User Fees
A combination of collecting land rent and imposing
user fees will move us closer to economic and social
justice, and will help reduce the enormous privileges
that accrue to those who have title to our very best land
and natural resources.
Robert V. Andelson Henry George and the
Reconstruction of Capitalism
Under Henry George's system,
private land titles would not be disturbed one iota. No
one would be expropriated. Instead, the community would
simply take something approaching the total annual economic
rent of land for public purposes. This amount would be
determined by the value of each site on the free market,
not by any arbitrary governmental fiat. In other words, the
privilege of monopolizing a site is a benefit received from
society and for which society should be fully compensated;
and so, under the Georgist system, the person who wished to
monopolize a site would pay a rent for it to the community,
approaching 100 percent of its annual rental value,
exclusive of improvements.
Let me emphasize that last phrase,
"exclusive of improvements."
- The apartment house owner would pay the full
value of his lot, and nothing on his
building;
- the factory owner would pay the full value of
his site, and nothing on his factory;
- the farmer would pay the full value of his
ground, and nothing on his structures or his
- crop, his livestock or his
machinery;
- the homeowner would pay the full value of his
lot, and nothing on his house.
If the land had no market value, the
owner would pay nothing; if it had a value, he would pay
regardless of whether he were using it or deriving income
from it.
This would, of course, eliminate
all speculative profit in landholding, squeeze the
"speculative water" out of land prices, and in effect bring
back the frontier by making cheap land readily available to
everyone -- at least initially. The result would be to
raise the margin of production, increase real wages, and
stimulate building and productivity. Eventually,
the flourishing economy would cause use value to exceed the
former speculative value, but instead of being engrossed by
those who make no contribution to the economy, land rent
would flow into the public coffers in place of taxes levied
upon labor and capital. The land-value charge is really
what Walt
Rybeck so aptly calls "a super user's fee." For the
privilege of exclusive access to and disposition of a site
and its natural resources, the owner pays an indemnity to
those who are thereby dispossessed -- an indemnity
reflecting precisely the market value of his privilege,
collected through the tax mechanism and relieving them of
the burden of payment for public services. What could be
more fair?
Actually, I daresay that each one of
you, probably without realizing it, frequently pays
something that partakes of the principle of such a "super
user's fee" whether you own land or not. Every time you
put money in a parking meter, you are purchasing a
temporary monopoly of the parking space. Don't ever
complain about having to put money in a public parking
meter; it's a bargain for you. You're getting a free gift
from the community -- the difference between what you pay
and what a commercial parking lot in the vicinity would
charge! Read the
whole article
Charles B. Fillebrown: A Catechism of Natural
Taxation, from Principles of Natural Taxation
(1917)
Q5. What is meant by equal right to
land?
A. The right of access upon equal terms -- preference to
be secured only upon payment of a premium that will
extinguish the equal rights of all other men.
Q7. What is meant by land value?
A. Its site value -- its selling or market value -- its
net value to the purchaser -- the capitalization of its
net rent -- the value supposed to be adopted by the
assessors as the basis of taxation.
Q50. How could the landowner escape the alleged
burden of an increase in his land tax?
A. Simply by assuming the legitimate role of a model
landlord, by putting his land to suitable use, in
providing for tenants at lowest possible price the best
accommodations and facilities appropriate to the
situation that money can buy.
... read
the whole article
Fred E. Foldvary — The Ultimate Tax Reform: Public
Revenue from Land Rent
Taxes, while ostensibly payments made for the services
of government, are quite unlike payments made in the
marketplace. The prominent libertarian economist Murray
Rothbard was among those who emphasized taxation as a
“coerced exchange,”3 in that few would freely
choose to pay taxes if not for the penalties imposed on
those who refuse to do so. But taxes are also different
from market prices in that the tax usually has no
relation to any specific benefit. Income and spending are
taxed because of “ability to pay,” meaning
there is a flow of funds from which money can be
siphoned, to put it politely.
In contrast, user fees (truly voluntary fees, not
excise taxes disguised as fees) are somewhat like market
prices, as the user pays for a specific and wanted
benefit, such as entrance to a park. Land value taxation,
too, is based on the benefit principle and on market
prices. A landowner receives extra land value or land
rental from the government infrastructure, security,
schooling, transit, fire protection, and so on. Land
rent, priced by the market, reflects the neighborhood
amenities. ...
Frank Chodorov, a fervent individualist and founding
editor of The Freeman, published by the Foundation for
Economic Education and still a leading libertarian
journal of ideas, became in 1937 director of the Henry
George School of Social Science in New York City, serving
until 1942. Like most followers of Henry George, Chodorov
regarded a charge on land value as not a true tax, which
arbitrarily extracts wealth, but a “payment for the
use of a location, determined by the higgling and
haggling of the market, and it makes no difference to the
land user whether he pays rent to the city fathers or to
a private owner.”26 Explaining the value of a
location derives to a great extent from community
services, rather than the efforts of the landowner as
such, Chodorov noted “it would seem logical that
this value—which we call land rent—should go
to defray the expenses of these common services.”27
... read the whole
document
Bill Batt: The
Merits of Site Value Taxation
... Not all revenue collection on the part of
government is grounded in the constitutional authority of
its tax powers. Taxes in the strictest sense of the term
are revenues involuntarily paid to general funds for the
general purposes of government. But there are many other
revenues paid to government that would never be construed
as taxes: lottery revenues, fines, interest payments,
environmental (green) fees, payment for information, and
user fees being the most common examples. Fines, green
fees, and user fees are instruments of police power
precisely because their primary purpose is to correct
behavior, and only secondarily to raise revenue. User
fees, along with environmental fees particularly, are
employed to recover the costs of use, wear or damage to
environmental or government-provided "services." (Only in
recent years has it been fashionable to regard use or
degradation of the natural environment as a "service,"
necessitating "correction," as was originally explicated
by Pigou earlier this century. ... Read the
whole piece
Louis Post: Outlines
of Louis F. Post's Lectures, with Illustrative Notes and
Charts (1894)
2. THE TWO KINDS OF DIRECT
TAXATION
Direct taxes fall into two general classes: (1) Taxes
that are levied upon men in proportion to their
ability to pay, and (2) taxes that are levied in
proportion to the benefits received by the
tax-payer from the public. Income taxes are the principal
ones of the first class, though probate and inheritance
taxes would rank high. The single tax is the only
important one of the second class.
There should be no difficulty in choosing between the
two. To tax in proportion to ability to pay, regardless
of benefits received, is in accord with no principle of
just government; it is a device of piracy. The single
tax, therefore, as the only important tax in proportion
to benefits, is the ideal tax.
But here we encounter two plausible objections. One
arises from the mistaken but common notion that men are
not taxed in proportion to benefits unless they pay taxes
upon every kind of property they own that comes under the
protection of government; the other is founded in the
assumption that it is impossible to measure the value of
the public benefits that each individual enjoys. Though
the first of these objections ostensibly accepts the
doctrine of taxation according to benefits,12 yet, as it
leads to attempts at taxation in proportion to wealth,
it, like the other, is really a plea for the piratical
doctrine of taxation according to ability to pay. The two
objections stand or fall together.
12. It is often said, for instance, by
its advocates, that house owners should in justice
contribute to the support of the fire departments that
protect them and it is even gravely argued that houses
are more appropriate subjects of taxation than land;
because they need protection, whereas land needs none.
Read note 8.
Let it once be perceived that the value of the service
which government renders to each individual would be
justly measured by the single tax, and neither objection
would any longer have weight. We should then no more
think of taxing people in proportion to their wealth or
ability to pay, regardless of the benefits they receive
from government than an honest merchant would think of
charging his customers in proportion to their wealth or
ability to pay, regardless of the value of the goods they
bought of him." 13
13. Following is an interesting
computation of the cost and loss to the city of Boston
of the present mixed system of taxation as compared
with the single tax; The computation was made by James
R. Carret, Esq., the leading conveyancer of Boston:
Valuation of Boston, May 1,
1892 Land... ... . ..
... .. ... .. $399,170,175 Buildings ... ... ... ... ..$281,109,700
Total assessed value of real estate
$680,279,875 Assessed
value of personal estate $213,695,829
.... .... ... ... ... ... ...
... .... .... .... ... .... ...
$893,975,704 Rate of
taxation, $12.90 per $1000
Total tax levy, May 1, 1892 $11,805,036
Amount of taxes levied in respect of the
different subjects of taxation and percentages of the
same:
Land .... .... .... .... $5,149,295 43.62%
Buildings .... .... .. $3,626,295 30.72%
Personal estate .. $2,756,676 23.35%
Polls ... .... ... .... .... ...272,750
2.31%
But to ascertain the total cost to the
people of Boston of the present system of taxation for
the taxable year, beginning May 1, 1892, there should
be added to the taxes assessed upon them what it cost
them to pay the owners of the land of Boston for the
use of the land, being the net ground rent, which I
estimate at four per cent on the land value.
Total tax levy, May 1, 1892 ...
... ... ... .... .... .... .... .... ..... .... ....
.... .... .... .... ..$11,805,036
Net ground rent, four percent, on the
land value ($399,170,175)..... ... ...
...$15,966,807 Total
cost of the present system to the people of Boston for
that year ... $27,771,843
To contrast this with what the single
tax system would have cost the people of Boston for
that year, take the gross ground rent, found by adding
to the net ground rent the taxation on land values for
that year, being $12.90 per $1000, or 1.29 per cent
added to 4 per cent = 5.29 per cent.
Total cost of present system as
above .. .... .... .... .... .... .... .... ....
....$27,771,843 Single
tax, or gross ground rent, 5.29 per cent on
$399,170,175 ... ..$21,116,102
Excess cost of present system, which
is the sum of taxes in
respect of buildings, personal property, and polls ....
...... .. $6,655,741
But the present system not only costs
the people more than the single tax would, but produces
less revenue:
Proceeds of single tax ... ... ...
... ..... .... .... ..... .... .... .... ..... .....
.... $21,116,102 Present
tax levy ... ... ... ... ... .... .... .... ..... ....
.... .... .... .... .... ....
....$11,805,036 Loss to
public treasury by present system ... .... .... ....
.... .. ..... ..$9,311,066
This, however, is not a complete
contrast between the present system and the single tax,
for large amounts of real estate are exempt from
taxation, being held by the United States, the
Commonwealth, by the city itself, by religious
societies and corporations, and by charitable,
literary, and scientific institutions. The total amount
of the value of land so held as returned by the
assessors for the year 1892 is $60,626,171.
Reasons can be given why all lands
within the city should be assessed for taxation to
secure a just distribution of the public burdens, which
I cannot take the space to enter into here. There is
good reason to believe also that lands in the city of
Boston are assessed to quite an appreciable extent
below their fair market value. As an indication of this
see an editorial in the Boston Daily
Advertiser for October 3, 1893, under the title,
"Their Own Figures."
The vacant lands, marsh lands, and flats
in Boston were valued by the assessors in 1892 (page 3
of their annual report) at $52,712,600. I believe that
this represents not more than fifty per cent of their
true market value.
Taking this and the undervaluation of
improved property and the exemptions above mentioned
into consideration, I think $500,000,000 to be a fair
estimate of the land values of Boston. Making this the
basis of contrast, we have:
Proceeds of single tax 5.29 per
cent on $500,000,000 ... .... .... ....
$26,450,000 Present tax
levy ... .... ... .... .... .... .... .... ..... ....
.... .... .... ..... .... ....
..$11,805,036 Loss to
public treasury by present system ... ... ... ... ....
.... .... ....$14,644,974
3. THE SINGLE TAX FALLS IN PROPORTION TO
BENEFITS
To perceive that the single tax would justly measure the
value of government service we have only to realize that
the mass of individuals everywhere and now, in paying for
the land they use, actually pay for government service in
proportion to what they receive. He who would enjoy the
benefits of a government must use land within its
jurisdiction. He cannot carry land from where government
is poor to where it is good; neither can he carry it from
where the benefits of good government are few or enjoyed
with difficulty to where they are many and fully enjoyed.
He must rent or buy land where the benefits of government
are available, or forego them. And unless he buys or
rents where they are greatest and most available he must
forego them in degree. Consequently, if he would work or
live where the benefits of government are available, and
does not already own land there, he will be compelled to
rent or buy at a valuation which, other things being
equal, will depend upon the value of the government
service that the site he selects enables him to enjoy. 14
Thus does he pay for the service of government in
proportion to its value to him. But he does not pay the
public which provides the service; he is required to pay
land-owners.
14. Land values are lower in all
countries of poor government than in any country of
better government, other things being equal. They are
lower in cities of poor government, other things being
equal, than in cities of better government. Land values
are lower, for example, in Juarez, on the Mexican side
of the Rio Grande, where government is bad, than in El
Paso, the neighboring city on the American side, where
government is better. They are lower in the same city
under bad government than under improved government.
When Seth Low, after a reform campaign, was elected
mayor of Brooklyn, N.Y., rents advanced before he took
the oath of office, upon the bare expectation that he
would eradicate municipal abuses. Let the city
authorities anywhere pave a street, put water through
it and sewer it, or do any of these things, and lots in
the neighborhood rise in value. Everywhere that the
"good roads" agitation of wheel men has borne fruit in
better highways, the value of adjacent land has
increased. Instances of this effect as results of
public improvements might be collected in abundance.
Every man must be able to recall some within his own
experience.
And it is perfectly reasonable that it
should be so. Land and not other property must rise in
value with desired improvements in government, because,
while any tendency on the part of other kinds of
property to rise in value is checked by greater
production, land can not be reproduced.
Imagine an utterly lawless place, where
life and property are constantly threatened by
desperadoes. He must be either a very bold man or a
very avaricious one who will build a store in such a
community and stock it with goods; but suppose such a
man should appear. His store costs him more than the
same building would cost in a civilized community;
mechanics are not plentiful in such a place, and
materials are hard to get. The building is finally
erected, however, and stocked. And now what about this
merchant's prices for goods? Competition is weak,
because there are few men who will take the chances he
has taken, and he charges all that his customers will
pay. A hundred per cent, five hundred per cent, perhaps
one or two thousand per cent profit rewards him for his
pains and risk. His goods are dear, enormously dear
— dear enough to satisfy the most contemptuous
enemy of cheapness; and if any one should wish to buy
his store that would be dear too, for the difficulties
in the way of building continue. But land is
cheap! This is the type of community in which may
be found that land, so often mentioned and so seldom
seen, which "the owners actually can't give away, you
know!"
But suppose that government improves. An
efficient administration of justice rids the place of
desperadoes, and life and property are safe. What about
prices then? It would no longer require a bold or
desperately avaricious man to engage in selling goods
in that community, and competition would set in. High
profits would soon come down. Goods would be cheap
— as cheap as anywhere in the world, the cost of
transportation considered. Builders and building
materials could be had without difficulty, and stores
would be cheap, too. But land would be dear!
Improvement in government increases the value of that,
and of that alone.
Now, the economic principle pursuant to which
land-owners are thus able to charge their fellow-citizens
for the common benefits of their common government points
to the true method of taxation. With the exception of
such other monopoly property as is analogous to land
titles, and which in the purview of the single tax is
included with land for purposes of taxation, 15 land is
the only kind of property that is increased in value by
government; and the increase of value is in proportion,
other influences aside, to the public service which its
possession secures to the occupant. Therefore, by taxing
land in proportion to its value, and exempting all other
property, kindred monopolies excepted — that is to
say, by adopting the single tax — we should be
levying taxes according to benefits.16
15. Railroad franchises, for example,
are not usually thought of as land titles, but that is
what they are. By an act of sovereign authority they
confer rights of control for transportation purposes
over narrow strips of land between terminals and along
trading points. The value of this right of way is a
land value.
16. Each occupant would pay to his
landlord the value of the public benefits in the way of
highways, schools, courts, police and fire protection,
etc., that his site enabled him to enjoy. The landlord
would pay a tax proportioned to the pecuniary benefits
conferred upon him by the public in raising and
maintaining the value of his holding. And if occupant
and owner were the same, he would pay directly
according to the value of his land for all the public
benefits he enjoyed, both intangible and pecuniary.
And in no sense would this be class taxation. Indeed,
the cry of class taxation is a rather impudent one for
owners of valuable land to raise against the single tax,
when it is considered that under existing systems of
taxation they are exempt. 17 Even the poorest and the
most degraded classes in the community, besides paying
land-owners for such public benefits as come their way,
are compelled by indirect taxation to contribute to the
support of government. But landowners as a class go free.
They enjoy the protection of the courts, and of police
and fire departments, and they have the use of schools
and the benefit of highways and other public
improvements, all in common with the most favored, and
upon the same specific terms; yet, though they go through
the form of paying taxes, and if their holdings are of
considerable value pose as "the tax-payers" on
all important occasions, they, in effect and considered
as a class, pay no taxes, because government, by
increasing the value of their land, enables them to
recover back in higher rents and higher prices more than
their taxes amount to. Enjoying the same tangible
benefits of government that others do, many of them as
individuals and all of them as a class receive in
addition a tangible pecuniary benefit which government
confers upon no other property-owners. The value of their
property is enhanced in proportion to the benefits of
government which its occupants enjoy. To tax them alone,
therefore, is not to discriminate against them; it is to
charge them for what they get.18
17. While the landholders of the City of
Washington were paying something less than two per cent
annually in taxes, a Congressional Committee
(Report of the Select Committee to Investigate Tax
Assessments in the District of Columbia, composed of
Messrs. Johnson, of Ohio, Chairman, Wadsworth, of New
York, and Washington, of Tennessee. Made to the House
of Representatives, May 24, 1892. Report No.
1469), brought out the fact that the value of
their land had been increasing at a minimum rate of ten
per cent per annum. The Washington land-owners as a
class thus appear to have received back in higher land
values, actually and potentially, about ten dollars for
every two dollars that as land-owners they paid in
taxes. If any one supposes that this condition is
peculiar to Washington let him make similar estimates
for any progressive locality, and see if the
land-owners there are not favored in like manner.
But the point is not dependent upon
increase in the capitalized value of land. If the land
yields or will yield to its owner an income in the
nature of actual or potential ground rent, then to the
extent that this actual or possible income is dependent
upon government the landlord is in effect exempt from
taxation. No matter what tax he pays on account of his
ownership of land, the public gives it back to him to
that extent.
18. Take for illustration two towns, one
of excellent government and the other of inefficient
government, but in all other respects alike. Suppose
you are hunting for a place of residence and find a
suitable site in the town of good government. For
simplicity of illustration let us suppose that the land
there is not sold outright but is let upon ground rent.
You meet the owner of the lot you have selected and ask
him his terms. He replies:
"Two hundred and fifty dollars a
year."
"Two hundred and fifty dollars a year! "
you exclaim. "Why, I can get just as good a site in
that other town for a hundred dollars a year."
"Certainly you can," he will say. "But
if you build a house there and it catches fire it will
burn down; they have no fire department. If you go out
after dark you will be 'held up' and robbed; they have
no police force. If you ride out in the spring, your
carriage will stick in the mud up to the hubs, and if
you walk you may break your legs and will be lucky if
you don t break your neck; they have no street
pavements and their sidewalks are dangerously out of
repair. When the moon doesn't shine the streets are in
darkness, for they have no street lights. The water you
need for your house you must get from a well; there is
no water supply there. Now in our town it is different.
We have a splendid fire department, and the best police
force in the world. Our streets are macadamized, and
lighted with electricity; our sidewalks are always in
first class repair; we have a water system that equals
that of New York; and in every way the public benefits
in this town are unsurpassed. It is the best governed
town in all this region. Isn't it worth a hundred and
fifty dollars a year more for a building site here than
over in that poorly governed town?"
You recognize the advantages and agree
to the terms. But when your house is built and the
assessor visits you officially, what would be the
conversation if your sense of the fitness of things
were not warped by familiarity with false systems of
taxation? Would it not be something like what
follows?
"How much do you regard this house as
worth? " asks the assessor.
"What is that to you?" you inquire.
"I am the town assessor and am about to
appraise your property for taxation."
"Am I to be taxed by this town? What
for?"
"What for?" echoes the assessor in
surprise. "What for? Is not your house protected from
fire by our magnificent fire department? Are not you
protected from robbery by the best police force in the
world? Do not you have the use of macadamized
pavements, and good sidewalks, and electric street
lights, and a first class water supply? Don't you
suppose these things cost something? And don't you
think you ought to pay your share?"
"Yes," you answer, with more or
less calmness; "I do have the benefit of these things,
and I do think that I ought to pay my share toward
supporting them. But I have already paid my share for
this year. I have paid it to the owner of this lot. He
charges me two hundred and fifty dollars a year -- one
hundred and fifty dollars more than I should pay or he
could get but for those very benefits. He has
collected my share of this year's expense of
maintaining town improvements; you go and collect from
him. If you do not, but insist upon collecting from me,
I shall be paying twice for these things, once to him
and once to you; and he won't be paying at all, but
will be making money out of them, although he derives
the same benefits from them in all other respects that
I do." ... read the book
Charles B. Fillebrown: A Catechism of Natural
Taxation, from Principles of Natural Taxation
(1917)
Q3. What is meant by economic rent?
A. Gross ground rent -- the annual site value of land --
what land, including any quality or content of the land
itself, is worth annually for use -- what the land does
or would command for use per annum if offered in open
market -- the annual value of the exclusive use in
control of a given area of land, involving the enjoyment
of those "rights and privileges thereto pertaining" which
are stipulated in every title deed, and which, enumerated
specifically, are as follows: right and ease of access
to
* water, and
* health inspection,
* sewerage,
* fire protection,
* police,
* schools,
* libraries,
* museums,
* parks,
* playgrounds,
* steam and electric railway service,
* gas and electric lighting,
* telegraph and telephone service,
* subways,
* ferries,
* churches,
* public schools,
* private schools,
* colleges,
* universities,
* public buildings --
utilities which depend for their efficiency and
economy on the character of the government; which
collectively constitute the economic and social
advantages of the land which are due to the presence and
activity of population, and are inseparable therefrom,
including the benefit of proximity to, and command of,
facilities for commerce and communication with the world
-- an artificial value created primarily through public
expenditure of taxes. For the sake of brevity, the
substance of this definition may be conveniently
expressed as the value of "proximity." It is ordinarily
measured by interest on investment plus taxes.
... read
the whole article
Bill Batt: The
Nexus of Transportation, Economic Rent, and Land
Use
Correcting Distortions by
Pricing: Increasing the Collection of Land
Rent
Recovering the economic rent from urban parcels
helps people to appreciate the true costs of the
transportation versus location trade-off. It brings the
carrying costs of site choices back to the present time
and makes them comparable with travel choices. The
payment of site rent becomes an operating cost. The other
corrective policy needed is to raise transportation costs
to a level commensurate with their full value as private
goods. Transportation user fees, in the form of motor
fuel taxes, green taxes, congestion fees, and
administrative costs (for the administration of drivers'
licenses and registration fees) could easily provide the
needed price corrections to bring into balance marginal
transportation costs and land rent collection. Doing so
would equilibrate choices between people living and
working in high rent urban centers and those in
peripheral low rent (but higher travel cost)
locales.
Figure 2 shows how a tax on land value (or
alternatively the tax on land rent) coupled with the
proper design of transportation fees can equilibrate the
competitive advantage of markets in urban areas relative
to suburbs, thereby reducing, and perhaps even reversing,
the centrifugal forces of sprawl development. The land
tax cannot alone redress the problem, especially so long
as such inordinate social subsidies are granted to
private motor vehicle transportation services. Nor can
transportation fees, raised to a level fully commensurate
with the social and private costs they incur, alone
ensure that the price of locations will be matched. But
to the extent that both are assessed, they reach far
toward correcting this disequilibrium. One could even
argue that all site rent should be recaptured by society
and that all transportation costs that are identifiable
as consumption of private goods should be priced
accordingly. Some advocates even suggest that doing so
will not only foster economic efficient behavior but also
provide sufficient revenue for a citizen's dividend
consistent with economic justice....
read the whole
article
Maurie Fabrikant: An Open Letter to
Wayne Swan
The "Great Australian Dream"
now - as in preceding years - has been to own your own
home. From their earliest years of adulthood, most
citizens have attempted to purchase "a roof over their
head." It used to be - no more than two human generations
ago - "a three-bedroom weatherboard - or brick veneer, if
you could afford it! - on a quarter-acre block in the
suburbs." Most citizens - then - succeeded in realising
that dream; at least they started repaying a loan that
was large compared with their earnings. Nowadays, it's
quite impossible for most. Why? Simply because land-price
has escalated out of the reach of most. Allow me to give
you a specific instance:- ...
As you can very clearly see, it now costs couples
- or singles - a great deal more to own a residence.
Naturally, if they don't own their own residence, they
must
- pay rent to somebody else or
- live in a caravan park or
- share a home with relatives or friends
or
- have no place to call
"home".
None of these alternatives lead
to a high quality lifestyle and undoubtedly are potent
factors in separation and divorce and reliance on drug
abuse which, itself, leads to anti-social - even criminal
- behaviour. We also know to our great regret that
these aberrations are becoming increasingly prevalent. So
is there a solution? And if so, what is it?
In my opinion, there certainly is a solution ...
but, seemingly, very few want to know it. Judging by your
article, I think you do. Here it is: ...
Modern conventional wisdom is
that increasing land price signifies a healthy economy.
Exactly the reverse is true! Increasing land price
demonstrates that much money is being invested in real
estate and that necessarily means that less money is
being invested in productive ventures. Increasing land
price causes increasing rents ... because the land owner
must derive sufficient income to pay the interest charged
on the loan needed to buy the land and its improvements.
This makes it increasingly difficult for businesses to
trade profitably ... especially when there is a plethora
of complicated taxes that cause extremely high compliance
costs. It's no wonder that more and more goods are now
imported as local manufacturers choose to close their
operations. In many places in Australia, land lies
relatively idle. For example, in Melbourne's CBD, several
large blocks have been idle for years and in the suburbs,
shops remain empty for months, even years. Yet
government-released figures on unemployment - the reality
may well be much worse! - admit that unemployment exceeds
6%. The old adage, "Idle lands cause idle hands" is
clearly demonstrated in Australia ... and
elsewhere.
The only possible "winners" in
this "game" are those who presently own land; the more
they own, the more they have the potential to "win". Land
owners enjoy enormous increase in the price of land they
own simply because they were able to purchase it when its
price was comparatively low. They do not - in their role
as owners - contribute in any way to the prosperity of
the nation. Indeed, because they grow wealthier without
producing, they are, in fact, parasites! That sounds
incredible but it is true nonetheless. How so? Simply
because those owners receive part of the wealth earned by
all citizens; at least some of that wealth is used to
push up land prices but only owners enjoy those increased
prices. Tenants certainly do not! All who labour - and
this includes land owners who perform labour! - are
thereby effectively robbed of some of their earnings.
(Please note that I do not blame landowners personally;
most would - I'm certain - be horrified to think that
they are parasites. The fault
lies in the parliamentary enactments that permit such a
situation to prevail.)
Difficult as the situation is
now, it will be worse still in another
two human generations' time. How
so? Because the same forces that have been exerted in the
past continue unabated. In fact, these forces appear to
be intensifying! Taxation is continuing to escalate as
pressure groups clamour ever louder for financial
assistance. The average rate at which personal income tax
is levied is increasing - even though the maximum rate
levied is falling - and sales taxes and the like are
being applied to a widening range of goods and services.
The wealthy continue to derive benefit from the
tax-minimisation experts they employ - because they save
more tax than they pay to those experts - leaving the
relatively poorly-paid employees to carry most of the
burden. Unless, of course, steps are taken to change
these tendencies, Australia will become an increasingly
unpleasant country in which to live. That's definitely
not the future I want for my 3 children and 7
grandchildren. And I'm sure you don't,
either!
The solution to this conundrum
is, perhaps amazingly, incredibly simple; namely, require
all owners of land - in fact, all natural resources,
including intangibles such as broadcast bands, to pay to
all Australians, via the government, an annual rental in
exchange for exclusive ownership rights to those natural
resources. What could be fairer? If a citizen has exclusive ownership
rights to a natural resource, that obviously means that
all others have no rights to it whatsoever. Therefore,
that citizen must pay compensation - in the form of a
periodic rent - to all others. Now
that's a perfect manifestation of "user pays". How
big is this periodic rent? That's simply answered, too.
It's what the citizens, generally, think that natural
resource is worth! And that's easily - and accurately -
determined by valuers, individuals who have great
experience because they simply note the prices at which
similar natural resources in the vicinity - both in space
and in time - are sold then use those prices to predict
that of a similar resource.
This would constitute real tax reform and - when
implemented - would obviate the need for income taxes and
sales taxes. How is this? When a continuing rent is
charged for ownership rights to a natural resource, that
natural resource will have little or no purchase price.
Setting up a business or residence will
be much cheaper first up as only the improvements must be
paid for initially. Money that presently must be
borrowed to pay for access to natural resources will
become available for productive purposes. Because rents
will be payable on all natural resources that are
privately owned - whether or not they are in use - those
natural resources will become used or will return to the
nation as public land. Speculation in natural resources
will be immediately terminated thus eliminating a major
factor in escalating price. The converse of the old adage
quoted earlier is apposite:- Far less
idle land will translate into far fewer idle hands!
That will translate into a
reduced need for social security
expenditure. Additionally, lower levels of
unemployment will cause reduced anti-social and criminal
activity with consequent savings in law enforcement,
punishment and rehabilitation. And elimination of most of
our taxation regulations will cause compliance costs to
all but disappear. The brakes that presently retard
Australia's productivity will not merely be released;
they will be discarded! ... read the entire
article
Henry George: The Condition of Labor
— An Open Letter to Pope Leo XIII in response to
Rerum Novarum (1891)
You assume that the labor question is a question
between wage-workers and their employers. But working for
wages is not the primary or exclusive occupation of
labor. Primarily men work for themselves without the
intervention of an employer. And the primary source of
wages is in the earnings of labor, the man who works for
himself and consumes his own products receiving his wages
in the fruits of his labor. Are not fishermen, boatmen,
cab-drivers, peddlers, working farmers — all, in
short, of the many workers who get their wages directly
by the sale of their services or products without the
medium of an employer, as much laborers as those who work
for the specific wages of an employer? In your
consideration of remedies you do not seem even to have
thought of them. Yet in reality the laborers who work for
themselves are the first to be considered, since what men
will be willing to accept from employers depends
manifestly on what they can get by working for
themselves.
You assume that all employers are rich men, who might
raise wages much higher were they not so grasping. But is
it not the fact that the great majority of employers are
in reality as much pressed by competition as their
workmen, many of them constantly on the verge of failure?
Such employers could not possibly raise the wages they
pay, however they might wish to, unless all others were
compelled to do so.
You assume that there are in the natural order two
classes, the rich and the poor, and that laborers
naturally belong to the poor.
It is true as you say that there are differences in
capacity, in diligence, in health and in strength, that
may produce differences in fortune. These, however, are
not the differences that divide men into rich and poor.
The natural differences in powers and aptitudes are
certainly not greater than are natural differences in
stature. But while it is only by selecting giants and
dwarfs that we can find men twice as tall as others, yet
in the difference between rich and poor that exists today
we find some men richer than other men by the
thousandfold and the millionfold.
Nowhere do these differences between wealth and
poverty coincide with differences in individual powers
and aptitudes. The real difference between rich and poor
is the difference between those who hold the tollgates
and those who pay toll; between tribute-receivers and
tribute-yielders. ... read the whole
letter
Mason Gaffney: Red-Light Taxes and
Green-Light Taxes
The need for user
charges
My fellow Green-lighters have a lot to learn
about Red Light Taxes and charges, too. Much of what all
of us need to learn has been worked out by those
often-awful but sometimes-useful economists, under the
name of "marginal-cost pricing." On private land, where
the owner controls access, there is little need for user
charges (except for externalities). The owner's
self-interest takes care of finding the optimal intensity
of use. On public land, however, with unrestricted
access, it is another matter. Witness, for example, the
crowding of Oxford sidewalks relative to the
undercrowding of private and University lands abutting
them.
On public lands, when a bridge is new,
and oversized for its traffic, no toll should be charged:
circumstances call instead for a Green Light Tax on the
benefited lands, to hasten their settlement. When traffic
queues up, however, it is time to charge a toll (and/or to
widen the bridge).
Likewise, when demand for water
exceeds supply, it is time to price it and charge people
for withdrawing it from Nature. The history of irrigation
in California is instructive. During the Populist and
Progressive eras Californians developed the legal framework
for what we call Irrigation Districts, to divert,
store and distribute water. They raised funds by taxing
land; most of them delivered water free of variable cost.
Likewise, no one charged them for taking our water from our
rivers. There was ample water, so it seemed, running to
waste, or into swamps. The result, from 1900-30, was to
convert California from pasture and wasteland to the #1
farm state in America. It was a Georgist object lesson, and
a brilliant success story. Quoth Albert Henley, a prominent
attorney,
"The discovery of the legal formula of these
organizations was of infinitely greater value to
California than the discovery of gold a generation
before. They are an extraordinarily potent engine for the
creation of wealth."
A worm in the apple was waste of
water. The same policy that promoted close economy and
rapid conversion of land also tolerated waste of water, and
even subsidized it by basing the quantity of rival water
claims on histories of use - what economists now call
"rent-seeking." It was once a minor problem, but times
change, and "circumstances alter cases." Today we are stuck
with much of our water, a limiting natural resource, frozen
in lower uses and withheld from higher ones - exactly what
Georgist policy is supposed to prevent. The solution,
clearly, is for the State to charge each Irrigation
District (and other diverters) per unit of water they take,
and reallocate the great surpluses they would immediately
stop taking.
Traditional "Green Light" Georgists need to
introspect deeply over this case, and many like it, and
master the theory and practice of marginal-cost pricing
as developed so ably by closet Georgist economists like
Harold Hotelling and William Vickrey. Marginal-cost
pricing is a flexible, adaptable theory that allows for
both Green Light and Red Light taxes, each in the its
season. Using this basic, simple tool of economic
analysis, Red Light and Green Light champions can compose
their differences and move ahead in triumphant
unity. ... read
the whole article
Bill Batt: Stemming
Sprawl: The Fiscal Approach
We do an awful lot of driving just to do what we need
to do. This is because transportation engineers and land
use planners have confused two fundamental concepts:
access and mobility.
By confusing these two principles, we spend an
inordinate amount of money on transportation services,
most of it on roads and highways. One 1993 study
calculated that the total costs of motor vehicle
transportation to our society equal approximately a
fourth of our gross domestic product (GDP).[3] The study
concluded that "when the full range of costs of
transportation are tallied, passenger ground
transportation costs the American public a total of $1.2
to $1.6 trillion each year. Just the costs of automobile
crashes represents a figure equal to 8 percent of the
American GDP.[4] Japan, by way
of comparison, spends an estimated 10.4 percent to
satisfy all its transportation requirements, although the
figure might be a bit low because not all externalities
are included in the calculation.[5] Road user fees
in 1991 totaled only about $33 billion, whereas the true
costs to society were ten times that;[6] put another
way, drivers pay only 10 percent of the true costs of
their motor vehicle use.[7] The balance is
paid by society, effectively subsidizing highway use by
paying for all but the marginal out-of-pocket operating
costs. ...
Stemming Sprawl: Pricing Measures for
Transportation
From the foregoing, it is clear that insofar as the
causes of sprawl development are economic, the solution
needs to be economic as well. The equilibrium of forces
can be restored in two ways:
1) by charging the true marginal costs of motor
vehicle transportation to users and
2) by recovering the economic rent from urban site
owners that is really the socially created value.
It is easy to distinguish five elements of
transportation service cost: capital investment,
maintenance costs, regulation costs, environmental
externalities, and congestion costs. Each of these calls
for a different treatment with respect to revenue design.
Capital costs are best recovered by recapturing the land
rent proximate to the highway corridors. This is socially
created value, which is better used to honor debt service
of infrastructure investment than allowing it to be
retained as windfall gains by titleholders to property
close by. User fees, most aptly linked to the purchase of
motor fuel and tire wear, serve as a proxy for the use of
the roads and can be designed to be commensurate with
use. As the wear and tear of roads as well as police
patrol, snow and ice control, and signaling all involve
operating and maintenance costs, such charges are easily
linked with benefits received. In the future, still more
accurate systems of service charges are likely to appear:
Singapore, Hong Kong, and New Zealand are already reliant
on electronic devices that record road use by time,
place, and vehicle weight.
Ensuring the safety of drivers and vehicles through
licenses, registrations, and inspections is most
appropriately financed by fees commensurate with the
costs of their administration. This way, if a vehicle is
used but seldom, it is charged on the basis of its
identification rather than assuming any projected level
of use. Environmental externalities such as pollution
costs can be linked to the polluting source, such as
diesel fuel and gasoline consumption, to the full extent
necessary to equilibrate air quality and other
environmental ambiences. Congestion costs, the last of
the major components of a pricing design for highway use,
are partially paid for by the time loss of those caught
in traffic. The costs of time lost due to highway
congestion are enormous: In 2000, the average driver
spent 62 hours sitting in traffic at a nationwide cost of
$68 billion in gas and time lost In Los Angeles, the
average driver spent 136 hours stalled in traffic at an
average cost of $2,510.[33] Commuting
times were also 20 percent longer than they were a decade
ago, about 22 minutes one way nationally on average but
as high as 32 minutes on average in New York.[34] But not all
people's time is valued equally, and people themselves
value their time differently at different times, and it
is unfair to require people to impose their congestion on
others. Therefore, congestion pricing, being explored in
several urban regions, provides a rationing of limited
highway space. In a sense, that payment for space usage,
in time or money, is a form of land rent. ... read the whole article
Fred Foldvary: The Rent, the Whole Rent, and
Nothing but the Rent
The use of rent for public revenues therefore has
no excess burden, no burden on society or the economy.
Taxes on income, goods, and transactions do have an
excess burden, since by raising the price and reducing
the quantity of goods, resources do not get allocated to
where the people most want them. Taxes on labor and goods
raise prices, while rent-based payments do not affect the
rent, and they lower the price of land rather than raise
it.
Rent is therefore the ideal
source of general public and community revenue.
Tax reform should therefore shift to rent as the primary
source of general funds.Pollution
charges can supplement the rent, and indeed can be
considered a rental charge for using and abusing the
atmosphere, land, soil, and other forms of land.
There could also be user fees for services specific to
users, fines for violating traffic rules, and profits
from enterprises.
The economic rent from minerals,
water, and oil would be natural resource royalties that
could be paid by bidding for the rights to extract, from
payments based on the amount of mining, and the profits
from the operations, depending on the
circumstances. ... Read the
whole article
Nic Tideman: Using Tax Policy to
Promote Urban Growth
The efficiency that is entailed in using the rent
of land to finance public activities applies to certain
other sources of public revenue as well:
1. Charges on any publicly granted privileges,
such as the exclusive right to use a portion of the
frequency spectrum for radio and TV broadcasts.
2. Payments for extractions of natural
resources. Such payments should be set at levels that
yield the greatest possible revenue of the resources,
in present value terms.
3. Taxes on pollution. Every individual or
enterprise that pollutes the air, water or ground
should be required to pay the estimated cost of the
pollution it generates. The effect of pollution on the
rental value of surrounding land is one possible
measure of its cost.
4. Taxes on any other activities that reduce
the rental value of surrounding land.
5. Taxes on activities such as driving or
parking in crowded streets, where one person's
activities reduce opportunities for others. The
administration of such charges may be so expensive that
it is not worth implementing them, but if the
administration can be handled sufficiently cheaply,
these charges are efficient to the extent that they
only charge people for costs imposed on
others.
6. Taxes on activities, such as the
consumption of alcohol, which impose costs on others
(e.g., higher traffic fatalities).
7. Charges for local public services, such as
water, electricity, sewer connections, etc. It is not
generally desirable to make every service completely
self-financing. Rather, what is desirable is that each
user be required to pay the marginal cost of the
service he receives. Extensions of service networks are
efficient when they increase publicly collected land
rents by enough to cover the costs not covered by user
charges.
8. A self-assessed tax on permanent
improvements to land, at a very low rate (perhaps 1/10
of 1% per year). With a self-assessed tax, each
possessor of land names a price at which he would be
willing to part with the land he possesses (and any
immovable improvements). He pays a tax proportional to
the value he names, and anyone who wishes to may take
over possession at that price. The value of such a tax
is that it makes it much easier to assemble land for
redevelopment, and to identify appropriate compensation
when land is taken for public purposes.
All of the above taxes are
positively beneficial and should be collected even if the
revenue is not needed for public purposes. Any excess can
be returned to the population on an equal per capita
basis. If these attractive sources of revenue do
not suffice to finance necessary public expenditures,
then the least damaging additional tax would probably be
a "poll tax," a uniform charge on all residents. If some
residents are regarded to be incapable of paying such a
tax, then the next most efficient tax is a proportional
tax on income up to some specified amount. Then there is
no disincentive effect for all persons who reach the tax
limit. The next most efficient tax is a proportional tax
on all income.
It is important not to tax the
profits of corporations. Capital moves from where
it is taxed to where it is not, until the same rate of
return is earned everywhere. If the city refrains from
taxing corporations they will invest more in St.
Petersburg. Wages will be higher, and the rent of land,
collected by the government, will be higher. The least
damaging tax on corporations is one that provides a
complete write-off of investments, with a carry-over of
tax credits to future years. Such a tax has the effect of
making the government a partner in all new investments.
With such a tax the government provides, through tax
credits, the same share of costs that it later receives
in revenues. However, the tax does diminish the incentive
for entrepreneurial activity, and it raises no revenue
when investment is expanding rapidly. Furthermore, the
efficiency of such a tax requires that everyone believe
that the tax rate will never change. Thus it is best not
to tax the profits of corporations at all. If the people
of St. Petersburg want to share in the profits of
corporations, then they should invest directly in the
corporations, either privately or publicly. The residents
of St. Petersburg would be best served by refraining from
taxing the profits of corporations. Creating a place
where profits are not taxed can be expected to attract so
much capital that the resulting rises in wages and in
government-collected rents will more than offset what
might have been collected by taxing profits.
The taxes that promote urban growth have at
least one of two features.
- The first feature that a growth-promoting
tax can have is that it can serve to allocate a
naturally occurring resource among competing potential
users. Charges for the use of land, for the use of the
frequency spectrum and for depleting natural resources
share this feature.
- The second feature that a growth-promoting
tax can have is that of being a charge for the costs
imposed on the city by the person who pays the tax.
This feature is shared by taxes on pollution, taxes on
other activities that reduce the value of surrounding
land, taxes on imposing congestion and other costs on
other residents of the city, charges for the marginal
cost of publicly provided services, and a self-assessed
tax on property, reflecting the hindrance to future
growth represented by existing
development.
A city that confines itself to these taxes
can expect to attract capital rapidly, and therefore to
experience rapid growth, raising the wages of its
citizens and the publicly-collected rent of its
land. ... Read
the whole article
Nic Tideman:
Land Taxation and Efficient Land Speculation
Indirect Effects of Taxing Land
One consequence of levying additional taxes on land is
that it becomes possible to lower taxes on other things.
One of the things most likely to be taxed less when land
is taxed more is improvements. Lowering taxes on
improvements makes the present value of land development
very much less costly, and hence is likely to accelerate
development although it would be possible to construct
cases in which the effect of lowering taxes on
improvements would be to postpone development. Whether it
retards or accelerates development, the lowering of taxes
on improvements results in more intensive development
when development occurs. The possibility of promoting
more intensive development by reducing or eliminating
taxes on improvements is an important beneficial effect
of an increase in taxes on land.
A second consequence of levying additional taxes on
land is that it becomes possible to price public services
more efficiently. Services to land such as sewers, water
and electricity are used most effectively when they are
priced at marginal cost. The costs of these services,
however, are generally such that the sum of marginal
costs will not cover total costs. Land taxes have the
potential to provide a fund to cover the difference
between total costs and the sum of marginal costs. If
land taxes are so used, the reductions in the costs of
using services that complement development will promote
more efficient development. ...
read the whole article
Nic Tideman:
The Morality of Taxation: The Local Case
Consider first the question of adequacy of revenue.
There is a theorem in economics, known as the Henry George Theorem, that addresses this
question (Arnott and Stiglitz, 1979). One of the simpler
versions of this theorem is:
If the following three conditions are
met:
1. Public expenditures provide benefits only over a
limited area,
2. People can move costlessly, and
3. The number of persons who value a public service
as highly as anyone does exceeds the number of
persons who can live in the area where the service
provides benefits,
then for any public service that is worth at least as
much as it costs to those who receive it, the increase
in the rental value of land that results from providing
the service exceeds the net cost of the service.
The Henry George Theorem is true because people who
can move costlessly will bid up the rental value of land
to reflect the value of public services that are not
available elsewhere. The assumption that the number of
bidders exceeds the number of people who can benefit from
the public service guarantees that the upward movement of
rents will not end until all the benefits of the public
service are reflected in these rents. If some people who
receive a public service value it more highly than
others, then they will receive a surplus in addition to
the rent they pay for land, and some worthwhile
increments of public services will not add quite enough
to rent to pay for themselves (Tideman 1993). But rent
increments will go a very long way toward paying for
worthwhile local public services.
With some local public services, such as weather
reports that are broadcasted by radio at a specified
wattage, there is no social cost of having another person
within the reception area use the service. With others,
such as distribution of water, the extra cost of one
additional user will be noticeable, but still a
relatively small fraction of the average cost of the
service. For public services to provide the greatest
possible net value, users must be charged the costs of
additional use (what economists call marginal cost). If
they are charged less than marginal cost, self-interest
will motivate them to use the service wastefully. And if
they are charged more than marginal cost, self-interest
will motivate them to economize inefficiently on the
service.
Thus local public services are financed efficiently
when users are required to pay marginal costs, and the
component of total cost that is not covered by marginal
cost charges is financed by levies on land that collect
the increases in rental value of land that result from
provision of the service. If all citizens in a
locality valued the service equally, then every increment
in the level of the service that was worthwhile would
have a cost that was less than or equal to the sum of the
revenue that could be raised from charges for use equal
to marginal cost and the increase in the rental value of
land in the community that resulted from the availability
of the service. When people value the service
differently, the increase in the rental value of land
that results from the provision of a service will be less
than the value of the service to those who receive it. By
a criterion of maximizing the real incomes of residents,
the best outcome that covers the full cost of a service
will involve a level of service somewhat lower than that
for which marginal cost is equal to the sum of marginal
benefits, along with charges that exceed somewhat the
marginal cost of providing the service to additional
persons. Still, in general, the combination of
user fees approximately equal to marginal cost and taxes
on land to finance the remainder of costs is capable of
providing financing for local public services that is
adequate and reasonably efficient.
Next consider fairness. The fairness of such
financing is the fairness of incremental decisions in an
environment in which the initial allocation is fair. (It
does not provide special opportunities for disadvantaged
persons. They would need to be provided for by insurance
that operated independently of the provision of public
goods.) A person who is treated fairly in the absence of
public goods cannot reasonably complain about being
required to pay for a service according to its marginal
cost, or about have to pay the value that is added to his
land by the availability of a public service. ...
read the whole article
Frank Stilwell and Kirrily Jordan: The Political Economy of Land:
Putting Henry George in His Place
What about the relevance of Georgist ideas to current
concerns with environmental quality and ecological
sustainability? Here too there is a strong claim to
consider. Interest in Georgism has been reinvigorated in
recent years by the need to develop public policies that
reflect the nature of land as a finite natural resource.
From a ‘green’ perspective, land tax is a
useful tool in discouraging the excessive and wasteful
use of land. That is, the prospect of paying a high rate
of land tax can be expected to discourage people from
purchasing more land than they need directly for their
own purposes. It accords with the principle that people
should be taxed according to their use of scarce
environmental assets.
This ‘ecological take’ on Georgism is
particularly powerful at a time of intensifying global
environmental problems and recognition of the need for
remedial policy responses. It requires creative extension
of Georgist principles because the limitation of
George’s own analysis in this context is its
primary focus on land. A range of other natural resources
needs to be considered, linking up with the broader
concerns of modern environmentalists such as Herman Daly
(see, for example, Daly and Cobb, 1990). Hence, land tax
should be seen as an adjunct to taxes on the use of other
scarce environmental assets, including mineral, forestry
and fishing stocks, and also bandwidth for radio and
telecommunications, for example (Stilwell, 2002:
316-317). It should also be seen as a corollary to other
taxes that discourage environmental damage, including
resource rental taxes, carbon taxes and fuel excises.
The case for these environmental taxes need not
necessarily rest on Georgist principles, of course, but
Georgism can claim to provide a unifying analytical
framework. A common feature of ‘environmental
taxes’ is that they are all targeted, like land
tax, at reducing the scope for profiting from the private
appropriation of natural resources, and thereby
restricting the profligate use of those resources.
A tension remains, reflecting the Georgist orientation
towards taxes rather than more directly regulatory
interventions. Whether the use of the price mechanism in
this ‘environmental fine tuning’ is
sufficient for dealing with pervasive environment threats
is a moot point. The nature and severity of environmental
stresses is such that more directly proscriptive
environmental policies are commonly needed to protect
natural resources. The creation and maintenance of
national parks, for example, constitutes a necessary
direct regulation of land-use: the market, even when
modified by taxes, cannot absolutely guarantee the
conservation of such crucial assets. In other words,
protection of ‘natural capital’ may commonly
require regulation as well as taxation. ... read the whole
article
|
To share this page with a friend:
right click, choose "send," and add your
comments.
|
|
Red links have not been
visited; .
Green links are pages you've seen
|
Essential Documents pertinent
to this theme:
|
|