Distribution of Wealth
This phrase is commonly used to describe how the
ownership of specific kinds of assets falls across a
population. (For example, the Federal Reserve Board's
triennial Survey of Consumer Finances tells us that the
top 1% of the US households own 33.4% of Net Worth in
2004, up from 30.1% in 1989; the bottom 90% of us hold
30.5%, down from 32.8% in 1989. Detail available here.)
But for the purposes of wealthandwant.com,
"distribution of wealth" also has to do with who gets
what: what share of the pie does labor get? What
share of the pie does the owner of the land get? And that
leads to the question of what it is legitimate to tap
— to tax — in order to provide for the
revenue needs of the community.
If there is a kind of income which is truly
"unearned," isn't that a legitimate tax base?
Henry George: Political
Dangers (Chapter 2 of Social
Problems, 1883)
[12] Beneath all political
problems lies the social problem of the distribution of
wealth. This our people do not generally recognize, and
they listen to quacks who propose to cure the symptoms
without touching the disease. "Let us elect good men to
office," say the quacks. Yes; let us catch little birds
by sprinkling salt on their tails! ... read the
entire essay
Louis Post: Outlines of Louis F. Post's
Lectures, with Illustrative Notes and Charts (1894)
3. THE DISTRIBUTION OF
WEALTH
The chart on the following page displays the
fundamental principle of Production, which we considered
at the beginning, and also the fundamental principle of
Distribution, which is yet to be considered. In the
development of the latter will be found the explanation
of the divorce in the civilized state of Labor from Land:
[chart]
This chart reminds us that Labor (human exertion), by
application to Land (natural materials and forces
external to man), produces Wealth (the generic term for
all those things that tend to satisfy the material Wants
of man), and so tends to abolish poverty. No man's
poverty can be abolished in any other way, unless it be
by gifts, or vulgar robbery, or legalized spoils.
The chart shows also that Wealth distributes
ultimately in Wages 82 (a fund made up of the aggregate
of the earnings of individual laborers), which
corresponds to Labor; and Rent 83 (a fund made up of the
aggregate premiums for specially desirable locations),
which corresponds to Land.84
82. "What is paid for labor of any kind
is called wages. We are apt to speak of the payment
given to the common day laborer only as wages; and we
give finer names to the payments which are made for
some other kinds of services. Thus we speak of the
doctor's or the lawyer's fee; of the judge's salary; of
the teacher's income; of the merchant's profit; of the
banker's interest, and of the professor's emoluments.
They are all in reality only payments for labor of
different kinds, or for different results of labor,
— that is, they are all wages." — Dick's
Outlines, p. 23
"Wages is what goes to pay for all the
trouble of labor." — Jevons's Primer, sec. 39
"His [the manager's] share is called the
wages of superintendence, and although usually much
larger than the share of a common laborer, it is really
wages of the same nature." — Id., sec. 41.
"The common meaning of the word wages is
the compensation paid to a hired person for manual
labor. But in political economy the word wages has a
much wider meaning, and includes all returns for
exertion. For, as political economists explain, the
three agents or factors in production are land, labor,
and capital, and that part of the produce which goes to
the second of these factors is styled by them wages. .
. It is important to keep this in mind. For in the
standard economic works this sense of the term wages is
recognized with greater or less clearness only to be
subsequently ignored." — Progress and Poverty,
book i, ck. ii.
83. Rent "is what is paid for the use of
a natural agent, whether land, or beds of minerals, or
rivers, or lakes. The rent of a house or factory is,
therefore, not all rent in our meaning of the word."
— Jevons's Primer, sec. 40.
"The term rent in its economic sense . .
. differs in meaning from the word rent as commonly
used. In some respects this economic meaning is
narrower than the common meaning; in other respects it
is wider.
"It is narrower in this: In common
speech, we apply the word rent to payments for the use
of buildings, machinery, fixtures, etc., as well as to
payments for the use of land or other natural
capabilities; and in speaking of the rent of a house or
the rent of a farm, we do not separate the price for
the use of the improvements from the price for the use
of the bare land. But in the economic meaning of rent,
payments for the use of any of the products of human
exertion are excluded, and of the lumped payments for
the use of houses, farms, etc., only that part is rent
which constitutes the consideration for the use of the
land — that part paid for the use of buildings or
other improvements being properly interest, as it is a
consideration for the use of capital.
"It is wider in this: In common speech we
only speak of rent when owner and user are distinct
persons. But in the economic sense there is also rent
where the same person is both owner and user. Where
owner and user are thus the same person, whatever part
of his income he might obtain by letting the land to
another is rent, while the return for his labor and
capital are that part of his income which they would
yield him did he hire instead of owning the land. Rent
is also expressed in a selling price. When land is
purchased, the payment which is made for the ownership,
or right to perpetual use, is rent commuted or
capitalized. If I buy land for a small price and hold
it until I can sell it for a large price, I have become
rich, not by wages for my labor or by interest upon my
capital, but by the increase of rent.
"Rent, in short, is the share in the
wealth produced which the exclusive right to the use of
natural capabilities gives to the owner. Wherever land
has an exchange value there is rent in the economic
meaning of the term. Wherever land having a value is
used, either by owner or hirer, there is rent actual;
wherever it is not used, but still has a value, there
is rent potential. It is this capacity of yielding rent
which gives value to land. Until its ownership will
confer some advantage, land has no value." —
Progress and Poverty, book iii, chap ii
84. "The primary division of wealth in
distribution is dual, not tripartite. Capital is but a
form of labor, and its distinction from labor is in
reality but a subdivision, just as the division of
labor into skilled and unskilled would be. In our
examination we have reached the same point as would
have been attained had we simply treated capital as a
form of labor, and sought the law which divides the
produce between rent and wages; that is to say, between
the possessors of the two factors, natural substances
and powers, and human exertion — which two
factors by their union produce all wealth." —
Progress and Poverty, book iii, ch. v.
Care must be taken not to confuse the
hire of a house, commonly and legally termed "rent,"
with economic Rent. House rent is really Wages; it is
compensation for the labor of house building. But
economic Rent is not compensation for anything; it is
simply the premiums for advantages of location. ...
This illustrates the elementary principle of
Distribution, that Wages fall and Rent rises as demand
for land forces labor to land of lower productiveness.90
The principle may be more graphically illustrated by
supposing that demand for spaces in the chart advances so
far as to include all the closed spaces, except part of
the poorest one. Thus: [chart]
We now find that all Wages have fallen to the level of
Wages on the poorest land that yields anything to the
given unit of labor force; while the Rent of all but that
has, at the expense of Wages, risen in proportion to its
superior productiveness.91
91. The labor that was forced to the
poorest lands would continually bid for the
opportunities that the better lands offered, until an
equilibrium was reached at the point shown in the
preceding chart, where the given expenditure of labor
is as well compensated in one place as in another.
If laborer and land-owner be different
persons, the laborer receives what is distinguished as
Wages, and the land-owner what is distinguished as
Rent. If the same person, he receives Wages as laborer
and Rent as land-owner.
Reflection will convince us that this must be so.
Wages for a given expenditure of labor force are no more
anywhere, for any length of time, all things considered,
than the same expenditure of labor force will produce
from the best land to be had for nothing. Rent absorbs
the difference.92
92. But we must not jump to the
conclusion that there is any essential wrong in Rent.
Rent is nature's method of measuring the value of the
differences in natural opportunity which different
laborers, owing to variations in land, are obliged to
accept. And, what in practice is more important, it is
nature's method of measuring the value to each
individual of those advantages which consist in
accumulations of common knowledge, in co-operative
effort, in good government, in a word, in the benefits
that society as a whole confers as distinguished from
those which each individual earns. The question is not
one of the rightfulness or the wrongfulness of Rent.
Personal freedom necessitates Rent, for it necessitates
the private possession of land, and private possession
of land makes Rent inevitable. Nothing short of
communism could abolish it. The real question is, What
shall society do with Rent? Shall it give it to
individuals, or use it for common purposes?
"Were there only one man on earth, he
would have a right to the use of the whole earth.
"When there is more than one man on
earth, the right to the use of land that any one of
them would have, were he alone, is not abrogated; it is
only limited. . . It has become by reason of this
limitation, not an absolute right to use any part of
the earth, but (1) an absolute right to use any part of
the earth as to which his use does not conflict with
the equal rights of others (i. e., which no one else
wants to use at the same time), and (2) a co-equal
right to the use of any part of the earth which he and
others may want to use at the same time." —
Perplexed Philosopher, p. 45.
It is in adjustment of this co-equal
right that rent occurs.
b. Normal Effect of Social Progress upon
Wages and Rent
In the foregoing charts the effect of social growth is
ignored, it being assumed that the given expenditure of
labor force does not become more productive.93 Let us now
try to illustrate that effect, upon the supposition that
social growth increases the productive power of the given
expenditure of labor force as applied to the first closed
space, to 100; as applied to the second, to 50; as
applied to the third, to 10; as applied to the fourth, to
3, and as applied to the open space, to 1. 94 If there
were no increased demand for land the chart would then be
like this: [chart]
93. "The effect of increasing population
upon the distribution of wealth is to increase rent ..
. in two ways: First, By lowering the margin of
cultivation. Second, By bringing out in land special
capabilities otherwise latent, and by attaching special
capabilities to particular lands.
"I am disposed to think that the latter
mode, to which little attention has been given by
political economists, is really the more important."
— Progress and Poverty, book iv, ch. iii.
"When we have inquired what it is that
marks off land from those material things which we
regard as products of the land, we shall find that the
fundamental attribute of land is its extension. The
right to use a piece of land gives command over a
certain space — a certain part of the earth's
surface. The area of the earth is fixed; the geometric
relations in which any particular part of it stands to
other parts are fixed. Man has no control over them;
they are wholly unaffected by demand; they have no cost
of production; there is no supply price at which they
can be produced.
"The use of a certain area of the earth's
surface is a primary condition of anything that man can
do; it gives him room for his own actions, with the
enjoyment of the heat and the light, the air and the
rain which nature assigns to that area; and it
determines his distance from, and in great measure his
relations to, other things and other persons. We shall
find that it is this property of land, which, though as
yet insufficient prominence has been given to it, is
the ultimate cause of the distinction which all writers
are compelled to make between land and other things."
— Marshall's Prin., book iv, ch. ii, sec. i.
94. Of course social growth does not go
on in this regular way; the charts are merely
illustrative. They are intended to illustrate the
universal fact that as any land becomes a center of
trade or other social relationship its value rises.
Though Rent is now increased, so are Wages. Both
benefit by social growth. But if we consider the fact
that increase in the productive power of labor increases
demand for land we shall see that the tendency of Wages
(as a proportion of product if not as an absolute
quantity) is downward, while that of Rent is upward. 95
And this conclusion is confirmed by observation. 96
95. "Perhaps it may be well to remind the
reader, before closing this chapter, of what has been
before stated — that I am using the word wages
not in the sense of a quantity, but in the sense of a
proportion. When I say that wages fall as rent rises, I
do not mean that the quantity of wealth obtained by
laborers as wages is necessarily less, but that the
proportion which it bears to the whole produce is
necessarily less. The proportion may diminish while the
quantity remains the same or increases." —
Progress and Poverty, book iii, ch. vi.
96. The condition illustrated in the last
chart would be the result of social growth if all land
but that which was in full use were common land. The
discovery of mines, the development of cities and
towns, and the construction of railroads, the
irrigation of and places, improvements in government,
all the infinite conveniences and laborsaving devices
that civilization generates, would tend to abolish
poverty by increasing the compensation of labor, and
making it impossible for any man to be in involuntary
idleness, or underpaid, so long as mankind was in want.
If demand for land increased, Wages would tend to fall
as the demand brought lower grades of land into use;
but they would at the same time tend to rise as social
growth added new capabilities to the lower grades. And
it is altogether probable that, while progress would
lower Wages as a proportion of total product, it would
increase them as an absolute quantity.
c. Significance of the Upward Tendency of
Rent
Now, what is the meaning of this tendency of Rent to
rise with social progress, while Wages tend to fall? Is
it not a plain promise that if Rent be treated as common
property, advances in productive power shall be steps in
the direction of realizing through orderly and natural
growth those grand conceptions of both the socialist and
the individualist, which in the present condition of
society are justly ranked as Utopian? Is it not likewise
a plain warning that if Rent be treated as private
property, advances in productive power will be steps in
the direction of making slaves of the many laborers, and
masters of a few land-owners? Does it not mean that
common ownership of Rent is in harmony with natural law,
and that its private appropriation is disorderly and
degrading? When the cause of Rent and the tendency
illustrated in the preceding chart are considered in
connection with the self-evident truth that God made the
earth for common use and not for private monopoly, how
can a contrary inference hold? Caused and increased by
social growth, 97 the benefits of which should be common,
and attaching to land, the just right to which is equal,
Rent must be the natural fund for public expenses. 98
97. Here, far away from civilization, is
a solitary settler. Getting no benefits from
government, he needs no public revenues, and none of
the land about him has any value. Another settler
comes, and another, until a village appears. Some
public revenue is then required. Not much, but some.
And the land has a little value, only a little; perhaps
just enough to equal the need for public revenue. The
village becomes a town. More revenues are needed, and
land values are higher. It becomes a city. The public
revenues required are enormous, and so are the land
values.
98. Society, and society alone, causes
Rent. Rising with the rise, advancing with the growth,
and receding with the decline of society, it measures
the earning power of society as a whole as
distinguished from that of the individuals. Wages, on
the other hand, measure the earning power of the
individuals as distinguished from that of society as a
whole. We have distinguished the parts into which
Wealth is distributed as Wages and Rent; but it would
be correct, indeed it is the same thing, to regard all
wealth as earnings, and to distinguish the two kinds as
Communal Earnings and Individual Earnings. How, then,
can there be any question as to the fund from which
society should be supported? How can it be justly
supported in any other way than out of its own
earnings?
If there be at all such a thing as design in the
universe — and who can doubt it? — then has
it been designed that Rent, the earnings of the
community, shall be retained for the support of the
community, and that Wages, the earnings of the
individual, shall be left to the individual in proportion
to the value of his service. This is the divine law,
whether we trace it through complex moral and economic
relations, or find it in the eighth commandment.
d. Effect of Confiscating Rent to Private
Use.
By giving Rent to individuals society ignores this
most just law, 99 thereby creating social disorder and
inviting social disease. Upon society alone, therefore,
and not upon divine Providence which has provided
bountifully, nor upon the disinherited poor, rests the
responsibility for poverty and fear of poverty.
99. "Whatever dispute arouses the
passions of men, the conflict is sure to rage, not so
much as to the question 'Is it wise?' as to the
question 'Is it right?'
"This tendency of popular discussions to
take an ethical form has a cause. It springs from a law
of the human mind; it rests upon a vague and
instinctive recognition of what is probably the deepest
truth we can grasp. That alone is wise which is just;
that alone is enduring which is right. In the narrow
scale of individual actions and individual life this
truth may be often obscured, but in the wider field of
national life it everywhere stands out.
"I bow to this arbitrament, and accept
this test." — Progress and Poverty, book vii, ch.
i.
The reader who has been deceived into
believing that Mr. George's proposition is in any
respect unjust, will find profit in a perusal of the
entire chapter from which the foregoing extract is
taken.
Let us try to trace the connection by means of a
chart, beginning with the white spaces on page 68. As
before, the first-comers take possession of the best
land. But instead of leaving for others what they do not
themselves need for use, as in the previous
illustrations, they appropriate the whole space, using
only part, but claiming ownership of the rest. We may
distinguish the used part with red color, and that which
is appropriated without use with blue. Thus: [chart]
But what motive is there for appropriating more of the
space than is used? Simply that the appropriators may
secure the pecuniary benefit of future social growth.
What will enable them to secure that? Our system of
confiscating Rent from the community that earns it, and
giving it to land-owners who, as such, earn
nothing.100
100. It is reported from Iowa that a few
years ago a workman in that State saw a meteorite fall,
and. securing possession of it after much digging, he
was offered $105 by a college for his "find." But the
owner of the land on which the meteorite fell claimed
the money, and the two went to law about it. After an
appeal to the highest court of the State, it was
finally decided that neither by right of discovery, nor
by right of labor, could the workman have the money,
because the title to the meteorite was in the man who
owned the land upon which it fell.
Observe the effect now upon Rent and Wages. When other
men come, instead of finding half of the best land still
common and free, as in the corresponding chart on page
68, they find all of it owned, and are obliged either to
go upon poorer land or to buy or rent from owners of the
best. How much will they pay for the best? Not more than
1, if they want it for use and not to hold for a higher
price in the future, for that represents the full
difference between its productiveness and the
productiveness of the next best. But if the first-comers,
reasoning that the next best land will soon be scarce and
theirs will then rise in value, refuse to sell or to rent
at that valuation, the newcomers must resort to land of
the second grade, though the best be as yet only partly
used. Consequently land of the first grade commands Rent
before it otherwise would.
As the sellers' price, under these circumstances, is
arbitrary it cannot be stated in the chart; but the
buyers' price is limited by the superiority of the best
land over that which can be had for nothing, and the
chart may be made to show it: [chart]
And now, owing to the success of the appropriators of
the best land in securing more than their fellows for the
same expenditure of labor force, a rush is made for
unappropriated land. It is not to use it that it is
wanted, but to enable its appropriators to put Rent into
their own pockets as soon as growing demand for land
makes it valuable.101 We may, for illustration, suppose
that all the remainder of the second space and the whole
of the third are thus appropriated, and note the effect:
[chart]
At this point Rent does not increase nor Wages fall,
because there is no increased demand for land for use.
The holding of inferior land for higher prices, when
demand for use is at a standstill, is like owning lots in
the moon — entertaining, perhaps, but not
profitable. But let more land be needed for use, and
matters promptly assume a different appearance. The new
labor must either go to the space that yields but 1, or
buy or rent from owners of better grades, or hire out.
The effect would be the same in any case. Nobody for the
given expenditure of labor force would get more than 1;
the surplus of products would go to landowners as Rent,
either directly in rent payments, or indirectly through
lower Wages. Thus: [chart]
101. The text speaks of Rent only as a
periodical or continuous payment — what would be
called "ground rent." But actual or potential Rent may
always be, and frequently is, capitalized for the
purpose of selling the right to enjoy it, and it is to
selling value that we usually refer when dealing in
land.
Land which has the power of yielding Rent
to its owner will have a selling value, whether it be
used or not, and whether Rent is actually derived from
it or not. This selling value will be the
capitalization of its present or prospective power of
producing Rent. In fact, much the larger proportion of
laud that has a selling value is wholly or partly
unused, producing no Rent at all, or less than it would
if fully used. This condition is expressed in the chart
by the blue color.
"The capitalized value of land is the
actuarial 'discounted' value of all the net incomes
which it is likely to afford, allowance being made on
the one hand for all incidental expenses, including
those of collecting the rents, and on the other for its
mineral wealth, its capabilities of development for any
kind of business, and its advantages, material, social,
and aesthetic, for the purposes of residence." —
Marshall's Prin., book vi, ch. ix, sec. 9.
"The value of land is commonly expressed
as a certain number of times the current money rental,
or in other words, a certain 'number of years'
purchase' of that rental; and other things being equal,
it will be the higher the more important these direct
gratifications are, as well as the greater the chance
that they and the money income afforded by the land
will rise." — Id., note.
"Value . . . means not utility, not any
quality inhering in the thing itself, but a quality
which gives to the possession of a thing the power of
obtaining other things, in return for it or for its
use. . . Value in this sense — the usual sense
— is purely relative. It exists from and is
measured by the power of obtaining things for things by
exchanging them. . . Utility is necessary to value, for
nothing can be valuable unless it has the quality of
gratifying some physical or mental desire of man,
though it be but a fancy or whim. But utility of itself
does not give value. . . If we ask ourselves the reason
of . . . variations in . . . value . . . we see that
things having some form of utility or desirability, are
valuable or not valuable, as they are hard or easy to
get. And if we ask further, we may see that with most
of the things that have value this difficulty or ease
of getting them, which determines value, depends on the
amount of labor which must be expended in producing
them ; i.e., bringing them into the place, form and
condition in which they are desired. . . Value is
simply an expression of the labor required for the
production of such a thing. But there are some things
as to which this is not so clear. Land is not produced
by labor, yet land, irrespective of any improvements
that labor has made on it, often has value. . . Yet a
little examination will show that such facts are but
exemplifications of the general principle, just as the
rise of a balloon and the fall of a stone both
exemplify the universal law of gravitation. . . The
value of everything produced by labor, from a pound of
chalk or a paper of pins to the elaborate structure and
appurtenances of a first-class ocean steamer, is
resolvable on analysis into an equivalent of the labor
required to produce such a thing in form and place;
while the value of things not produced by labor, but
nevertheless susceptible of ownership, is in the same
way resolvable into an equivalent of the labor which
the ownership of such a thing enables the owner to
obtain or save." —
Perplexed Philosopher, ch. v.
The figure 1 in parenthesis, as an item of Rent,
indicates potential Rent. Labor would give that much for
the privilege of using the space, but the owners hold out
for better terms; therefore neither Rent nor Wages is
actually produced, though but for this both might be.
In this chart, notwithstanding that but little space
is used, indicated with red, Wages are reduced to the
same low point by the mere appropriation of space,
indicated with blue, that they would reach if all the
space above the poorest were fully used. It thereby
appears that under a system which confiscates Rent to
private uses, the demand for land for speculative
purposes becomes so great that Wages fall to a minimum
long before they would if land were appropriated only for
use.
In illustrating the effect of confiscating Rent to
private use we have as yet ignored the element of social
growth. Let us now assume as before (page 73), that
social growth increases the productive power of the given
expenditure of labor force to 100 when applied to the
best land, 50 when applied to the next best, 10 to the
next, 3 to the next, and 1 to the poorest. Labor would
not be benefited now, as it appeared to be when on page
73 we illustrated the appropriation of land for use only,
although much less land is actually used. The prizes
which expectation of future social growth dangles before
men as the rewards of owning land, would raise demand so
as to make it more than ever difficult to get land. All
of the fourth grade would be taken up in expectation of
future demand; and "surplus labor" would be crowded out
to the open space that originally yielded nothing, but
which in consequence of increased labor power now yields
as much as the poorest closed space originally yielded,
namely, 1 to the given expenditure of labor force.102
Wages would then be reduced to the present productiveness
of the open space. Thus: [chart]
102. The paradise to which the youth of
our country have so long been directed in the advice,
"Go West, young man, go West," is truthfully described
in "Progress and Poverty," book iv, ch. iv, as follows
:
"The man who sets out from the eastern
seaboard in search of the margin of cultivation,
where he may obtain land without paying rent, must,
like the man who swam the river to get a drink, pass
for long distances through half-titled farms, and
traverse vast areas of virgin soil, before he reaches
the point where land can be had free of rent —
i.e., by homestead entry or preemption."
If we assume that 1 for the given expenditure of labor
force is the least that labor can take while exerting the
same force, the downward movement of Wages will be here
held in equilibrium. They cannot fall below 1; but
neither can they rise above it, no matter how much
productive power may increase, so long as it pays to hold
land for higher values. Some laborers would continually
be pushed back to land which increased productive power
would have brought up in productiveness from 0 to 1, and
by perpetual competition for work would so regulate the
labor market that the given expenditure of labor force,
however much it produced, could nowhere secure more than
1 in Wages.103 And this tendency would persist until some
labor was forced upon land which, despite increase in
productive power, would not yield the accustomed living
without increase of labor force. Competition for work
would then compel all laborers to increase their
expenditure of labor force, and to do it over and over
again as progress went on and lower and lower grades of
land were monopolized, until human endurance could go no
further.104 Either that, or they would be obliged to
adapt themselves to a lower scale of living.105
103. Henry Fawcett, in his work on
"Political Economy," book ii, ch. iii, observes with
reference to improvements in agricultural implements
which diminish the expense of cultivation, that they do
not increase the profits of the farmer or the wages of
his laborers, but that "the landlord will receive in
addition to the rent already paid to him, all that is
saved in the expense of cultivation." This is true not
alone of improvements in agriculture, but also of
improvements in all other branches of industry.
104. "The cause which limits speculation
in commodities, the tendency of increasing price to
draw forth additional supplies, cannot limit the
speculative advance in land values, as land is a fixed
quantity, which human agency can neither increase nor
diminish; but there is nevertheless a limit to the
price of land, in the minimum required by labor and
capital as the condition of engaging in production. If
it were possible to continuously reduce wages until
zero were reached, it would be possible to continuously
increase rent until it swallowed up the whole produce.
But as wages cannot be permanently reduced below the
point at which laborers will consent to work and
reproduce, nor interest below the point at which
capital will be devoted to production, there is a limit
which restrains the speculative advance of rent. Hence,
speculation cannot have the same scope to advance rent
in countries where wages and interest are already near
the minimum, as in countries where they are
considerably above it. Yet that there is in all
progressive countries a constant tendency in the
speculative advance of rent to overpass the limit where
production would cease, is, I think, shown by recurring
seasons of industrial paralysis." — Progress and
Poverty, book iv, ch. iv.
105. As Puck once put it, "the man who
makes two blades of grass to grow where but one grew
before, must not be surprised when ordered to 'keep off
the grass.' "
They in fact do both, and the incidental disturbances
of general readjustment are what we call "hard times."
106 These culminate in forcing unused land into the
market, thereby reducing Rent and reviving industry. Thus
increase of labor force, a lowering of the scale of
living, and depression of Rent, co-operate to bring on
what we call "good times." But no sooner do "good times"
return than renewed demands for land set in, Rent rises
again, Wages fall again, and "hard times" duly reappear.
The end of every period of "hard times" finds Rent higher
and Wages lower than at the end of the previous
period.107
106. "That a speculative advance in rent
or land values invariably precedes each of these
seasons of industrial depression is everywhere clear.
That they bear to each other the relation of cause and
effect, is obvious to whoever considers the necessary
relation between land and labor." — Progress and
Poverty, book v, ch. i.
107. What are called "good times" reach a
point at which an upward land market sets in. From that
point there is a downward tendency of wages (or a rise
in the cost of living, which is the same thing) in all
departments of labor and with all grades of laborers.
This tendency continues until the fictitious values of
land give way. So long as the tendency is felt only by
that class which is hired for wages, it is poverty
merely; when the same tendency is felt by the class of
labor that is distinguished as "the business interests
of the country," it is "hard times." And "hard times"
are periodical because land values, by falling, allow
"good times" to set it, and by rising with "good times"
bring "hard times" on again. The effect of "hard times"
may be overcome, without much, if any, fall in land
values, by sufficient increase in productive power to
overtake the fictitious value of land.
The dishonest and disorderly system under which
society confiscates Rent from common to individual uses,
produces this result. That maladjustment is the
fundamental cause of poverty. And progress, so long as
the maladjustment continues, instead of tending to remove
poverty as naturally it should, actually generates and
intensifies it. Poverty persists with increase of
productive power because land values, when Rent is
privately appropriated, tend to even greater increase.
There can be but one outcome if this continues: for
individuals suffering and degradation, and for society
destruction. ... read the book
Rev. A. C. Auchmuty: Gems from George, a themed
collection of excerpts from the writings of Henry
George (with links to sources)
IN the economic meaning of the term production, the
transporter or exchanger, or anyone engaged in any
subdivision of those functions, is as truly engaged in
production as is the primary extractor or maker. A
newspaper-carrier or the keeper of a news-stand would,
for instance, in common speech be styled a distributor.
But in economic terminology he is not a distributor of
wealth, but a producer of wealth. Although his part in
the process of producing the newspaper to the final
receiver comes last, not first, he is as much a producer
as the paper-maker or type-founder, the editor, or
compositor, or press-man. For the object of production is
the satisfaction of human desires, that is to say, it is
consumption; and this object is not made capable of
attainment, that is to say, production is not really
complete, until wealth is brought to the place where it
is to be consumed and put at the disposal of him whose
desire it is to satisfy. — The Science of
Political Economy
unabridged: Book III, Chapter 1, The Production of
Wealth: The Meaning of Production • abridged:
Part III, Chapter 1, The Production of Wealth: The
Meaning of Production
PRODUCTION and distribution are not separate things, but
two mentally distinguishable parts of one thing —
the exertion of human labor in the satisfaction of human
desire. Though materially distinguishable, they are as
closely related as the two arms of the syphon. And as it
is the outflow of water at the longer end of the syphon
that is the cause of the inflow of water at the shorter
end, so it is that distribution is really the cause of
production, not production the cause of distribution. In
the ordinary course, things are not distributed because
they have been produced, but are produced in order that
they may be distributed. Thus interference with the
distribution of wealth is interference with the
production of wealth, and shows its effect in lessened
production. — The Science of Political
Economy —
unabridged Book IV, Chapter 2, The Distribution of
Wealth: The Nature of Distribution • abridged
Part IV, Chapter 2, The Distribution of Wealth: The
Nature of Distribution
OUR inquiry into the laws of the distribution of wealth
is not an inquiry into the municipal laws or human
enactments which either here and now, or in any other
time and place, prescribe or have prescribed how wealth
shall be divided among men. With them we have no concern,
unless it may be for purposes of illustration. What we
have to seek are those laws of the distribution of wealth
which belong to the natural order — laws which are
a part of that system or arrangement which constitutes
the social organism or body economic, as distinguished
from the body politic or state, the Greater Leviathan
which makes its appearance with civilization and develops
with its advance. These natural laws are in all times and
places the same, and though they may be crossed by human
enactment, can never be annulled or swerved by it. It is
more needful to call this to mind, because, in what have
passed for systematic treatises on political economy, the
fact that it is with natural laws, not human laws, that
the science of political economy is concerned, has, in
treating of the distribution of wealth, been utterly
ignored, and even flatly denied. — The Science
of Political Economy —
unabridged: Part IV, Chapter 1, The Distribution of
Wealth: The Meaning of Distribution • abridged:
Part IV, Chapter 1, The Distribution of Wealth: The
Meaning of Distribution
THE distinction between the laws of production and the
laws of distribution is not, as is erroneously taught in
the scholastic political economy, that the one set of
laws are natural laws and the other human laws. Both sets
of laws are laws of nature. The real distinction is that
the natural laws of production are physical laws and the
natural laws of distribution are moral laws. . . . The
moment we turn from a consideration of the laws of the
production of wealth to a consideration of the laws of
the distribution of wealth, the idea of ought or duty
becomes primary. All consideration of distribution
involves the ethical principle, is necessarily a
consideration of ought or duty — a consideration in
which the idea of right or justice is from the very first
involved. — The Science of Political
Economy —
unabridged: Book IV, Chapter 4, The Distribution of
Wealth: The Real Difference Between Laws of Production
and of Distribution • abridged:
Part IV, Chapter 3: The Distribution of Wealth: Physical
and Moral Laws
THE primary purpose and end of government being to
secure the natural rights and equal liberty of each, all
businesses that involve monopoly are within the necessary
province of governmental regulation, and businesses that
are in their nature complete monopolies become properly
functions of the State. As society develops, the State
must assume these functions, in their nature
co-operative, in order to secure the equal rights and
liberty of all. That is to say, as, in the process of
integration, the individual becomes more and more
dependent upon and subordinate to the all, it becomes
necessary for government, which is properly that social
organ by which alone the whole body of individuals can
act, to take upon itself, in the interest of all, certain
functions which cannot safely be left to individuals.
—
Social Problems
— Chapter 17, The Functions of
Government
IT is not the business of government to make men virtuous
or religious, or to preserve the fool from the
consequences of his own folly. Government should be
repressive no further than is necessary to secure liberty
by protecting the equal rights of each from aggression on
the part of others, and the moment governmental
prohibitions extend beyond this line they are in danger
of defeating the very ends they are intended to
serve.—
Social Problems
— Chapter 17, The Functions of
Government
ALL schemes for securing equality in the conditions of
men by placing the distribution of wealth in the hands of
government have the fatal defect of beginning at the
wrong end. They pre-suppose pure government; but it is
not government that makes society; it is society that
makes government; and until there is something like
substantial equality in the distribution of wealth, we
cannot expect pure government. — Protection or
Free Trade, Chapter 28
econlib ... go
to "Gems from George"
Charles B. Fillebrown: A Catechism of
Natural Taxation, from Principles of Natural
Taxation (1917)
Q22. What is privilege?
A. Strictly defined, privilege is, according to the
Century Dictionary, "a special and exclusive power
conferred by law on particular persons or classes of
persons and ordinarily in derogation of the common
right."
Q23. What is today the popular conception of
privilege?
A. That it is the law-given power of one man to profit at
another man's expense.
Q24. What are the principal forms of
privilege?
A. The appropriation by individuals, or by public service
corporations, of the net rent of land created by the
growth and activity of the community without payment for
the same. Also, the less important privileges connected
with patents, tariff, and the currency.
Q25. Where in does privilege differ from
capital?
A. Capital is a material thing, a product of labor,
stored-up wages; an instrument of production paid for in
human labor, and destined to wear out. Capital is the
natural ally of labor, and is harmless except as allied
to privilege. Privilege is none of these, but is an
intangible statutory power, an unpaid-for and perpetual
lien upon the future labor of this and succeeding
generations. Capital is paid for and ephemeral. Privilege
is unpaid for and eternal. A man accumulated in his
profession $5,000 capital, which he invested in land in
Canada. Ten years later he sold the same land for
$200,000. Here is an instance of $5,000 capital allied
with $195,000 privilege. This illustrates that privilege
and not capital is the real enemy of labor.
Q26. How may franchises be treated?
A. Franchise privileges may be abated, or gradually
abolished by lower rates, or by taxation, or by both, in
the interest of the community.
Q27. Why should privilege be especially
taxed?
A. Because such payment is fairly due from grantee to the
grantor of privilege and also because a tax upon
privilege can never be a burden upon industry or
commerce, nor can it ever operate to reduce the wages of
labor or increase prices to the consumer.
Q28. How are landlords privileged?
A. Because, in so far as their land tax is an "old" tax,
it is a burdenless tax, and because their buildings' tax
is shifted upon their tenants; most landlords who let
land and also the tenement houses and business blocks
thereon avoid all share in the tax burden.
Q29. How does privilege affect the distribution of
wealth?
A. Wealth as produced is now distributed
substantially in but two channels, privilege and wages.
The abolition of privilege would leave but the one proper
channel, viz., wages of capital, hand, and
brain.
... read
the whole article
|
To share this page with a friend:
right click, choose "send," and add your
comments.
|
|
Red links have not been
visited; .
Green links are pages you've seen
|
Essential Documents pertinent
to this theme:
essential_documents
|
|