inducing others to make the things that he
demands, in order to exchange them for what he makes,
really produces what he demands. But for his demands,
supplemented by his labor, these things would not be
produced.
True it is that in general trade goods are usually
made in advance of specific demand for them. But it would
be superficial reasoning to infer from this that
production determines consumption instead of being
determined by it. The collection of commodities in the
market is analogous to the collection of water in
reservoirs for the accommodation of the inhabitants of
cities. Water is so collected in advance of specific
demand, not to induce the people to consume water, but
because, being accustomed to consuming water, they make a
steady demand for it. And this demand determines the
supply. There are large reservoirs for large cities and
small ones for small cities. So with the commercial
reservoir. Stores are filled with goods in advance of
specific demand, not to induce demand but in obedience to
it. There is an approximate constancy to the demand for
wealth, upon which labor relies, and in consequence of
which wealth is continually in process of completion.
Though orders be supplied from existing stock. the stock
is at once replenished in accordance with the demand upon
it. And this is equivalent to the proposition that demand
for consumption determines the direction in which labor
will be expended in production. For it makes no
difference in economic principle whether a show dealer
takes his customer's measure and makes him a pair of
shoes, or keeps shoes in stock, and when he sells a pair
buys another like them. In either case the shoe dealer is
providing shoes pursuant to order. In the one, he
anticipates the order and has the goods ready when they
are called for; in the other, he obliges his customer to
wait until the goods can be made.
Though production may often seem to precede demand, as
when goods are stored months in advance of any possible
demand for consumption, and may sometimes actually
precede it, as when a new nostrum is placed upon the
market, the fact remains that production in any direction
rises and falls with the rise and fall of demand for
consumption; in other words, is determined by that
demand.
And this law regulates the supply of wealth not only
as to quantity, but also as to quality and variety.
Let us now complete this chart. When we began it a
distinction was noted between Personal Servants, who render
mere intangible services, and the other classes, who
produce tangible wealth. But essentially there is no
difference. By referring to the chart and observing the
course of the arrows, Food-makers are seen working for
Personal Servants precisely as Personal Servants work for
Luxury-makers. We may therefore abandon the distinction.
This makes it no longer necessary to mention particular
classes of products in the chart; it is enough to
distinguish the different kinds of labor.76 Thus:
Chart 25, page 58
76. "This, then, we may say is the great
law which binds society — 'service for service.'
"— Dick's Outlines, p. 9.
For simplicity the workers have been divided into great
classes, and each class has been supposed to serve only one
other class. But the actual currents of trade are much more
complex. It would be practically impossible to follow them
in detail, or to illustrate their particular movements in
any simple way. And it is unnecessary. The principle
illustrated in the chart is the principle of all division
of labor and trade, however minute the details and
intricate the movement; and any person of ordinary
intelligence who wishes to understand will need only to
grasp the principle as illustrated by the chart to be able
to apply it to the experiences of everyday industrial life.
All legitimate trade is the interchange of Labor for
Labor.77
77. In the light of this principle how absurd are some
of the explanations of hard times.
Overproduction! when an infinite variety of
wants are unsatisfied which those who are in want are
anxious and able to satisfy for one another. Hatters want
bread, and bakers want hats, and farmers want both, and
they all want machines, and machinists want bread and
hats and machines, and so on without end. Yet while men
are against their will in partial or complete idleness,
their wants go unsatisfied! Since producers are also
consumers, and production is governed by demand for
consumption, there can be no real overproduction until
demand ceases. The apparent overproduction which we see
— overproduction relatively to "effective demand"
— is in fact a congestion of some things due to an
abnormal underproduction of other things, the
underproduction being caused by obstructions in the way
of labor.
Scarcity of capital! when makers of capital
in all its forms are involuntarily idle. Scarcity of
capital, like scarcity of money, is only an expression
for lack of employment. But why should there be any lack
of employment while men have unsatisfied wants which they
can reciprocally satisfy?
Too much competition! when competition and
freedom are the same. It is not freedom but restraint,
not competition but protection, that obstructs the action
and reaction of demand and supply which we have
illustrated in the chart.
d. Dependence of Labor upon Land
We have now seen that division of labor and trade, the
distinguishing characteristics of civilization, not only
increase labor power, but grow out of a law of human nature
which tends, by maintaining a perpetual revolution of the
circle of trade, to cause opportunities for mutual
employment to correspond to desire for wealth. Surely there
could be no lack of employment if the circle flowed freely
in accordance with the principle here illustrated; work
would abound until want was satisfied. There must therefore
be some obstruction. That indirect taxes hamper trade, we
have already seen;78 but there is a more fundamental
obstruction. As we learned at the outset, all the material
wants of men are satisfied by Labor from Land. Even
personal services cannot be rendered without the use of
appropriate land.79 Let us then introduce into the
preceding chart, in addition to the different classes of
Labor, the corresponding classes of Land-owning interests,
indicating them by black balls:
Chart 26, page 60
78. See ante, pp. 9, 6 and 16.
79. Demand for food is not only demand for all kinds
and grades of Food-makers, but also for as many different
kinds of land as there are different kinds of labor set
at work. So a demand for clothing is not only a demand
for Clothing-makers, a demand for shelter is not only one
for Shelter-makers, a demand for luxuries is not only one
for Luxury-makers, a demand for services is not only one
for Personal Servants, but those demands are also demands
for appropriate land — pasture land for wool,
cotton land for cotton, factory land, water fronts and
rights of way, store sites, residence sites, office
sites, theater sites, and so on to the end of an almost
endless catalogue.
Every class of Labor has now its own parasite.
The arrows which run from one kind of Labor to another,
indicating an out-flow of service, are respectively offset
by arrows that indicate a corresponding in-flow of service;
but the arrows that flow from the various classes of Labor
to the various Land-owning interests are offset by nothing
to indicate a corresponding return. What possible return
could those interests make? They do not produce the land
which they charge laborers for using; nature provides that.
They do not give value to it; Labor as a whole does that.
They do not protect the community through the police, the
courts, or the army, nor assist it through schools and post
offices; organized society does that to the extent to which
it is done, and the Land-owning interests contribute
nothing toward it other than a part of what they exact from
Labor.80 As between Labor interests and Land-owning
interests the arrows can be made to run only in the one
direction.
80 See ante, pp. 12, 13, and 14.
Now, suppose that as productive methods improve, the
exactions of the Land-owning interests so expand — so
enlarge the drain from Labor — as to make it
increasingly difficult for any of the workers to obtain the
Land they need in order to satisfy the demands made upon
them for the kind of Wealth they produce. Would it then be
much of a problem to determine the cause of poverty or to
explain hard times? Assuredly not. It would be plain that
poverty and hard times are due to obstacles placed by
Land-owning interests in the way of Labor's access to
Land.
We thus see that in the civilized state as well as in
the primitive, the fundamental cause of poverty is the
divorce of Labor from Land. 81 But the manner in which that
divorce is accomplished in the civilized state remains to
be explained.
81. People with socialistic tendencies argue that
while it is true that Labor and Land are the only things
necessary in primitive conditions, Capital also is
necessary in civilized conditions. (See ante,
notes 49 and 58.) And they want to know, with something
like a sneer, what clerks and mechanics and bookkeepers
and other specialists in our highly organized industry
would do with land even if it were freely open to them.
"They don't know how to make food, and they can't eat
sand!" I once heard a socialist exclaim. The same notion
is widespread among that large class of single tax
opponents in church and college, whom the late Wm. T.
Croasdale described as "people who believe in socialism,
but don't believe in putting it into practice."
The idea is best expressed perhaps by a writer of the
most brilliant socialistic verses, Charlotte Perkins
Stetson, in the following :
"Free land is not enough. In earliest days
When man, the baby, from the earth's bare breast
Drew for himself his simple sustenance,
Then freedom and his effort were enough.
The world to which a man is born to-day
Is a constructed, human, man-built world.
As the first savage needed the free wood,
We need the road, the ship, the bridge, the
house,
The government, society, and church, —
These are the basis of our life to-day
As much necessities to modern man
As was the forest to his ancestor.
To say to the newborn, 'Take here your land;
In primal freedom settle where you will,
And work your own salvation in the world
Is but to put the last-come upon earth
Back with the dim fore-runners of his race,
To climb the race's stairway in one life
Allied society owes to the young—
The new men come to carry on the world—
Account for all the past, the deeds, the keys,
Full access to the riches of the earth.
Why? That these new ones may not be compelled
Each for himself to do our work again ;
But reach their manhood even with to-day,
And gain to-morrow sooner.
To go on,—
To start from where we are and go ahead
That is true progress, true humanity."—In
This Our World.
If one man were turned loose alone upon the earth, or
shut off from trading with his fellows, it might in great
degree be true, as Mrs. Stetson says, that he would be
put "back with the dim forerunners of his race, to climb
the race's stairway in one life"; but her criticism does
not apply to millions of free men who freely trade. To
them the land would be enough. Even though they were
denied existing roads and ships and bridges and houses,
they would soon make new ones, and starting "from where
we are," would "go ahead." For free land means access to
all natural materials and forces, and free trade means
unobstructed industrial intercourse between laborer and
laborer. These are the essential conditions, the only
conditions, of all production — even of the most
civilized.
The root of the socialistic idea is the thought that
we are dependent for social life upon accumulated
capital. This is a mistake. Social life depends, not upon
accumulated capital, but upon accumulated knowledge made
effective by interchange of labor. A laborer who operates
some great machine seems to be dependent upon the owner
of his machine for opportunity to work; but the only
people upon whom he really depends are laborers who are
competent co-operatively to make such machines, and who
have access to both the land from which the materials
must be drawn and that upon which they must group
themselves while doing the work. When socialists lay
stress upon the importance of accumulated capital they
are attributing to accumulated capital the power that
resides in land and trade; for to control these is to
command the benefits of accumulated knowledge.
Since the production of a machine precedes its use,
the inference is almost irresistible, upon a superficial
consideration, that opportunities to labor and
compensation for labor are governed by the existing
supplies of machinery to which labor is allowed access.
But this is of a piece with the old notion of classical
political economy that opportunities to labor are
dependent upon the existing supplies of subsistence that
are devoted to the maintenance of laborers. The inference
is wrong in either form. When we once grasp the essential
truth of the law illustrated in the text, that the
production of subsistence, or machinery, or any other
unfinished object, that is to say, of Capital, is but a
form of general wealth production, and that all forms of
wealth production are in obedience to demand, we clearly
see that labor is in no respect dependent upon capital
either for employment or compensation. In the social as
in the solitary state, Labor and Land are the only
factors of wealth production. It is not Capital but Land
that supplies materials to Labor for its subsistence and
its machinery. Instead of capitalists supplying laborers
with subsistence and machinery, laborers themselves
continuously produce subsistence and machinery from the
materials that land supplies. Capitalists neither employ
nor pay laborers; laborers employ and pay one
another.
Read "Progress and Poverty," book i, chs. iii, iv, and
v. Also read "The Story of My Dictatorship" (No. 4,
Sterling Library), chs. v, vi, vii, and viii.
3. THE DISTRIBUTION OF WEALTH
The chart on the following page displays the fundamental
principle of Production, which we considered at the
beginning, and also the fundamental principle of
Distribution, which is yet to be considered. In the
development of the latter will be found the explanation of
the divorce in the civilized state of Labor from Land:
Chart 27, page
64
This chart reminds us that Labor (human exertion), by
application to Land (natural materials and forces external
to man), produces Wealth (the generic term for all those
things that tend to satisfy the material Wants of man), and
so tends to abolish poverty. No man's poverty can be
abolished in any other way, unless it be by gifts, or
vulgar robbery, or legalized spoils.
The chart shows also that Wealth distributes ultimately
in Wages 82 (a fund made up of the aggregate of the
earnings of individual laborers), which corresponds to
Labor; and Rent 83 (a fund made up of the aggregate
premiums for specially desirable locations), which
corresponds to Land.84
82. "What is paid for labor of any kind is
called wages. We are apt to speak of the payment given to
the common day laborer only as wages; and we give finer
names to the payments which are made for some other kinds
of services. Thus we speak of the doctor's or the
lawyer's fee; of the judge's salary; of the teacher's
income; of the merchant's profit; of the banker's
interest, and of the professor's emoluments. They are all
in reality only payments for labor of different kinds, or
for different results of labor, — that is, they are
all wages." — Dick's Outlines, p. 23
"Wages is what goes to pay for all the
trouble of labor." — Jevons's Primer, sec.
39
"His [the manager's] share is called the
wages of superintendence, and although usually much
larger than the share of a common laborer, it is really
wages of the same nature." — Id., sec.
41.
"The common meaning of the word wages is
the compensation paid to a hired person for manual labor.
But in political economy the word wages has a much wider
meaning, and includes all returns for exertion. For, as
political economists explain, the three agents or factors
in production are land, labor, and capital, and that part
of the produce which goes to the second of these factors
is styled by them wages. . . It is important to keep this
in mind. For in the standard economic works this sense of
the term wages is recognized with greater or less
clearness only to be subsequently ignored." —
Progress and Poverty, book i, ck. ii.
83. Rent "is what is paid for the use of a
natural agent, whether land, or beds of minerals, or
rivers, or lakes. The rent of a house or factory is,
therefore, not all rent in our meaning of the word."
— Jevons's Primer, sec. 40.
"The term rent in its economic sense . . .
differs in meaning from the word rent as commonly used.
In some respects this economic meaning is narrower than
the common meaning; in other respects it is wider.
"It is narrower in this: In common speech,
we apply the word rent to payments for the use of
buildings, machinery, fixtures, etc., as well as to
payments for the use of land or other natural
capabilities; and in speaking of the rent of a house or
the rent of a farm, we do not separate the price for the
use of the improvements from the price for the use of the
bare land. But in the economic meaning of rent, payments
for the use of any of the products of human exertion are
excluded, and of the lumped payments for the use of
houses, farms, etc., only that part is rent which
constitutes the consideration for the use of the land
— that part paid for the use of buildings or other
improvements being properly interest, as it is a
consideration for the use of capital.
"It is wider in this: In common speech we
only speak of rent when owner and user are distinct
persons. But in the economic sense there is also rent
where the same person is both owner and user. Where owner
and user are thus the same person, whatever part of his
income he might obtain by letting the land to another is
rent, while the return for his labor and capital are that
part of his income which they would yield him did he hire
instead of owning the land. Rent is also expressed in a
selling price. When land is purchased, the payment which
is made for the ownership, or right to perpetual use, is
rent commuted or capitalized. If I buy land for a small
price and hold it until I can sell it for a large price,
I have become rich, not by wages for my labor or by
interest upon my capital, but by the increase of
rent.
"Rent, in short, is the share in the wealth
produced which the exclusive right to the use of natural
capabilities gives to the owner. Wherever land has an
exchange value there is rent in the economic meaning of
the term. Wherever land having a value is used, either by
owner or hirer, there is rent actual; wherever it is not
used, but still has a value, there is rent potential. It
is this capacity of yielding rent which gives value to
land. Until its ownership will confer some advantage,
land has no value." — Progress and Poverty,
book iii, chap ii
84. "The primary division of wealth in
distribution is dual, not tripartite. Capital is but a
form of labor, and its distinction from labor is in
reality but a subdivision, just as the division of labor
into skilled and unskilled would be. In our examination
we have reached the same point as would have been
attained had we simply treated capital as a form of
labor, and sought the law which divides the produce
between rent and wages; that is to say, between the
possessors of the two factors, natural substances and
powers, and human exertion — which two factors by
their union produce all wealth." — Progress and
Poverty, book iii, ch. v.
Care must be taken not to confuse the hire
of a house, commonly and legally termed "rent," with
economic Rent. House rent is really Wages; it is
compensation for the labor of house building. But
economic Rent is not compensation for anything; it is
simply the premiums for advantages of location.
a. Explanation of Wages and
Rent
Differences in the desirableness of land divide Wealth
into the two funds, Wages and Rent. Labor naturally applies
its forces to that land from which, considering all the
existing and known circumstances, most Wealth can be
produced with least expenditure of labor force. Such land
is the best. So long as the best land exceeds demand for
it, laborers are upon an equality of opportunity, and the
entire product goes to them as Wages in proportion to the
labor force they respectively expend. But when the supply
of the best land falls below demand for it, some laborers
must resort to land where with an equal expenditure of
labor force they produce less wealth than those who use the
best land. The laborers thus excluded from the best land
naturally offer a premium for it, or what is the same
thing, offer to work for its owners for what they might
obtain by working for themselves upon the poorer land. This
condition differentiates Rent from Wages. Rent goes to
land-owners as such, irrespective of whether they labor or
not; Wages go to laborers as such, irrespective of whether
they own land or not.85
85. Land of every kind may vary in
desirableness from other land of the same kind. Certain
farming land, for example, is so fertile that it will
yield to a given application of labor two bushels of
wheat to every bushel that certain other farming land
will yield; and it is obvious that, other things being
equal, farmers would prefer the more fertile land. But
some fertile land lies so far away from market that less
fertile land lying nearer is more productive, because it
costs less to exchange its products for what their
producer demands; in such cases farmers would prefer the
less fertile land. The same principle applies to all
kinds of land. Building lots at or near a center of
residence or business are preferable for most purposes of
residence or business to lots equally good in other
respects which are far away.
Now, the land that is preferable is of
course most in demand; and if it be all in use, with
demand for it unsatisfied, competition for the preference
sets in, and gives value to it.
All land cannot be equally desirable. Some
excels in fertility. Some is rich with mineral deposits,
a species of fertility. On some, towns and cities settle,
thereby adding to the productiveness of the labor that
uses it, because these sites are thus made centers of
co-operation or trade. And yet production in the
civilized state requires that the producer shall have
exclusive possession of the land lie needs. This
necessity inevitably gives to some people more desirable
land than others have, even though all should have an
abundance. Consequently the returns to equal labor are
unequal. The man who has land that is more fertile or
better located than that of another gets more wealth than
the other in return for a given expenditure of labor. If,
for example, one with given labor produces 10 bushels of
corn from fertile land, equal, say, to $5 worth of any
kind of wealth in the market, and the other with the same
labor produces 8 bushels of corn, or $4 worth of any kind
of wealth in the market, the first receives 2 bushels (or
$1) more for his labor than the other receives for his,
though each labors with equal effort, skill, and
intelligence. Or, if the fertility of the land be the
same, but its situation in reference to the market be
such that the cost of transportation still preserves the
relation of $5 to $4, the same inequality of wages
results. It is this phenomenon that gives rise to Rent.
Rent is the market value of just such differences in
opportunity as are here illustrated. It is a premium for
choice land, for preferential locations, for site, for
space.
This premium is a very different thing from
compensation for labor. Nor is the difference modified
when premium owners first obtain Wages for work and with
them buy the premium-commanding land. Rent can no more be
turned into compensation for labor by exchanging labor
products for the power to exact it, than a man can be
turned into Wealth by exchanging Wealth for him. Whether
the fruits of purchase or of conquest, or of fraud, Rent
always constitutes that part of Wealth which is deducted
from current production as premiums for superior
opportunities for production.
Wages and Rent are both drawn from Wealth,
and both go often to the same individual and in the same
form of payment, as when a freehold farmer enjoys the use
of the grain he raises from more fertile land than his
neighbors have, or a city freeholder occupies or receives
hire from his house and lot: but Wages flow from Wealth
to labor as compensation for production, while Rent flows
from Wealth to land-owners in premiums for allowing labor
to produce Wealth from superior locations. Wages are
appurtenant to Labor; Rent is appurtenant to Land. It is
as laborer that the individual takes Wages, but as
land-owner that he takes Rent.
To illustrate: On the following page are four closed
spaces representing land which varies in productiveness to
a given expenditure of labor force, 86 from 4 down to 1.
There is also an open space at the right, representing land
that is yet so poor as to yield nothing to the given
expenditure of labor force. Thus:
Chart 28, page 68
86. A unit of labor cannot be definitely
measured save by the value of some labor product. The
day's labor of one man may produce less than an hour's
labor of another. But for purposes of illustration it is
competent to refer to a unit of labor force as an
abstraction, intending thereby to denote all the labor of
muscle and brain requisite to acquire the necessary
knowledge and skill and to produce wealth to a given
value from given natural sources.
For simplicity let the market be equally convenient to
each space. Let it be assumed also that one space is as
accessible to labor as another, and that the differences in
their productiveness are known. Now, to which space would
labor first resort? Obviously to that which would yield
most Wealth to the given expenditure of labor force —
the space to the extreme left.
Suppose, then, that labor appropriates only as much of
the best space as is required for use — say half of
it. We may note the fact with red color upon the chart:
Chart 29, page
68
Here we see that Wages are 4 and Rent 0. The laborers,
as such, take the entire product, dividing it among
themselves in proportion to their services. There is no
Rent because other laborers find equally good opportunities
to produce in the uncolored part of the space; the supply
of the best land exceeds the demand for it, and of course
it commands no premium.87
87. "No land ever pays rent unless in point
of fertility or situation it belongs to those superior
kinds which exist in less quantity than the demand."
— Mill's Prin., book ii, ch. xvi, sec.
2.
"The produce of labor constitutes the
natural recompense or wages of labor. In that original
state of things, which precedes both the appropriation of
land and the accumulation of stock, the whole produce of
labor belongs to the laborer." — Smith's Wealth
of Nations, book i, ch. viii.
"Rent or land value does not arise from the
productiveness or utility of land. It in no wise
represents any help or advantage given to production, but
simply the power of securing a part of the results of
production. No matter what are its capabilities, land can
yield no rent and have no value until some one is willing
to give labor or the results of labor for the privilege
of using it; and what any one will thus give, depends not
upon the capacity of the land, but upon its capacity as
compared with that of land that can be had for nothing. I
may have very rich land, but it will yield no rent and
have no value so long as there is other land as good to
be had without cost. But when this other land is
appropriated, and the best land to be had for nothing is
inferior, either in fertility, situation, or other
quality, my land will begin to have a value and yield
rent. And though the productiveness of my land may
decrease, yet if the productiveness of the land to be had
without charge decreases in greater proportion, the rent
I can get, and consequently the value of my land, will
steadily increase. Rent, in short, is the price of
monopoly, arising from the reduction to individual
ownership of natural elements which human exertion can
neither produce nor increase." — Progress and
Poverty, book iii, ch. ii.
But if demand for land should continue until the best
space was monopolized, 88 and some laborers were forced to
resort to the next, the best space would command a premium;
89 Rent would rise and Wages would fall. Even though but
few laborers were forced to the poorer space, they would be
perpetual bidders for the advantages of the other space.
The effect may be illustrated by indicating with red in our
chart the overflow of labor from the first into the second
space:
Chart 30, page 70
88. "Rent is the effect of a monopoly;
though the monopoly is a natural one, which may be
regulated, which may even be held as a trust for the
community generally, but which cannot be prevented from
existing. . . If all the land of the country belonged to
one person he could fix the rent at his pleasure. . . The
effect would be much the same if the land belonged to so
few people that they could and did act together as one
man and the rent by agreement among themselves . . . The
only remaining supposition is that of free competition.
— Mill's Prin., book ii, ch. xvi, sec.
I.
Rent "considered as the price paid for the
use of the land is naturally a monopoly price." —
Smith's Wealth of Nations, book o, ch. xi.
89. The line of separation between the
poorest land thus commanding a premium, and the best land
for which labor will not pay a premium, was formerly
called "the margin of cultivation," probably because the
law of rent was not understood with reference to any but
agricultural land; but it is now more generally called
"the margin of production," since it is understood that
the law of rent applies to all kinds of land, including,
of course, the building lots of cities.
The premium for land falls not into the
fund termed Wages, but into the fund termed Rent.
Henceforth Wages consist not of the entire product of
labor, but of so much of that product as might with the
same expenditure of labor force be produced from the best
land that commands no premium. The remainder goes to the
owners of the land from which it is in fact produced, in
proportion to the advantages which their land
respectively contributes to its production. This excess
is the premium. It is what constitutes Rent as
distinguished from Wages. And both the amount of the
general fund Rent, and the amount of rent which each
land-owner obtains, are determined by the competition of
labor for superior opportunities.
Thus, in the beginnings all Wealth would be
Wages; but as labor was forced from better to poorer
lands, or, what is the same thing in its principle of
operation, as greater capabilities attached to particular
lands in consequence of social development, good
government, industrial improvement, etc. Rent would
arise, and as a proportion of the gross Wealth-product,
would increase as labor was forced to poorer land or new
capabilities were added to land by society. The law
derived from these phenomena is known as Ricardo's law of
rent. Henry George formulates it as follows:
"The rent of land is determined by the
excess of its produce over that which the same
application can secure from the least productive land in
use." — Progress and Poverty, book iii, ch.
ii.
As will be noticed, the law is the law of
Wages as well as the law of Rent. For whatever determines
the proportion of Wealth to be taken as Rent necessarily
determines the proportion to be left as Wages.
This illustrates the elementary principle of
Distribution, that Wages fall and Rent rises as demand for
land forces labor to land of lower productiveness.90 The
principle may be more graphically illustrated by supposing
that demand for spaces in the chart advances so far as to
include all the closed spaces, except part of the poorest
one. Thus:
Chart 31, page
71
90. Though figures are used, these charts
are to be understood not as mathematical
demonstrations, but simply as
illustrations.
We now find that all Wages have fallen to the level of
Wages on the poorest land that yields anything to the given
unit of labor force; while the Rent of all but that has, at
the expense of Wages, risen in proportion to its superior
productiveness.91
91. The labor that was forced to the
poorest lands would continually bid for the opportunities
that the better lands offered, until an equilibrium was
reached at the point shown in the preceding chart, where
the given expenditure of labor is as well compensated in
one place as in another.
If laborer and land-owner be different
persons, the laborer receives what is distinguished as
Wages, and the land-owner what is distinguished as Rent.
If the same person, he receives Wages as laborer and Rent
as land-owner.
Reflection will convince us that this must be so. Wages
for a given expenditure of labor force are no more
anywhere, for any length of time, all things considered,
than the same expenditure of labor force will produce from
the best land to be had for nothing. Rent absorbs the
difference.92
92. But we must not jump to the conclusion
that there is any essential wrong in Rent. Rent is
nature's method of measuring the value of the differences
in natural opportunity which different laborers, owing to
variations in land, are obliged to accept. And, what in
practice is more important, it is nature's method of
measuring the value to each individual of those
advantages which consist in accumulations of common
knowledge, in co-operative effort, in good government, in
a word, in the benefits that society as a whole confers
as distinguished from those which each individual earns.
The question is not one of the rightfulness or the
wrongfulness of Rent. Personal freedom necessitates Rent,
for it necessitates the private possession of land, and
private possession of land makes Rent inevitable. Nothing
short of communism could abolish it. The real question
is, What shall society do with Rent? Shall it give it to
individuals, or use it for common purposes?
"Were there only one man on earth, he would
have a right to the use of the whole earth.
"When there is more than one man on earth,
the right to the use of land that any one of them would
have, were he alone, is not abrogated; it is only
limited. . . It has become by reason of this limitation,
not an absolute right to use any part of the earth, but
(1) an absolute right to use any part of the earth as to
which his use does not conflict with the equal rights of
others (i. e., which no one else wants to use at the same
time), and (2) a co-equal right to the use of any part of
the earth which he and others may want to use at the same
time." — Perplexed Philosopher, p. 45.
It is in adjustment of this co-equal right
that rent occurs.
b. Normal Effect of Social Progress upon Wages and
Rent
In the foregoing charts the effect of social growth is
ignored, it being assumed that the given expenditure of
labor force does not become more productive.93 Let us now
try to illustrate that effect, upon the supposition that
social growth increases the productive power of the given
expenditure of labor force as applied to the first closed
space, to 100; as applied to the second, to 50; as applied
to the third, to 10; as applied to the fourth, to 3, and as
applied to the open space, to 1. 94 If there were no
increased demand for land the chart would then be like
this:
Chart 32, page 73
93. "The effect of increasing population
upon the distribution of wealth is to increase rent .. .
in two ways: First, By lowering the margin of
cultivation. Second, By bringing out in land special
capabilities otherwise latent, and by attaching
special capabilities to particular lands.
"I am disposed to think that the latter
mode, to which little attention has been given by
political economists, is really the more important."
— Progress and Poverty, book iv, ch.
iii.
"When we have inquired what it is that
marks off land from those material things which we regard
as products of the land, we shall find that the
fundamental attribute of land is its extension. The right
to use a piece of land gives command over a certain space
— a certain part of the earth's surface. The area
of the earth is fixed; the geometric relations in which
any particular part of it stands to other parts are
fixed. Man has no control over them; they are wholly
unaffected by demand; they have no cost of production;
there is no supply price at which they can be
produced.
"The use of a certain area of the earth's
surface is a primary condition of anything that man can
do; it gives him room for his own actions, with the
enjoyment of the heat and the light, the air and the rain
which nature assigns to that area; and it determines
his distance from, and in great measure his relations to,
other things and other persons. We shall find that
it is this property of land, which, though as yet
insufficient prominence has been given to it, is the
ultimate cause of the distinction which all writers are
compelled to make between land and other things." —
Marshall's Prin., book iv, ch. ii, sec. i.
94. Of course social growth does not go on
in this regular way; the charts are merely illustrative.
They are intended to illustrate the universal fact that
as any land becomes a center of trade or other social
relationship its value rises.
Though Rent is now increased, so are Wages. Both benefit
by social growth. But if we consider the fact that increase
in the productive power of labor increases demand for land
we shall see that the tendency of Wages (as a proportion of
product if not as an absolute quantity) is downward, while
that of Rent is upward. 95 And this conclusion is confirmed
by observation. 96
95. "Perhaps it may be well to remind the
reader, before closing this chapter, of what has been
before stated — that I am using the word wages not
in the sense of a quantity, but in the sense of a
proportion. When I say that wages fall as rent rises, I
do not mean that the quantity of wealth obtained by
laborers as wages is necessarily less, but that the
proportion which it bears to the whole produce is
necessarily less. The proportion may diminish while the
quantity remains the same or increases." —
Progress and Poverty, book iii, ch. vi.
96. The condition illustrated in the last
chart would be the result of social growth if all land
but that which was in full use were common land. The
discovery of mines, the development of cities and towns,
and the construction of railroads, the irrigation of and
places, improvements in government, all the infinite
conveniences and laborsaving devices that civilization
generates, would tend to abolish poverty by increasing
the compensation of labor, and making it impossible for
any man to be in involuntary idleness, or underpaid, so
long as mankind was in want. If demand for land
increased, Wages would tend to fall as the demand brought
lower grades of land into use; but they would at the same
time tend to rise as social growth added new capabilities
to the lower grades. And it is altogether probable that,
while progress would lower Wages as a proportion of total
product, it would increase them as an absolute
quantity.
c. Significance of the Upward Tendency of
Rent
Now, what is the meaning of this tendency of Rent to
rise with social progress, while Wages tend to fall? Is it
not a plain promise that if Rent be treated as common
property, advances in productive power shall be steps in
the direction of realizing through orderly and natural
growth those grand conceptions of both the socialist and
the individualist, which in the present condition of
society are justly ranked as Utopian? Is it not likewise a
plain warning that if Rent be treated as private
property, advances in productive power will be steps in the
direction of making slaves of the many laborers, and
masters of a few land-owners? Does it not mean that common
ownership of Rent is in harmony with natural law, and that
its private appropriation is disorderly and degrading? When
the cause of Rent and the tendency illustrated in the
preceding chart are considered in connection with the
self-evident truth that God made the earth for common use
and not for private monopoly, how can a contrary inference
hold? Caused and increased by social growth, 97 the
benefits of which should be common, and attaching to land,
the just right to which is equal, Rent must be the natural
fund for public expenses. 98
97. Here, far away from civilization, is a
solitary settler. Getting no benefits from government, he
needs no public revenues, and none of the land about him
has any value. Another settler comes, and another, until
a village appears. Some public revenue is then required.
Not much, but some. And the land has a little value, only
a little; perhaps just enough to equal the need for
public revenue. The village becomes a town. More revenues
are needed, and land values are higher. It becomes a
city. The public revenues required are enormous, and so
are the land values.
98. Society, and society alone, causes
Rent. Rising with the rise, advancing with the growth,
and receding with the decline of society, it measures the
earning power of society as a whole as distinguished from
that of the individuals. Wages, on the other hand,
measure the earning power of the individuals as
distinguished from that of society as a whole. We have
distinguished the parts into which Wealth is distributed
as Wages and Rent; but it would be correct, indeed it is
the same thing, to regard all wealth as earnings, and to
distinguish the two kinds as Communal Earnings and
Individual Earnings. How, then, can there be any question
as to the fund from which society should be supported?
How can it be justly supported in any other way than out
of its own earnings?
If there be at all such a thing as design in the
universe — and who can doubt it? — then has it
been designed that Rent, the earnings of the community,
shall be retained for the support of the community, and
that Wages, the earnings of the individual, shall be left
to the individual in proportion to the value of his
service. This is the divine law, whether we trace it
through complex moral and economic relations, or find it in
the eighth commandment.
d. Effect of Confiscating Rent to Private
Use
By giving Rent to individuals society ignores this most
just law, 99 thereby creating social disorder and inviting
social disease. Upon society alone, therefore, and not upon
divine Providence which has provided bountifully, nor upon
the disinherited poor, rests the responsibility for poverty
and fear of poverty.
99. "Whatever dispute arouses the passions
of men, the conflict is sure to rage, not so much as to
the question 'Is it wise?' as to the question 'Is it
right?'
"This tendency of popular discussions to
take an ethical form has a cause. It springs from a law
of the human mind; it rests upon a vague and instinctive
recognition of what is probably the deepest truth we can
grasp. That alone is wise which is just; that alone is
enduring which is right. In the narrow scale of
individual actions and individual life this truth may be
often obscured, but in the wider field of national life
it everywhere stands out.
"I bow to this arbitrament, and accept this
test." — Progress and Poverty, book vii, ch.
i.
The reader who has been deceived into
believing that Mr. George's proposition is in any respect
unjust, will find profit in a perusal of the entire
chapter from which the foregoing extract is taken.
Let us try to trace the connection by means of a chart,
beginning with the white spaces on page 68. As before, the
first-comers take possession of the best land. But instead
of leaving for others what they do not themselves need for
use, as in the previous illustrations, they appropriate the
whole space, using only part, but claiming ownership of the
rest. We may distinguish the used part with red color, and
that which is appropriated without use with blue. Thus:
Chart 33, page 76
But what motive is there for appropriating more of the
space than is used? Simply that the appropriators may
secure the pecuniary benefit of future social growth. What
will enable them to secure that? Our system of confiscating
Rent from the community that earns it, and giving it to
land-owners who, as such, earn nothing.100
100. It is reported from Iowa that a few
years ago a workman in that State saw a meteorite fall,
and. securing possession of it after much digging, he was
offered $105 by a college for his "find." But the owner
of the land on which the meteorite fell claimed the
money, and the two went to law about it. After an appeal
to the highest court of the State, it was finally decided
that neither by right of discovery, nor by right of
labor, could the workman have the money, because the
title to the meteorite was in the man who owned the land
upon which it fell.
Observe the effect now upon Rent and Wages. When other
men come, instead of finding half of the best land still
common and free, as in the corresponding chart on page 68,
they find all of it owned, and are obliged either to go
upon poorer land or to buy or rent from owners of the best.
How much will they pay for the best? Not more than 1, if
they want it for use and not to hold for a higher price in
the future, for that represents the full difference between
its productiveness and the productiveness of the next best.
But if the first-comers, reasoning that the next best land
will soon be scarce and theirs will then rise in value,
refuse to sell or to rent at that valuation, the newcomers
must resort to land of the second grade, though the best be
as yet only partly used. Consequently land of the first
grade commands Rent before it otherwise would.
As the sellers' price, under these
circumstances, is arbitrary it cannot be stated in the
chart; but the buyers' price is limited by the superiority
of the best land over that which can be had for nothing,
and the chart may be made to show it:
Chart 34, page 78
And now, owing to the success of the appropriators of
the best land in securing more than their fellows for the
same expenditure of labor force, a rush is made for
unappropriated land. It is not to use it that it is wanted,
but to enable its appropriators to put Rent into their own
pockets as soon as growing demand for land makes it
valuable.101 We may, for illustration, suppose that all the
remainder of the second space and the whole of the third
are thus appropriated, and note the effect:
Chart 35, page 79
At this point Rent does not increase nor Wages fall,
because there is no increased demand for land for use. The
holding of inferior land for higher prices, when demand for
use is at a standstill, is like owning lots in the moon
— entertaining, perhaps, but not profitable. But let
more land be needed for use, and matters promptly assume a
different appearance. The new labor must either go to the
space that yields but 1, or buy or rent from owners of
better grades, or hire out. The effect would be the same in
any case. Nobody for the given expenditure of labor force
would get more than 1; the surplus of products would go to
landowners as Rent, either directly in rent payments, or
indirectly through lower Wages. Thus:
Chart 36, page 80
101. The text speaks of Rent only as a
periodical or continuous payment — what would be
called "ground rent." But actual or potential Rent may
always be, and frequently is, capitalized for the purpose
of selling the right to enjoy it, and it is to selling
value that we usually refer when dealing in land.
Land which has the power of yielding Rent
to its owner will have a selling value, whether it be
used or not, and whether Rent is actually derived from it
or not. This selling value will be the capitalization of
its present or prospective power of producing Rent. In
fact, much the larger proportion of laud that has a
selling value is wholly or partly unused, producing no
Rent at all, or less than it would if fully used. This
condition is expressed in the chart by the blue
color.
"The capitalized value of land is the
actuarial 'discounted' value of all the net incomes which
it is likely to afford, allowance being made on the one
hand for all incidental expenses, including those of
collecting the rents, and on the other for its mineral
wealth, its capabilities of development for any kind of
business, and its advantages, material, social, and
aesthetic, for the purposes of residence." —
Marshall's Prin., book vi, ch. ix, sec. 9.
"The value of land is commonly expressed as
a certain number of times the current money rental, or in
other words, a certain 'number of years' purchase' of
that rental; and other things being equal, it will be the
higher the more important these direct gratifications
are, as well as the greater the chance that they and the
money income afforded by the land will rise." —
Id., note.
"Value . . . means not utility, not any
quality inhering in the thing itself, but a quality which
gives to the possession of a thing the power of obtaining
other things, in return for it or for its use. . . Value
in this sense — the usual sense — is purely
relative. It exists from and is measured by the power of
obtaining things for things by exchanging them. . .
Utility is necessary to value, for nothing can be
valuable unless it has the quality of gratifying some
physical or mental desire of man, though it be but a
fancy or whim. But utility of itself does not give value.
. . If we ask ourselves the reason of . . . variations in
. . . value . . . we see that things having some form of
utility or desirability, are valuable or not valuable, as
they are hard or easy to get. And if we ask further, we
may see that with most of the things that have value this
difficulty or ease of getting them, which determines
value, depends on the amount of labor which must be
expended in producing them ; i.e., bringing them into the
place, form and condition in which they are desired. . .
Value is simply an expression of the labor required for
the production of such a thing. But there are some things
as to which this is not so clear. Land is not produced by
labor, yet land, irrespective of any improvements that
labor has made on it, often has value. . . Yet a little
examination will show that such facts are but
exemplifications of the general principle, just as the
rise of a balloon and the fall of a stone both exemplify
the universal law of gravitation. . . The value of
everything produced by labor, from a pound of chalk or a
paper of pins to the elaborate structure and
appurtenances of a first-class ocean steamer, is
resolvable on analysis into an equivalent of the labor
required to produce such a thing in form and place; while
the value of things not produced by labor, but
nevertheless susceptible of ownership, is in the same way
resolvable into an equivalent of the labor which the
ownership of such a thing enables the owner to obtain or
save." — Perplexed Philosopher, ch. v.
The figure 1 in parenthesis, as an item of Rent,
indicates potential Rent. Labor would give that much for
the privilege of using the space, but the owners hold out
for better terms; therefore neither Rent nor Wages is
actually produced, though but for this both might be.
In this chart, notwithstanding that but little space is
used, indicated with red, Wages are reduced to the same low
point by the mere appropriation of space, indicated with
blue, that they would reach if all the space above the
poorest were fully used. It thereby appears that under a
system which confiscates Rent to private uses, the demand
for land for speculative purposes becomes so great that
Wages fall to a minimum long before they would if land were
appropriated only for use.
In illustrating the effect of confiscating Rent to
private use we have as yet ignored the element of social
growth. Let us now assume as before (page 73), that social
growth increases the productive power of the given
expenditure of labor force to 100 when applied to the best
land, 50 when applied to the next best, 10 to the next, 3
to the next, and 1 to the poorest. Labor would not be
benefited now, as it appeared to be when on page 73 we
illustrated the appropriation of land for use only,
although much less land is actually used. The prizes which
expectation of future social growth dangles before men as
the rewards of owning land, would raise demand so as to
make it more than ever difficult to get land. All of the
fourth grade would be taken up in expectation of future
demand; and "surplus labor" would be crowded out to the
open space that originally yielded nothing, but which in
consequence of increased labor power now yields as much as
the poorest closed space originally yielded, namely, 1 to
the given expenditure of labor force.102 Wages would then
be reduced to the present productiveness of the open space.
Thus:
Chart 37, Page 82
102. The paradise to which the youth of
our country have so long been directed in the advice, "Go
West, young man, go West," is truthfully described in
"Progress and Poverty," book iv, ch. iv, as follows
:
"The man who sets out from the eastern seaboard in search
of the margin of cultivation, where he may obtain land
without paying rent, must, like the man who swam the
river to get a drink, pass for long distances through
half-titled farms, and traverse vast areas of virgin
soil, before he reaches the point where land can be had
free of rent — i.e., by homestead entry or
preemption."
If we assume that 1 for the given expenditure of labor
force is the least that labor can take while exerting the
same force, the downward movement of Wages will be here
held in equilibrium. They cannot fall below 1; but neither
can they rise above it, no matter how much productive power
may increase, so long as it pays to hold land for higher
values. Some laborers would continually be pushed back to
land which increased productive power would have brought up
in productiveness from 0 to 1, and by perpetual competition
for work would so regulate the labor market that the given
expenditure of labor force, however much it produced, could
nowhere secure more than 1 in Wages.103 And this tendency
would persist until some labor was forced upon land which,
despite increase in productive power, would not yield the
accustomed living without increase of labor force.
Competition for work would then compel all laborers to
increase their expenditure of labor force, and to do it
over and over again as progress went on and lower and lower
grades of land were monopolized, until human endurance
could go no further.104 Either that, or they would be
obliged to adapt themselves to a lower scale of
living.105
103. Henry Fawcett, in his work on
"Political Economy," book ii, ch. iii, observes with
reference to improvements in agricultural implements
which diminish the expense of cultivation, that they do
not increase the profits of the farmer or the wages of
his laborers, but that "the landlord will receive in
addition to the rent already paid to him, all that is
saved in the expense of cultivation." This is true not
alone of improvements in agriculture, but also of
improvements in all other branches of industry.
104. "The cause which limits speculation in
commodities, the tendency of increasing price to draw
forth additional supplies, cannot limit the speculative
advance in land values, as land is a fixed quantity,
which human agency can neither increase nor diminish; but
there is nevertheless a limit to the price of land, in
the minimum required by labor and capital as the
condition of engaging in production. If it were possible
to continuously reduce wages until zero were reached, it
would be possible to continuously increase rent until it
swallowed up the whole produce. But as wages cannot be
permanently reduced below the point at which laborers
will consent to work and reproduce, nor interest below
the point at which capital will be devoted to production,
there is a limit which restrains the speculative advance
of rent. Hence, speculation cannot have the same scope to
advance rent in countries where wages and interest are
already near the minimum, as in countries where they are
considerably above it. Yet that there is in all
progressive countries a constant tendency in the
speculative advance of rent to overpass the limit where
production would cease, is, I think, shown by recurring
seasons of industrial paralysis." — Progress
and Poverty, book iv, ch. iv.
105. As Puck once put it, "the man who
makes two blades of grass to grow where but one grew
before, must not be surprised when ordered to 'keep off
the grass.' "
They in fact do both, and the incidental disturbances of
general readjustment are what we call "hard times." 106
These culminate in forcing unused land into the market,
thereby reducing Rent and reviving industry. Thus increase
of labor force, a lowering of the scale of living, and
depression of Rent, co-operate to bring on what we call
"good times." But no sooner do "good times" return than
renewed demands for land set in, Rent rises again, Wages
fall again, and "hard times" duly reappear. The end of
every period of "hard times" finds Rent higher and Wages
lower than at the end of the previous period.107
106. "That a speculative advance in rent or
land values invariably precedes each of these seasons of
industrial depression is everywhere clear. That they bear
to each other the relation of cause and effect, is
obvious to whoever considers the necessary relation
between land and labor." — Progress and
Poverty, book v, ch. i.
107. What are called "good times" reach a
point at which an upward land market sets in. From that
point there is a downward tendency of wages (or a rise in
the cost of living, which is the same thing) in all
departments of labor and with all grades of laborers.
This tendency continues until the fictitious values of
land give way. So long as the tendency is felt only by
that class which is hired for wages, it is poverty
merely; when the same tendency is felt by the class of
labor that is distinguished as "the business interests of
the country," it is "hard times." And "hard times" are
periodical because land values, by falling, allow "good
times" to set it, and by rising with "good times" bring
"hard times" on again. The effect of "hard times" may be
overcome, without much, if any, fall in land values, by
sufficient increase in productive power to overtake the
fictitious value of land.
The dishonest and disorderly system under which society
confiscates Rent from common to individual uses, produces
this result. That maladjustment is the fundamental cause of
poverty. And progress, so long as the maladjustment
continues, instead of tending to remove poverty as
naturally it should, actually generates and intensifies it.
Poverty persists with increase of productive power because
land values, when Rent is privately appropriated, tend to
even greater increase. There can be but one outcome if this
continues: for individuals suffering and degradation, and
for society destruction.
e. Effect of Retaining Rent for Common
Use
If society retained Rent for common purposes, all
incentive to hold land for any other object than immediate
use would disappear. The effect may be illustrated by a
comparison of the last preceding chart with the
following:
Chart 38, page 85
There is but one difference between this chart and the
chart immediately preceding. In that Rent is confiscated to
private use, whereas in this Rent is retained for common
use. All the labor force indicated with red in the first of
the two charts would not more than utilize the space to the
left and part of the adjoining one, which would elevate
Wages to what, with the given labor force, could be
produced from the poorer of the two spaces. After that,
increase of Rent would not enrich land-owners at the
expense of other classes; it would enrich the whole
community.108
108. The laborer would receive in
Distribution all that he earned and no more than he
earned in Production; and that is the natural law.
In social conditions, where industry is
subdivided and trade is intricate, it is impossible to
say arbitrarily what is the equivalent of given labor.
Hence no statute fixing the compensation for labor can
really be operative. All that we can say is that labor is
worth what men freely contract to give and take for it.
But it must be what they freely contract to take as well
as what they freely contract to give; and men are not
free to contract for the sale of their labor when labor
generally is so divorced from land as to abnormally glut
the labor market and make men's sale of their labor for
almost anything the buyer offers, the alternative of
starvation. Laborers may be as truly enslaved by
divorcing labor from land as by driving them with a
whip.
f. The Single Tax Retains Rent for Common
Use
To retain Rent for common use it is not necessary to
abolish land-titles, nor to let land out to the highest
bidder, nor to invent some new mechanism of taxation, nor
in any other way to directly change existing modes of
holding land for use, or existing machinery for collecting
public revenues. "Great changes can be best brought about
under old forms."109 Let land be held nominally as it is
now. Let taxes be collected by the same kind of machinery
as now. But abolish all taxes except those that fall upon
actual and potential Rent, that is to say, upon land
values.
109. "Such dupes are men to custom, and so
prone
To rev'rence what is ancient and can plead
A course of long observance for its use,
That even servitude, the worst of ills,
Because delivered down from sire to son
Is kept and guarded as a sacred thing."
—Cowper.
It is only custom that makes the ownership
of land seem reasonable. I have frequently had occasion
to tell of the necessity under which the city of
Cleveland, Ohio, found itself, of paying a land-owner
several thousand dollars for the right to swing a
bridge-draw over his land. When I described the matter in
that way, the story attracted no attention; it seemed
perfectly reasonable to the ordinary lecture audience.
But when I described the transaction as a payment by the
city to a land-owner of thousands of dollars for the
privilege of swinging the draw "through that man's air,"
the audience invariably manifested its appreciation of
the absurdity of such an ownership. The idea of owning
air was ridiculous; the idea of owning land was not. Yet
who can explain the difference, except as a matter of
custom?
To the same effect was the question of the
Rev. F. L. Higgins to a friend. While stationed at
Galveston, Tex., Mr. Higgins fell into a discussion with
his friend as to the right of government to make land
private property. The friend argued that no matter what
the abstract right might be, the government had made
private property of land, and people had bought and sold
upon the strength of the government title, and therefore
land titles were morally absolute.
"Suppose," said Mr. Higgins, "that the
government should vest in a corporation title to the Gulf
of Mexico, so that no one could fish there, or sail
there, or do anything in or upon the waters of the Gulf
without permission from the corporation. Would that be
right?"
"No," answered the friend.
"Well, suppose the corporation should then
parcel out the Gulf to different parties until some of
the people came to own the whole Gulf to the exclusion of
everybody else, born and unborn. Could any such title be
acquired by these purchasers, or their descendants or
assignees, as that the rest of the people if they got the
power would not have a moral right to abrogate it?"
"Certainly not," said the friend.
"Could private titles to the Gulf possibly
become absolute in morals?"
"No."
"Then tell me," asked Mr. Higgins, "what
difference it would make if all the water were taken off
the Gulf and only the bare land left."
If that were done it is doubtful if land-owners could
any longer confiscate enough Rent to be worth the trouble.
Even though some surplus were still kept by them, it would
be so much more easy to secure Wealth by working for it
than by confiscating Rent to private use, to say nothing of
its being so much more respectable, that speculation in
land values would practically be abandoned. At any rate,
the question of a surplus — Rent in excess of the
requirements of the community — may be readily
determined when the principle that Rent justly belongs to
the community and Wages to the individual shall have been
recognized by society in the adoption of the Single
Tax."'
110. Thomas G. Shearman, Esq., of New York,
author of the famous magazine article on "Who Owns the
United States," estimates that sixty-five per cent of the
present annual value of the land in the United States
would pay all the present expenses of American government
— federal, state, county, and municipal.
IV. CONCLUSION
In "Progress and Poverty," after reaching his conclusion
that command of the land which is necessary for labor is
command of all the fruits of labor save enough to enable
labor to exist, Henry George says:
So simple and so clear is this truth that to fully see
it once is always to recognize it. There are pictures
which, though looked at again and again, present only a
confused labyrinth of lines or scroll-work — a
landscape, trees, or something of the kind — until
once attention is called to the fact that these things
make up a face or a figure. This relation once recognized
is always afterward clear. 111 It is so in this case. In
the light of this truth all social facts group themselves
in an orderly relation, and the most diverse phenomena
are seen to spring from one great principle.
111. This idea of the concealed picture was
graphically illustrated with a story by Congressman James
G. Maguire, at that time a Judge of the Superior Court of
San Francisco, in a speech at the Academy of Music, New
York City, in 1887. In substance he said:
"I was one day walking along Kearney Street
in San Francisco, when I noticed a crowd around the show
window of a store, looking at something inside. I took a
glance myself and saw only a very poor picture of a very
uninteresting landscape. But as I was turning away my eye
caught the words underneath the picture, 'Do you see the
cat?' I looked again and more closely, but saw no cat in
the picture. Then I spoke to the crowd.
"'Gentlemen,' I said, 'I see no cat in that
picture. Is there a cat there?'
Some one in the crowd replied:
"'Naw, there ain't no cat there. Here's a
crank who says he sees the cat, but nobody else can see
it.'
Then the crank spoke up:
'I tell you there is a cat there, too. It's
all cat. What you fellows take for a landscape is just
nothing more than the outlines of a cat. And you needn't
call a man a crank either, because he can see more with
his eyes than you can.'
"Well," the judge continued, "I looked very
closely at the picture, and then I said to the man they
called a crank:
"'Really, sir, I cannot make out a cat. I
can see nothing but a poor picture of a landscape.'
"'Why, judge,' he exclaimed, 'just look at
that bird in the air. That's the cat's ear.'
I looked, but was obliged to say:
'I am sorry to be so stupid, but I can't
make a cat's ear of that bird. It is a poor bird, but not
a cat's ear.'
"'Well, then,' the crank urged, 'look at
that twig twirled around in a circle. That's the cat's
eye.'
But I couldn't make an eye of it.
'Oh, then,' said the crank a little
impatiently, 'look at those sprouts at the foot of the
tree, and the grass. They make the cat's claws.'
"After another deliberate examination, I
reported that they did look a little like a claw, but I
couldn't connect them with a cat.
"Once more the crank came back at me.
'Don't you see that limb off there? and that other limb
under it? and that white space between? Well, that white
space is the cat's tail.'
"I looked again and was just on the point
of replying that there was no cat there so far as I could
see, when suddenly the whole cat burst upon me. There it
was, sure enough, just as the crank had said; and the
only reason that the rest of us couldn't see it was that
we hadn't got the right point of view. But now that I saw
it I could see nothing else in the picture. The landscape
had disappeared and a cat had taken its place. And, do
you know, I was never afterward able, upon looking at
that picture, to see anything in it but the cat!"
From this story as told by Judge Maguire,
has come the slang of the single tax agitation. To "see
the cat " is to understand the single tax.
Many events subsequent to his writing have gone to prove
that Henry George was right. Each new phase of the social
problem makes it still more clear that the disorderly
development of our civilization is explained, not by
pressure of population, nor by the superficial relations of
employers and employed, nor by scarcity of money, nor by
the drinking habits of the poor, nor by individual
differences in ability to produce wealth, nor by an
incompetent or malevolent Creator, but, as he has said, by
"inequality in the ownership of land." And each new phase
makes it equally clear that the remedy for poverty is not
to be found in famine and disease and war, nor in strikes
which are akin to war, nor in the suppression of strikes by
force of arms, nor in the coinage of money, nor in
prohibition or high license, nor in technical education,
nor in anything else short of approximate equality in the
ownership of land. This alone secures equal opportunities
to produce, and full ownership by each producer of his own
product. This is justice, this is order. And unless our
civilization have it for a foundation, new forms of slavery
will assuredly lead us into new forms of barbarism.112
112. "Our primary social adjustment is a
denial of justice. In allowing one man to own the land on
which and from which other men must live, we have made
them his bondsmen in a degree which increases as material
progress goes on. This is the subtile alchemy that in
ways they do not realize is extracting from the masses in
every civilized country the fruits of their weary toil;
that is instituting a harder and more hopeless slavery in
place of that which has been destroyed; that is bringing
political despotism out of political freedom, and must
soon transmute democratic institutions into anarchy.
"It is this that turns the blessings of
material progress into a curse. It is this that crowds
human beings into noisome cellars and squalid tenement
houses; that fills prisons and brothels; that goads men
with want and consumes them with greed; that robs women
of the grace and beauty of perfect womanhood; that takes
from little children the joy and innocence of life's
morning.
"Civilization so based cannot
continue. The eternal laws of the universe forbid it.
Ruins of dead empires testify, and the witness that is in
every soul answers, that it cannot be. It is something
grander than Benevolence, something more august than
Charity — it is justice herself that demands of us
to right this wrong. justice that will not be denied;
that cannot be put off — justice that with the
scales carries the sword." — Progress and
Poverty, book x, ch. v.
APPENDIX
BRIEF ANSWERS TO TYPICAL QUESTIONS
Q1. Do you regard the single tax as a panacea for all
social disease?
A. When William Lloyd Garrison announced his conversion to
the single tax in a letter to Henry George, he took pains
to state that he did not believe it to be a panacea, and
Mr. George replied : "Neither do I; but I believe that
freedom is." Your question may be answered in the same way.
Freedom is the panacea for social wrongs and the ills they
breed, and the single tax principle is the tap-root of
freedom.
Q2. Would the single tax yield revenue sufficient for
all kinds of government?
A. Thomas G. Shearman, Esq., of New York, estimates that
sixty-five per cent of the rent that the land in the United
States now yields actually and potentially to its owners,
would be sufficient. But whether it would or not is as yet
an unimportant question. If all revenues ought to be raised
from land values, then no revenues should be drawn from
other sources while any land value remains in private
possession. Until land values are exhausted the taxation of
labor cannot be excused.
Q3. In an interior or frontier town, where land has but
little value, how would you raise enough money for schools,
highways, and other public needs?
A. There is no town whose finances are reasonably managed
in which the land values are insufficient for local needs.
Schools, highways, and so forth, are not local but general,
and should be maintained from the land values of the state
at large.
Q4. What disposition would you make of the revenues that
exceeded the needs of government?
A. The people who ask this question ought to settle it with
those who want to know whether the single tax would yield
revenue enough. I do not believe that public revenues under
the single tax would exceed the just needs of economical
government; in better highways, better sidewalks, better
wharves, better schools, better public service of various
kinds, we should find sufficient demand for all our
revenues. But the question of deficiency or surplus is one
to be met and disposed of when it arises. The present
question is the wisdom and the justice of applying land
values to common use, as far as they will go or as much of
them as may be needed as the case may prove to be.
Q5. If the full rental value were taken would it not
produce too much revenue and encourage official
extravagance? If only what was needed for an economical
administration of government, would not land still have a
speculative value?
A. In the first part of your question you are thinking of a
vast centralized government as administering public
revenues. With the revenues raised locally, each locality
being assessed for its contribution to the state and the
nation, there would be no such danger. The possibility of
this danger would be still further reduced by the fact that
private business would then offer greater pecuniary prizes
than would public office, wherefore public office would be
sought for purer purposes than as money-making
opportunities. As to the second part of your question, the
speculative value of land would be wiped out as soon as the
tax on land values was high enough and that on improvement
values low enough to make production more profitable than
speculation. And this point would be reached long before
the whole rental value was absorbed in taxation.
Q6. If a land-owner builds, does not that increase the
value of his land and consequently the amount of the tax he
would have to pay? If so, would not he be taxed for his
improvement?
A. No. Upon the value of the building he would never pay
any tax. It is true that his improvement might attract
others to the locality in such numbers as to make land
there scarcer and consequently dearer. His own lot would in
that case rise in value with the other land and be taxed
more, just as the rest would be. But that would not take
any of his labor in taxes; he would still have his building
free of taxation. Thus: If on a lot worth $1000 a building
worth $1000 were erected, making the whole worth $2000, the
tax would fall only upon the $1000 which represents the
value of the lot. If land then became so scarce that the
lot rose in value to $1500 the tax would be raised. But the
owner's improvement would be still exempt. When his
property was worth $2000 he was taxed on $1000, the value
of the lot, leaving $1000, the value of the building, free;
and now, though he is taxed on $1500, the value of the lot,
$1000, the value of the building, is still free.
Q7. If a man owns a city lot with a $5000 building on
it, what, under the single tax, would hinder another man,
perhaps with hostile intent, from bidding a higher tax than
the first man was able to pay, and thus ousting him from
his building?
A. The question rests upon a misapprehension of method. The
single tax is not a method of nationalizing land and
renting it out to the highest bidder. It is a method of
taxation. And it would not only hinder, it would prevent
the unjust ousting of another from his building. The single
tax falls upon land-owners in proportion to the unimproved
value of their land; and this value is determined by the
real estate market — by the demands of the whole
community — and not by arbitrary bids. No one could
oust a man from his building by bidding more for the land
on which it stood than the occupier was paying; the single
tax would not be increased in any case unless the land upon
which it fell was in so much greater demand that the owner
could let it for a higher rent.
Q8. What would be the expense of collecting the single
tax as compared with that of collecting present
taxes?
A. Much less. It is easier to assess fairly, and easier to
collect fully; the machinery of assessment and collection
would be simpler and cheaper, and it would not enable first
payers to collect the tax with profits upon it from
ultimate payers.
Q9. How would you estimate land values?
A. As we do it now. As real estate dealers estimate them.
As appraisers in partition would estimate them. Read note
28.
Q10. How would you value the land of a farm when all the
land of the neighborhood was fully improved?
A. By ascertaining the value per square rod of the adjacent
highway. The value of that, for the purpose of adding it to
the farms along which it runs, would denote the land value
of the farms. Read notes 4 and 28.
Q11. How can mines be taxed without increasing the price
of the out-put?
A. By taxing the royalty, or, what is essentially the same,
by taxing their capitalized value as mining opportunities.
This would tend to lower rather than increase the price of
the product. Read note 11.
Q12. How would the single tax be assessed on a railroad
which passed through a farm worth (without its
improvements) $30 an acre?
A. According to the value, not of the adjacent farms, but
of the total right of way, much as the value of a navigable
river might be determined if it were private property.
Q13. How would you assess the land value tax of a man
who, by making levees, had reclaimed land from the
Mississippi? Say that the land when reclaimed was worth $50
an acre, but that the levees cost a great deal less.
A. The fact that the levees cost less than the value of the
land when reclaimed, shows that the opportunity for
reclaiming such land has a value. That value, the value of
the opportunity to reclaim, is the land value of the
property, and would be the basis of the tax.
Q14. How would you adjust mortgages to the single tax
scheme?
A. Mortgages are modified deeds, and mortgageors are
landowners in degree. I would make no adjustment, but would
warn mortgageors and mortgagees to adjust their interests
as they see fit when they make their mortgages, just as I
would warn buyers and sellers of land to guard their
interests as between themselves by their contracts. Full
notice has now been given that as soon as possible and as
fast as possible we propose to induce the people to bring
about a condition in which land values will be taken for
public use and improvement values be left for private use.
People who in the face of this notice neglect to protect
themselves in their contracts have no one else to blame if
when the change comes they suffer pecuniary loss in the
re-adjustment.
Q15. How will the single tax affect leases already made?
Will the loss of declining values fall upon the owner or
the lessee?
A. That will depend upon the covenants in the lease. It
behooves tenants to see to it that their leases contain
provisions in this respect. If they fail to protect
themselves they cannot complain in case they suffer when
the single tax comes into operation. They will have had
ample warning, and their misfortune will be due to their
own negligence.
Q16. Should the whole rental value of land be taken for
common use, or only enough for government purposes?
A. Only enough for government purposes. When the people see
that this method of taxation improves business, increases
wages, cheapens land, and generally promotes prosperity,
they will not hesitate to increase their taxes so long as
public improvements are needed and land values are
unexhausted. As is said in "Progress and Poverty" (book
viii, ch. ii): "When the common right to land is so far
appreciated that all taxes are abolished save those which
fall upon rent, there is no danger of much more than is
necessary to induce them to collect the public revenues
being left to individual landholders."
Q17. How would the tax be collected from those who
neglected or refused to pay?
A. As individuals may now collect rent from tenants who
refuse to pay: by suing for the tax, or evicting the
occupant, or both if necessary. I think, however, that the
public would deal more justly with occupants than landlords
do with ground renters. I think it would compensate for any
loss in respect of improvements.
Q18. How would you reach the bondholder, or the man with
money alone?
A. Why should we wish to reach him if his bonds or his
money represent labor products to which he has honestly
acquired a just title? This question is a legitimate
offspring of the plundering theory that men should be taxed
according to their ability to pay, the merits of which are
considered on pages 7-9. It is a question which may also
have been suggested by the fact that "bondholders" and "men
of money" are so often men who have special privileges
which coin money for them. There is a feeling that it would
be unfair to allow such special privileges to escape
taxation. It would be. But inquiry will show that the most
important of these privileges rest in the ownership of
land, and that the "bondholders" and "men of money" whom
the questioner probably has in mind, are in fact great
landlords; that is to say, that their fortunes are really
based upon land. When land values were taxed, the great
source of unearned incomes — land monopoly —
would be practically abolished, and bondholders and men of
money would be only those who earn what they have. Such
property no man of honest instincts should wish to
expropriate.
Q19. In your lecture you tell of a meteorite which a
poor man found, but which the law gave to the owner of the
land on which it fell. (See note 100.) Wouldn't the owner,
or possessor, or whatever you choose to call him, of that
land get the meteorite just the same if the single tax were
in force?
A. Yes, if only one meteorite fell upon his land. But if
meteorites got into the habit of falling there the land
would grow in value, and then the single tax would operate
to take the value of those meteorites for common use, less
the labor expended upon them, the value of which would go
to the laborer. I told of the one meteorite to illustrate a
principle. But as a practical question we need deal only
with land upon which, speaking in metaphor, meteorites have
a habit of falling. The occasional diamond, the nugget of
gold, or other valuable thing found here or there as one of
the accidents of a day, are of no practical moment; it is
the diamond fields, the gold mines, the fertile farming
spots, the centers of trade, and similar valuable
opportunities for labor, that are of moment as factors in
social problems.
Q20. Would not the single tax increase the rent of
houses?
A. No. It takes taxes off buildings and materials, thus
making it cheaper to build houses. How can house rent go up
as the cost of building houses goes down? Read pp. 5 to 8
and the related notes.
Q21. Do not the benefits of good government increase the
value of houses as well as of land?
A. No. Houses are never worth any more than it costs to
reproduce them. Good government tends to diminish the cost
of house building; how, then, can good government increase
the value of houses? You are confused by the fact that
houses, being attached to land, seem to increase in value,
when it is the land and not the house that really
increases. It is the same mistake that a somewhat noted
economic teacher, who advocates protection as his
specialty, made when he tried to show that there is an
"unearned increment" to houses as well as to lands. He did
so by instancing a lot of vacant land which had risen in
value from $5000 to $10,000, and comparing it with a house
on a neighboring lot which, as he said, had also increased
in value from $5000 to $10,000. At the moment when he
wrote, the house to which he referred could have been
reproduced for $5000; and had he been capable of thinking
out a proposition he must have discovered that it was the
lot on which the house stood, and not the house itself,
which had increased in value.
Q22. What difference would it make to tenants whether
they paid land rent to the community or to private
owners?
A. When they pay it to the community they are paying it in
part to themselves, and what others pay they share in; for
they are part of the community. They are also exempt from
taxes. And since there would be no inducement to speculate
in land if rent went to the community, land would be more
plentiful and rents would consequently be lower.
Q23. Would not the merchant shift his land value tax by
adding it to the price of his goods?
A. No. Read note 11.
Q24. Would not the tax on land values increase the value
of land?
A. No. Read note 11.
Q25. What good would the single tax do to the poor? and
how?
A. By constantly keeping the demand for labor above the
supply it would enable them to abolish their poverty.
Q26. Hasn't every man who needs it a right to be
employed by the government?
A. No. But he has a right to have government secure him in
the enjoyment of his equal right to the opportunities for
employment that nature and social growth supply. When
government secures him in that respect, if he cannot get
work it is because (1) he does not offer the kind of
service that people want; or (2) he is incapable. His
remedy, if he does not offer the kind of service that
people want, is either to make people see that they are
mistaken, or go to work at something else; if he is
incapable, his remedy is to improve himself. In no case has
he a right to government interference in his behalf, either
through schemes to make work, or by bounties or
tariffs.
Q27. Would working people, whose savings are in savings
banks or insurance companies which own land or have
mortgages upon land, lose by the shrinkage in land
values?
A. Not if the companies were managed intelligently. Well
managed companies would shift their investments as they
observed the persistent decline of land values. They would
do it even as soon as conditions appeared which would
naturally cause land values to shrink. But working people
could well afford to give all their savings for the
permanent employment and high wages that the single tax
would bring about. It is not working people but idle people
who would lose anything by the single tax.
Q28. If taxes have to be paid by labor, what difference
does it make to laborers whether they are levied in
proportion to land values, or otherwise?
A. When taxes are levied upon earners in proportion to
earnings, they take what the earners would otherwise keep;
but when they are levied upon land-owners in proportion to
land values, they take what the earners must in any event
lose.
Q29. Under the single tax could employers cut wages to
the starvation point?
A. No. Under the single tax employers would be constantly
bidding for workmen, instead of workmen constantly bidding
for employers as is the case now. It is the "oversupply" of
labor that makes starvation wages possible, and the single
tax would abolish that; not by reducing the supply of
labor, the Malthusian device, but by allowing the effective
demand for labor to freely increase.
Q30. What effect would the single tax have on
immigration ? Would it cause an influx of foreigners from
different nations?
A. If adopted in one country of great natural
opportunities, and not in others, its tendency would not
only be to cause an influx of foreigners, but also to make
their coming highly desirable. Our own experience in the
United States, when we had an abundance of free land and
were begging the populations of the world to come to us,
offers a faint suggestion of what might be expected.
Q31. Will not the capitalist be able under the single
tax to undersell the laborer — to sell goods for less
than cost, at least temporarily — and thereby force
him to accept the capitalist's terms ?
A. With capitalists continually hunting for men to help
them fill their orders, and bidding against each other to
get men, as would be the case under the single tax, such a
contingency would be in the highest degree improbable. It
is practically impossible. Nothing short of a trust, an
absolutely perfect trust, of all the owners of capital the
world over could produce it. And even then, plenty of very
useful land of all kinds being free and labor products
being exempt from taxation, all people who were outside of
the trust would resort co-operatively to the land, and the
trust would be obliged to take them in as the alternative
of falling to pieces under their competition.
Q32. Is not ownership of land necessary to induce its
improvement? Does not history show that private ownership
is a step in advance of common ownership?
A. No. Private use was doubtless a step in advance of
common use. And because private use seems to us to have
been brought about under the institution of private
ownership, private ownership appears to the superficial to
have been the real advance. But a little observation and
reflection will remove that impression. Private ownership
of land is not necessary to its private use. And so far
from inducing improvement, private ownership retards it.
When a man owns land he may accumulate wealth by doing
nothing with the land, simply allowing the community to
increase its value while he pays a merely nominal tax, upon
the plea that he gets no income from the property. But when
the possessor has to pay the value of his land every year,
as he would have to under the single tax, and as ground
renters do now, he must improve his holding in order to
profit by it. Private possession of land, without profit
except from use, promotes improvement; private ownership,
with profit regardless of use, retards improvement. Every
city in the world, in its vacant lots, offers proof of the
statement. It is the lots that are owned, and not those
that are held upon ground-lease, that remain vacant.
Q33. Would not the full single tax destroy the basis of
all credit — land values?
A. The full single tax — one hundred per cent of
annual ground rent — would wipe out land values,
which are but the capitalization of rent. But land values
are not the basis of credit. Merchants do not prefer
mortgages on land as security for commercial debts, unless
they hope to get the ownership of the land through
foreclosure. The true basis of every man's credit, from the
consumer at the cross-roads store to the great retail
merchant at the factory or the jobbing house, is honesty,
opportunity, and ability. He who will pay his debts if he
can, and has an opportunity to earn enough to pay them
with, and is able to make good use of the opportunity,
needs no land values to offer as a basis for commercial
credit. He has the ideal basis of all credit. And this
basis of credit every man could have if the single tax were
in operation.
Q34. Would the single tax benefit the debtor class? If
so, how?
A. It would. By abolishing the monopoly of opportunities to
work, and thus enabling debtors to earn enough, while
decently supporting themselves, to honestly pay their
debts. The debtor class deserves sympathy, not because it
is in debt, but because it is forced by existing
institutions to go into debt in order to work, and is then
so hampered and harried by the same institutions as to make
orderly repayment impossible and bankruptcy inevitable.
Q35. What would be the effect of the single tax if you
still left railroad, telegraph, money, and other monopolies
in private hands?
A. The real strength of all monopolies is in land monopoly.
Observe, for example, the land holdings of the inside ring
of such railroads as the Southern Pacific, to which the
interests of the road are corruptly made subordinate.
Abolish land monopoly, and the power of all the others will
go, as Sampson's strength went with the cutting of his
hair.
Q36. How is it possible to determine what part of a
man's product is due to land, and what part is due to
labor?
A. All products are due wholly to the union of land and
labor. Labor is the active force, land is the passive
material; and without both there can be no product at all.
But the part of a man's product that he individually earns,
as distinguished from the part that he obtains by virtue of
advantageous location, is determined by the law of rent
— by what his location is worth.
Q37. What is the value of a man's labor?
A. What he can get for it under competition in a free
market. There is no other test.
Q38. Is there no danger that under the single tax
scheming men of great intellect would be able to take
advantage of their less intelligent brethren, and by the
competitive system corral everything as they do now?
A. If they did, it would not be by the competitive system,
but because the competitive system was still imperfectly
developed. Competition is freedom, and such a thing as you
suggest could not be done where freedom prevailed. I
believe that the single tax would perfect competition. If
it did, and at any rate to the extent that it did, every
one would get what he earned.
Q39. Why does not labor-saving machinery benefit
laborers?
A. Suppose labor-saving machinery to be ideally perfect
— so perfect that no more labor is needed. Could that
benefit laborers, so long as land was owned? Would it not
rather make landowners completely independent of laborers?
Of course it would. Well, the labor-saving machinery that
falls short of being ideally perfect has the same tendency.
The reason that it does not benefit laborers is because by
enhancing the value of land it restricts opportunities for
employment.
Q40. Under the single tax theory what right have you to
tax the value of "made land," like the Back Bay of Boston?
Is not such land produced by labor?
A. The surface soil is produced by labor. But the
foundation —the bottom of a bay, a swamp, a river, or
a hole, is not. "Made land" does not differ economically
from a house. Its materials are produced from one place to
another and adjusted to meet the demand. But nature in the
case of the "made land," as in that of the house, supplies
the materials and the foundation. The value of the Back Bay
of Boston is chiefly the value of a location — a
communal value. The single tax would not take the value of
"made land"; it would take the value of the space where the
"made land" is.
Q41. Why does land tend to concentrate in the hands of
the few?
A. Because material progress tends to increase its value,
and under existing conditions valuable things tend to
concentrate in the hands of the few.
Q42. Does not the growth of a community increase the
value of other things as well as of land? For example, does
it not add to the value of the services of professional
men, or of any other business that is dependent upon the
presence and growth of the community, as truly as it does
to the value of land?
A. Granted that the growth of a community primarily tends
to increase profits, the increased profits tend in turn to
attract men there to share them. This intensifies
competition and tends to lower profits. At the same time it
increases demand for land and tends to enhance the value of
that. It therefore cannot be said that the growth of a
community finally increases the value of other things as
well as of land. In fact it does not. Appropriate houses in
cities are no dearer than appropriate houses in the
country, differences in cost of production being allowed
for. And although some professional men get very high wages
in thickly populated cities, the average comfort of
professional men in cities is no higher than in the
country, if as high. Moreover, even if labor values as well
as land values were increased by communal growth, it must
never be forgotten that labor values must always be worked
for by the individual, whereas land values are never worked
for by the individual. A lawyer may command enormous fees,
but he gets no fee at all unless he works for it; but when
land commands enormous rent the owner gets it without doing
the slightest work.
Q43. Is there any land question in places where land is
cheap ? In Texas, for example, you can get land as cheap as
two dollars an acre. Is there a land question there?
A. There is no place where land is cheap in the sense
implied by the question. Land commands a low price in many
places, but it is poor land; it is not cheap land. It is
true that in Texas there is land that can be had for two
dollars an acre, but it would yield less profit to each
unit of labor and capital expended upon it than land in New
York City which costs hundreds of thousands of dollars an
acre. The valuable New York land is the cheaper of the two.
The land question is the question in every place where land
costs more than it is worth for immediate use.
Q44. Though some people have made money by owning land,
isn't it true that others have lost? And don't the losses
more than off-set the gains?
A. Possibly. But that has no bearing upon the question.
What men lose through investments in land, the community
does not gain; but what they gain the community does lose.
Therefore, as between land speculators and the community,
the losses cannot be charged against the gains.
Q45. What is the difference between speculation in land
and in other kinds of property?
A. If all the products of the world were cornered by
speculators, but land were free, new products would soon
appear and the ill effects of the speculation would quickly
pass away. But if all the land were cornered by
speculators, though everything else were free, the people
would immediately be dependent upon the speculators for a
chance to live. That illustrates the difference.
Q46. How can it be possible that speculative land values
cause business depressions when, as any business man will
tell you, the whole item of land value — whether
ground rent or interest on purchase money — is one of
the smallest items in every business ?
A. You overlook the fact that the item of speculative rent
is the only item which the business man does not get back
again. The cost of his goods, the expense of clerk hire,
the rent of his building, the wear and tear of implements,
are all received back, in the course of normal business, in
the prices of his goods. Even his ground rent, to the
extent that it is normal (i.e., what it would be if the
supply of land were determined alone by land in use, and
not affected by the land that is held out of use for higher
values), comes back to him in the sense that his aggregate
profits are that much greater than they would be where
ground rent was less. But the extra ground rent which he is
obliged to pay, in consequence of the abnormal scarcity of
land, is a dead weight; it does not come back to him.
Therefore, even if infinitesimal in amount, as compared
with the other expenses of his business — and that is
by no means admitted — it is the one expense which
may break a thriving business down. Besides, it is not
alone the ground rent paid by the business man for his
location that bears down upon his business prosperity; the
weight of abnormally high land values in general presses
upon business in general, and by obstructing the flow of
trade forces the weaker business units to the wall. It is
not altogether safe to deduce general economic principles
from the ledgers of particular business houses.
Q47. Which is the more important, land or money?
A. This is like asking whether to a thirsty man water or a
cup is the more important. Land is a necessity; money is
but a convenience. The use of money is to facilitate trade.
But we can live without trade. And even to trade, money is
not indispensable. Trade can be carried on by means of
primitive barter or by bookkeeping, and in a very high
degree it is so carried on. But we cannot so much as live,
either in solitude or in society, without appropriate land.
"Give me all the money in the world," said an objector
once, "and you may have all the land." And this was the
answer: "The first thing I should do would be to order you
to give me your money or get off from my land."
Q48. Would you let money escape taxation, and so favor
money lenders ?
A. It is a curious fact that this question is most popular
among people who clamor for cheap money. How they expect to
cheapen money by taxing its lenders on their loans is past
finding out. To tax money lenders is to discourage money
lending, and thereby to increase interest on loans. Yes, we
should let money escape taxation. It escapes taxation now,
which in itself is a politic reason for exempting it; but
we should exempt it (by taxing nothing but land values) for
the additional and better reason that a man's money is his
own and the community has no right to it, while a man's
land value is the community's and the man has no right to
it. This would not favor money lenders in any invidious
sense. It would favor both lenders and borrowers; borrowers
by enabling them to borrow on easier terms, and lenders by
making their loans more secure.
Q49. Would the single tax abolish interest?
A. I do not think so. Interest properly understood is a
form of wages, and so far from abolishing it, the single
tax, which would tend to increase all forms of wages, would
tend to increase interest. But monopoly profits are often
confounded with interest, and by force of association have
given to interest a bad name; these would be minimized if
not wholly abolished by the single tax. It is impossible to
answer this question intelligibly to everyone who asks it,
without requiring him to be specific; for it is seldom that
two persons agree as to what they mean by interest. The
Western farmer thinks of the high rate that he pays, partly
for risk, partly from his ignorance of the modus operandi
of banking, and partly because legitimate banking
facilities are scarce in his Community; the Wall Street
operator thinks of the premiums that he pays for currency
in times of stress to tide him over from day to day; others
think of "interest" on government bonds, and others of
dividends of companies with valuable land rights. None of
these payments are really interest, and the single tax
would tend to rid society of them. But that advantage which
the workmen enjoy whose implements and materials are
already gathered, over those who have yet to devote time to
gathering implements and materials, an advantage which is
expressed in money and as interest upon capital, will not,
I should think, be abolished by anything that man can do.
The value of such an advantage is part of the wages of the
labor that creates it.
Q50. Would not the single tax take away the home place,
and so tend to crush out the home sentiment?
A. When the home place now becomes valuable, it is parted
with.
Q51. Yes; but when the home place is parted with now,
the home owner is compensated by the high price he
gets.
A. Then your question does not turn upon the home sentiment
but upon the dollar sentiment. As a matter of sentiment,
the condition would be no worse in any case than now, and
in many cases far better; as a matter of dollars, the
question is one of justice and not of the home. Under the
single tax any one who wanted a home could have it, and
never be obliged to abandon one home for another, unless
such changes took place in the neighborhood as to make the
place inappropriate for a home. He could not then, as he
does now, play dog in the manger, saying to the community,
"I will not use this place for appropriate purposes, nor
will I allow any one else to do so."
Q52. Is not the right of ownership of a gold ring the
same as the ownership of a gold mine? and if the latter is
wrong is not the former also wrong ?
A. If it be wrong for you to own the spring of water which
you and your fellows use, is it therefore wrong for you to
own the water that you lift from the spring to drink? If so
how do you propose to slake your thirst? If you argue in
reply that it is not wrong for you to own the spring, then
how shall your fellows slake their thirst when you treat
them, as you would have a right to, as trespassers upon
your property? To own the source of labor products is to
own the labor of others; to own what you produce from that
source is to own only your own labor. Nature furnishes gold
mines, but men fashion gold rings. The right of ownership
is radically different.
Q53. Is it true that men are equally entitled to land?
Are they not entitled to it in proportion to their use of
it?
A. Yes, they are entitled to it in proportion to their use
of it and it is this title that the single tax would
secure. It would allow every one to possess as much land as
he wished, upon the sole condition that if it has a value
he shall account to the community for that value and for
nothing else; all that he produces from the land above its
value being absolutely his, free even from taxation. The
single tax is the method best adapted to our circumstances,
and to orderly conditions, for limiting possession of land
to its use. By making it unprofitable to hold land except
for use, or to hold more than can be used to advantage, it
constitutes every man his own judge of the amount and the
character of the land that he can use.
Q54. Is it right that the owners of land should pay all
the taxes for the support of public institutions, while the
owners of commodities go untaxed?
A. Yes. Public institutions increase the value of land but
not of commodities. Read notes 14 and 18.
Q55. Our city raises $20,000 for fire protection. Is it
fair to tax land, which doesn't get that protection, and
let houses go free though they do get it?
A. Is not the land worth more with your fire protection
than it would be without it? Which would be better for the
owners of land in your city, to pay the $20,000, or to have
no fire protection? Read notes 14 and 18.
Q56. Rich man with large mansion; poor widow with small
house on same sized lot adjoining. The two pay the same
tax. Is that right?
A. There is no reason in justice why the community should
not charge poor widows as much for monopolizing valuable
land as it charges rich men. In either case it confers a
special privilege and should be paid what the privilege is
worth. The question is seldom asked in good faith. Poor
widows who live on lots adjoining large mansions are not
numerous, and when they exist they are simply
land-grabbers. In our sympathy for these widows, let us not
forget the vast armies of widows who not only do not live
next to mansions, but have no place in the whole wide world
upon which to rest.
Q57. If land and labor are equally indispensable factors
of production, why are they not equally entitled to the
product?
A. The laborer justly owns his labor, but the land-owner
cannot justly own his land. The question is not one of the
relative rights of men and land, but of men and men.
Q58. Should not the poor man be compensated for the loss
of his land value?
A. No. The reasons are numerous. Among them are the
following: The poor man's rights in the community and in
common property are neither more nor less than the rich
man's. The better conditions for the poor man which the
single tax would bring about would more than off-set his
loss in land values. The poor man has no land values worth
speaking of.
Q59. How would you compensate the man who has bought a
lot in order to make a home upon it, but is not yet able to
build?
A. By letting him, when he is ready to build, have a better
lot for nothing. The single tax would do this by
discouraging the cornering of land which now makes all good
lots scarce. When land was no longer appropriated except
for use, and that would result from the operation of the
single tax, there would be an abundance of building lots to
be had for the taking, which would be far more desirable
than the kind to which men who cannot afford to build homes
now resort when they buy lots for a home.
Q60. If the value of land be destroyed by the single
tax, would not justice require that land-owners be
compensated?
A. No. Land is given for the use of all, and rent is
produced by the community as a whole. To legally vest
land-ownership in less than the whole, excluding those to
come as well as those that are here, is a moral crime
against all who are excluded. Therefore no government can
make a perpetual title to land which is or can become
morally binding. Neither can one generation vest the
communal earnings of future generations in particular
persons by any morally valid title, as they certainly
attempt to do when they make grants of land. There is both
divine justice and economic wisdom in the command that "the
land shall not be sold in perpetuity." In the forum of
morals all titles to land are subject to absolute
divestment as soon as the people decide upon the
change.
Q61. If a man buys land in good faith, under the laws
under which we live, is he not entitled to compensation for
his individual loss when titles are abolished?
A. There is no sounder principle of law than that which,
distinguishing the contractual from the legislative powers
of government, prescribes that government cannot tie up its
legislative powers. Now, land tenures and taxation are so
clearly matters of general public policy that no one would
deny that they are legislative and not contractual in
character. It follows that titles to land, and privileges
of more or less exemption from taxation, are voidable at
the pleasure of the people. And the possibility of such
action on the part of the people is as truly a part of
every grant of land as if it were written expressly in the
body of the instrument. Moreover, notice was given when
Henry George published "Progress and Poverty," and has been
reiterated often since in louder and louder tones until the
whole civilized world has become cognizant of it, that an
effort is in progress to do what is in effect this very
thing. That notice is a moral cloud upon every title, and
he who buys now buys with notice. It will not do for him
when the time comes, to say: "I relied upon the good faith
of the government whose laws told me I might buy." He has
notice, and if he buys he buys at his peril. Men cannot be
allowed to make bets that the effort to retain land values
for common use will fail, and then when they lose their
bets call upon the people to compensate them for the loss.
Read the chapter on "Compensation" in Henry George's
"Perplexed Philosopher."
Q62. If the ownership of land is immoral is it not the
duty of individuals who see its immorality to refrain from
profiting by it?
A. No. The immorality is institutional, not individual.
Every member of a community has a right to land and an
interest in the rent of land. Under the single tax both
rights would be conserved. But under existing social
institutions the only way of securing either is to own land
and profit by it. To refrain from doing so would have no
reformatory effect. It is one of the eccentricities of
narrow minds to believe or profess to believe that
institutional wrongs and individual wrongs are upon the
same plane and must be cured in the same way — by
individual reformation. But individuals cannot change
institutions by refraining from profiting by them, any more
than they could dredge a creek by refraining from swimming
in it. Institutional wrongs must be remedied by
institutional reforms.
LOUIS F. POST'S LECTURES
TESTIMONIALS FROM EDUCATIONAL INSTITUTIONS
"I doubt if the school ever enjoyed any lectures on
political economy as much as yours, because you presented
the subject with such simplicity and clearness that even
the most immature minds could follow it." — Sara
M. Ely, of The Misses Ely's School, Riverside Drive,
Eighty-fifth and Eighty-sixth Streets, New York.
"It is the unanimous verdict of the most competent
judges, that this lecture of Mr. Post's is not only the
best which has so far been delivered, but shows
extraordinary power of clear and instructive exposition of
his theory and of the fundamental principles of economics.
He impressed every intelligent person with the conviction
that he was a very remarkable teacher." — J. A.
Quarles, D.D., LL.D., Professor of Moral Philosophy,
Washington and Lee University, Lexington, Va.
"I had the pleasure of hearing in the chapel of
Washington and Lee University the lecture of Mr. Post on
single tax. I was greatly impressed by the ability of the
lecturer, and thought that I had never heard a more simple,
full, and clear exposition of the principles of the science
upon which the deductions of the lecturer were based. Mr.
Post has most admirable and exceptional gifts as a lecturer
and a teacher." — Gen. Scott Shipp,
Superintendent, Virginia Military Institute, Lexington,
Va.
"Mr. Post's lecture in City Hall last evening on
'Progress and Poverty' demonstrated that the elementary
truths of political economy can be presented to an audience
in a simple, luminous and deeply interesting way." —
Edwin P. Wentworth, ex-President Maine Chautauqua
Union.
"Mr. Post is a clear and pleasing speaker. He is
thoroughly familiar with the single tax theory. He states
his case in a clear and convincing manner. He was
especially satisfactory in the exposition of the single tax
theory, which he gave to the class in answer to questions
by members of the class." — Prof. Jesse Macy,
Chair of Constitutional History and Political Economy, Iowa
College, Grinnell, Ia.
"I was an interested listener at Mr. Post's last lecture
in Seattle. I did not miss a word, nor lose a thought.
While not accepting all his doctrine, I believe he has no
superior on the platform to-day." — Thomas M.
Gatch, President of the University of the State of
Washington, Seattle, Wash.
LETTERS FROM REPRESENTATIVE MEN.
"Mr. Post's method of presenting the subject of
political economy is admirable. His charts and diagrams,
together with his clear, concise, and forcible manner of
presenting the subject, make his lectures exceedingly
entertaining and instructive." — E. H. Long,
Superintendent of Public Schools of St. Louis, Mo.
"I not only enjoyed your lecture immensely, but think
that any one who had the vaguest interest in social
questions could not help being pleased with it." —
Bolton Hall, New York City
"I am not satisfied to let you leave Boston without an
expression of my enjoyment of your admirable lectures. The
approving words that have since come to me from many
listeners are an assurance that my opinion is unbiased."
— Wm. Lloyd Garrison, Boston, Mass.
"Wherever my endorsement may be of any use to you I will
be glad unequivocally to give it — to your personal
character, to your ability as a writer and lecturer, and to
the soundness, from my point of view, of the single tax
doctrines you are so successfully teaching." —
Henry George.
EXTRACTS FROM NEWSPAPER REPORTS AND EDITORIALS.
"Mr. Post is eloquent and entertaining." — San
Francisco (Cal.) Chronicle.
"Mr. Post is a speaker of much magnetism. His lecture
was replete with anecdote, and abounded in humor and
illustration." — Los Angeles (Cal.)
Express.
"He is not rhetorical; uses plain, simple language, and
is a natural logician. A subject complicated to many was
made simple and clear by his instructive discourse."
— Waco (Tex.) Evening News.
"He is an orator, but his style is conversational. His
language was so clear that even a child could understand."
— El Paso (Tex.) Daily Times.
"There was not a dry nor uninteresting moment in the
whole discourse." — San Francisco (Cal.)
Star.
"Mr Post's success in the treatment of his subject lies
in the charm of his manner. He talks to his audience, never
tiring them, surprising them by apt and unexpected
contrasts and illustrations, and running in his explanatory
anecdotes with a fluency and dry humor which sustain
interest until the last word. . . He never spared
hypocrisy, winked at dishonesty, or tolerated any means of
redress for wrongs except by peaceable and logical means."
— Seattle (Wash.) Post-Intelligencer.
"Mr. Post's style was admirable, his utterance rapid,
and he crowded into the compass of a single lecture enough
to make a volume." — Raton (N. M.)
Reporter.
"Mr. Post is a clear speaker, not lacking in platform
readiness and wit." — Montreal Herald.
"Mr. Louis F. Post is a clear, logical, and extremely
careful speaker." — Montreal Witness.
"A fluent speaker, and states his points very clearly."
— Toronto Empire.
"Mr. Post's style is lucid and forcible, without
anything savoring of grandiloquence." — Vancouver
(B. C.) Daily News-Advertiser
"He is a splendid speaker, clear, forcible, uses no
notes, and besides, is possessed of the gift of humor,
which he brings into welcome play." — Nanaimo (B.
C.) Free Press.
"The large audience was delighted with the lecture,
notwithstanding the fact that many of the ideas advanced
were new and strange to the greater part." —
Aspen (Col.) Daily Times
"He is a pleasing and effective speaker, and understands
his subject so thoroughly that he easily gained and held
the attention of his entire audience from the beginning to
the close of his lecture." — Mascoutah (Ill.)
Herald.
"A very pleasing speaker, easy and natural, with
excellent voice and convincing manner." — Elgin
(Ill.) Daily News.
"Mr. Post is an ideal lecturer." — Sioux City
(Ia.) Journal.
"Mr. Post is one of the most forcible speakers heard in
Des Moines on any subject in a long time." — Des
Moines (Ia.) Saturday Review.
"Louis F. Post turned what would ordinarily be a dry,
abstract discussion, in which only special students would
be interested, into a dissertation which all could
understand, and by which all could profit." —
Dubuque (Ia.) Herald.
"An admirable presentation of the single tax doctrine."
— Cedar Rapids (Ia.) Republican.
"Mr. Post is a very entertaining talker, and is
thoroughly versed in political economy." —
Atchison (Kan.) Globe.
"For two and one-half hours he held the attention of his
audience, interest in the subject, increasing at every
stage of his address." — New Iberia (La.)
Enterprise.
"Held his audience as by the power of a master mind."
— New Iberia (La.) Daily Iberian.
"A masterpiece of earnest eloquence and logical
argument." — Boston (Mass.) Advertiser.
"Has a power of clear and graphic presentation which few
men possess."— Editorial in Boston (Mass.)
Herald
"The exposition of the Henry George theory was
entertainingly clear, and furnishes a good basis for future
thought upon the subject." — University of
Michigan Daily, Area Arbor.
"The lecture — it was more of a talk — was
really a primer lesson on government and taxation. It was
quietly and earnestly given in plain words." —
Detroit (Mich.) Tribune.
"The lecturer is one of the best on the American
platform."— Cadillac (Mich.) State
Democrat.
"Mr. Post strikes one as being a deep thinker, a
scholar, a gentleman, and an unostentatious talker who
loses sight of himself in the interest he feels in the
subject he is presenting." — Adrian (Mich.) Daily
Times.
"Mr. Post is a very attractive and convincing speaker,
and the impression he made upon all who heard his address
last night was most favorable, and undoubtedly gave dignity
and won intellectual respect for his cause from many
persons who have not heretofore been disposed to give it
serious consideration." — Editorial in
Minneapolis (Minn.) Times.
"Mr. Post is evidently much more interested in
impressing his audience with the theory he elaborates than
with himself as its exponent. His gestures are a secondary
consideration, and his appearance is that of a professor
before his class." — Kansas City (Mo.)
Times.
"The address was two hours and a half in delivery, but
was so clear and logical that it was listened to with great
interest." — Lincoln (Neb.) State
Journal.
"His oratory held the attention of the audience
throughout his lecture." — Buffalo (N. Y.)
Enquirer.
"He delighted his hearers by his lucid treatment of the
theme." — Philadelphia (Pa.) Record.
"A fluent and entertaining talker, and speaks entirely
without notes. He intersperses his arguments and solid
points with illustrations in the shape of luminous
anecdotes." — Galveston (Tex.) Daily
News.
"An interesting speaker, and his lecture was
occasionally varied by a bright epigram or laughable
anecdote that gave pungency to his speech." —
Spokane (Wash.) Chronicle.
Mr. Post is a clear and forcible speaker, and presents
the Henry George theory of taxation with fine effect."
— Christian Standard
|
To share this page with a friend:
right click, choose "send," and add your
comments.
|
|
Red links have not been
visited; .
Green links are pages you've seen
|
|