Private Property in Land
Henry George: The Condition of
Labor — An Open Letter to Pope Leo XIII in response
to Rerum Novarum (1891)
... Your use, in so many passages of your Encyclical,
of the inclusive term “property” or
“private” property, of which in morals
nothing can be either affirmed or denied, makes your
meaning, if we take isolated sentences, in many places
ambiguous. But reading it as a whole, there can be no
doubt of your intention that private property in land
shall be understood when you speak merely of private
property. With this interpretation, I find that the
reasons you urge for private property in land are eight.
Let us consider them in order of presentation. You
urge:
1. That what is bought with rightful property is
rightful property. (RN, paragraph 5) ...
2. That private property in land proceeds from
man’s gift of reason. (RN, paragraphs 6-7.)
...
3. That private property in land deprives no one of the
use of land. (RN, paragraph 8.) ...
4. That Industry expended on land gives ownership in the
land itself. (RN, paragraphs 9-10.) ...
5. That private property in land has the support of the
common opinion of mankind, and has conduced to peace and
tranquillity, and that it is sanctioned by Divine Law.
(RN, paragraph 11.) ...
6. That fathers should provide for their children and
that private property in land is necessary to enable them
to do so. (RN, paragraphs 14-17.) ...
7. That the private ownership of land stimulates
industry, increases wealth, and attaches men to the soil
and to their country. (RN, paragraph 51.) ...
8. That the right to possess private property in land is
from nature, not from man; that the state has no right to
abolish it, and that to take the value of landownership
in taxation would be unjust and cruel to the private
owner. (RN, paragraph 51.) ...
Believing that the social question is at bottom a
religious question, we deem it of happy augury to the
world that in your Encyclical the most influential of all
religious teachers has directed attention to the
condition of labor.
But while we appreciate the many wholesome truths you
utter, while we feel, as all must feel, that you are
animated by a desire to help the suffering and oppressed,
and to put an end to any idea that the church is divorced
from the aspiration for liberty and progress, yet it is
painfully obvious to us that one fatal assumption hides
from you the cause of the evils you see, and makes it
impossible for you to propose any adequate remedy.
This assumption is, that private property in land
is of the same nature and has the same sanctions as
private property in things produced by labor. In
spite of its undeniable truths and its benevolent spirit,
your Encyclical shows you to be involved in such
difficulties as a physician called to examine one
suffering from disease of the stomach would meet should
he begin with a refusal to consider the stomach.
Prevented by this assumption from seeing the true
cause, the only causes you find it possible to assign for
the growth of misery and wretchedness are the destruction
of working-men’s guilds in the last century, the
repudiation in public institutions and laws of the
ancient religion, rapacious usury, the custom of working
by contract, and the concentration of trade.
Such diagnosis is manifestly inadequate to account for
evils that are alike felt in Catholic countries, in
Protestant countries, in countries that adhere to the
Greek communion and in countries where no religion is
professed by the state; that are alike felt in old
countries and in new countries; where industry is simple
and where it is most elaborate; and amid all varieties of
industrial customs and relations.
But the real cause will be clear if you will
consider that since labor must find its workshop and
reservoir in land, the labor question is but another name
for the land question, and will reexamine your assumption
that private property in land is necessary and
right.
See how fully adequate is the cause I have pointed
out. The most important of all the material relations of
man is his relation to the planet he inhabits, and hence,
the “impious resistance to the benevolent
intentions of his Creator,” which, as Bishop Nulty
says, is involved in private property in
land, must produce evils wherever it exists. But
by virtue of the law, “unto whom much is given,
from him much is required,” the very
progress of civilization makes the evils produced by
private property in land more wide-spread and
intense.
What is producing throughout the civilized world that
condition of things you rightly describe as intolerable
is not this and that local error or minor mistake. It is
nothing less than the progress of civilization itself;
nothing less than the intellectual advance and the
material growth in which our century has been so
preeminent, acting in a state of society based on
private property in land; nothing less than the
new gifts that in our time God has been showering on man,
but which are being turned into scourges by man’s
“impious resistance to the benevolent intentions of
his Creator.” ....
Your Holiness will remember the great London dock
strike of two years ago, which, with that of other
influential men, received the moral support of that
Prince of the Church whom we of the English speech hold
higher and dearer than any prelate has been held by us
since the blood of Thomas à Becket stained the
Canterbury altar.
In a volume called “The Story of the
Dockers’ Strike,” written by
Messrs. H. Llewellyn Smith and Vaughan Nash, with an
introduction by Sydney Buxton, M.P., which advocates
trades-unionism as the solution of the labor question,
and of which a large number were sent to Australia as a
sort of official recognition of the generous aid received
from there by the strikers, I find in the summing up, on
pages 164-165, the following:
If the settlement lasts, work at the docks will be
more regular, better paid, and carried on under better
conditions than ever before. All this will be an
unqualified gain to those who get the benefit from it.
But another result will undoubtedly be to contract the
field of employment and lessen the number of those for
whom work can be found. The lower-class casual will, in
the end, find his position more precarious than ever
before, in proportion to the increased regularity of
work which the “fitter” of the laborers
will secure. The effect of the organization of dock
labor, as of all classes of labor, will be to squeeze
out the residuum. The loafer, the cadger, the failure
in the industrial race — the members of
“Class B” of Mr. Charles Booth’s
hierarchy of social classes — will be no gainers
by the change, but will rather find another door closed
against them, and this in many cases the last door to
employment.
I am far from wishing that your Holiness should join
in that pharisaical denunciation of trades-unions common
among those who, while quick to point out the injustice
of trades-unions in denying to others the equal right to
work, are themselves supporters of that more primary
injustice that denies the equal right to the
standing-place and natural material necessary to work.
What I wish to point out is that trades-unionism, while
it may be a partial palliative, is not a remedy; that it
has not that moral character which could alone justify
one in the position of your Holiness in urging it as good
in itself. Yet, so long as you insist on private
property in land what better can you do? ...
I have already referred generally to the defects that
attach to all socialistic remedies for the evil condition
of labor, but respect for your Holiness dictates that I
should speak specifically, even though briefly, of the
remedies proposed or suggested by you.
Of these, the widest and strongest are that the state
should restrict the hours of labor, the employment of
women and children, the unsanitary conditions of
workshops, etc. Yet how little may in this way be
accomplished.
A strong, absolute ruler might hope by such
regulations to alleviate the conditions of chattel
slaves. But the tendency of our times is toward
democracy, and democratic states are necessarily weaker
in paternalism, while in the industrial slavery, growing
out of private ownership of land, that prevails in
Christendom today, it is not the master who forces the
slave to labor, but the slave who urges the master to let
him labor. Thus the greatest difficulty in enforcing such
regulations comes from those whom they are intended to
benefit. It is not, for instance, the masters who make it
difficult to enforce restrictions on child labor in
factories, but the mothers, who, prompted by poverty,
misrepresent the ages of their children even to the
masters, and teach the children to misrepresent.
But while in large factories and mines regulations as
to hours, ages, etc., though subject to evasion and
offering opportunities for extortion and corruption, may
be to some extent enforced, how can they have any effect
in those far wider branches of industry where the laborer
works for himself or for small employers?
All such remedies are of the nature of the remedy for
overcrowding that is generally prescribed with them
— the restriction under penalty of the number who
may occupy a room and the demolition of unsanitary
buildings. Since these measures have no tendency to
increase house accommodation or to augment ability to pay
for it, the overcrowding that is forced back in some
places goes on in other places and to a worse degree. All
such remedies begin at the wrong end. They are like
putting on brake and bit to hold in quietness horses that
are being lashed into frenzy; they are like trying to
stop a locomotive by holding its wheels instead of
shutting off steam; like attempting to cure smallpox by
driving back its pustules. Men do not overwork themselves
because they like it; it is not in the nature of the
mother’s heart to send children to work when they
ought to be at play; it is not of choice that laborers
will work under dangerous and unsanitary conditions.
These things, like overcrowding, come from the sting of
poverty. And so long as the poverty of which they are the
expression is left untouched, restrictions such as you
indorse can have only partial and evanescent results. The
cause remaining, repression in one place can only bring
out its effects in other places, and the task you assign
to the state is as hopeless as to ask it to lower the
level of the ocean by bailing out the sea.
Nor can the state cure poverty by regulating wages. It
is as much beyond the power of the state to regulate
wages as it is to regulate the rates of interest. Usury
laws have been tried again and again, but the only effect
they have ever had has been to increase what the poorer
borrowers must pay, and for the same reasons that all
attempts to lower by regulation the price of goods have
always resulted merely in increasing them. The general
rate of wages is fixed by the ease or difficulty with
which labor can obtain access to land, ranging from the
full earnings of labor, where land is free, to the least
on which laborers can live and reproduce, where land is
fully monopolized. Thus, where it has been comparatively
easy for laborers to get land, as in the United States
and in Australasia, wages have been higher than in Europe
and it has been impossible to get European laborers to
work there for wages that they would gladly accept at
home; while as monopolization goes on under the
influence of private property in land, wages tend to
fall, and the social conditions of Europe to
appear. Thus, under the partial yet substantial
recognition of common rights to land, of which I have
spoken, the many attempts of the British Parliament to
reduce wages by regulation failed utterly. And
so, when the institution of private property in land had
done its work in England, all attempts of Parliament to
raise wages proved unavailing. In the beginning
of this century it was even attempted to increase the
earnings of laborers by grants in aid of wages. But the
only result was to lower commensurately what wages
employers paid.
The state could maintain wages above the tendency of
the market (for as I have shown labor deprived of land
becomes a commodity), only by offering employment to all
who wish it; or by lending its sanction to strikes and
supporting them with its funds. Thus it is, that the
thoroughgoing socialists who want the state to take all
industry into its hands are much more logical than those
timid socialists who propose that the state should
regulate private industry — but only a little.
The same hopelessness attends your suggestion that
working-people should be encouraged by the state in
obtaining a share of the land. It is evident that by this
you mean that, as is now being attempted in Ireland, the
state shall buy out large landowners in favor of small
ones, establishing what are known as peasant proprietors.
Supposing that this can be done even to a considerable
extent, what will be accomplished save to substitute a
larger privileged class for a smaller privileged class?
What will be done for the still larger class that must
remain, the laborers of the agricultural districts, the
workmen of the towns, the proletarians of the cities? Is
it not true, as Professor De Laveleye says, that in such
countries as Belgium, where peasant proprietary exists,
the tenants, for there still exist tenants, are
rack-rented with a mercilessness unknown in Ireland? Is
it not true that in such countries as Belgium the
condition of the mere laborer is even worse than it is in
Great Britain, where large ownerships obtain? And if the
state attempts to buy up land for peasant proprietors
will not the effect be, what is seen today in Ireland, to
increase the market value of land and thus make it more
difficult for those not so favored, and for those who
will come after, to get land? How, moreover, on the
principle which you declare (36), that “to the
state the interests of all are equal, whether high or
low,” will you justify state aid to one man to buy
a bit of land without also insisting on state aid to
another man to buy a donkey, to another to buy a shop, to
another to buy the tools and materials of a trade —
state aid in short to everybody who may be able to make
good use of it or thinks that he could? And are you not
thus landed in communism — not the communism of the
early Christians and of the religious orders, but
communism that uses the coercive power of the state to
take rightful property by force from those who have, to
give to those who have not? For the state has no purse of
Fortunatus; the state cannot repeat the miracle of the
loaves and fishes; all that the state can give, it must
get by some form or other of the taxing power. And
whether it gives or lends money, or gives or lends
credit, it cannot give to those who have not, without
taking from those who have.
But aside from all this, any scheme of
dividing up land while maintaining private property in
land is futile. Small holdings cannot coexist
with the treatment of land as private property where
civilization is materially advancing and wealth augments.
We may see this in the economic tendencies that in
ancient times were the main cause that transformed
world-conquering Italy from a land of small farms to a
land of great estates. We may see it in the fact that
while two centuries ago the majority of English farmers
were owners of the land they tilled, tenancy has been for
a long time the all but universal condition of the
English farmer. And now the mighty forces of steam and
electricity have come to urge concentration. It is in the
United States that we may see on the largest scale how
their power is operating to turn a nation of landowners
into a nation of tenants. The principle is clear and
irresistible. Material progress makes land more valuable,
and when this increasing value is left to private owners
land must pass from the ownership of the poor into the
ownership of the rich, just as diamonds so pass when poor
men find them. What the British government is attempting
in Ireland is to build snow-houses in the Arabian desert!
to plant bananas in Labrador!
There is one way, and only one way, in which
working-people in our civilization may be secured a share
in the land of their country, and that is the way that we
propose — the taking of the profits of
landownership for the community. ...
Men who are sure of getting food when they shall need
it eat only what appetite dictates. But with the sparse
tribes who exist on the verge of the habitable globe life
is either a famine or a feast. Enduring hunger for days,
the fear of it prompts them to gorge like anacondas when
successful in their quest of game. And so, what gives
wealth its curse is what drives men to seek it, what
makes it so envied and admired — the fear of want.
As the unduly rich are the corollary of the unduly poor,
so is the soul-destroying quality of riches but the
reflex of the want that embrutes and degrades. The real
evil lies in the injustice from which unnatural
possession and unnatural deprivation both spring.
But this injustice can hardly be charged on
individuals or classes. The existence of private
property in land is a great social wrong from which
society at large suffers, and of which the very rich and
the very poor are alike victims, though at the opposite
extremes. Seeing this, it seems to us like a
violation of Christian charity to speak of the rich as
though they individually were responsible for the
sufferings of the poor. Yet, while you do this, you
insist that the cause of monstrous wealth and degrading
poverty shall not be touched. Here is a man with a
disfiguring and dangerous excrescence. One physician
would kindly, gently, but firmly remove it. Another
insists that it shall not be removed, but at the same
time holds up the poor victim to hatred and ridicule.
Which is right?
In seeking to restore all men to their equal and
natural rights we do not seek the benefit of any class,
but of all. For we both know by faith and see by fact
that injustice can profit no one and that justice must
benefit all. ...
And in taking for the uses of society what we clearly
see is the great fund intended for society in the divine
order, we would not levy the slightest tax on the
possessors of wealth, no matter how rich they might be.
Not only do we deem such taxes a violation of the right
of property, but we see that by virtue of beautiful
adaptations in the economic laws of the Creator, it is
impossible for any one honestly to acquire wealth,
without at the same time adding to the wealth of the
world.
To persist in a wrong, to refuse to undo it, is always
to become involved in other wrongs. Those who
defend private property in land, and thereby deny the
first and most important of all human rights, the equal
right to the material substratum of life, are compelled
to one of two courses. Either they must, as do those
whose gospel is “Devil take the hindermost,”
deny the equal right to life, and by some theory like
that to which the English clergyman Malthus has given his
name, assert that nature (they do not venture to say God)
brings into the world more men than there is provision
for; or, they must, as do the socialists, assert as
rights what in themselves are wrongs. ...
Let me again state the case that your Encyclical
presents:
What is that condition of labor which as you truly say
is “the question of the hour,” and
“fills every mind with painful apprehension”?
Reduced to its lowest expression it is the poverty of men
willing to work. And what is the lowest expression of
this phrase? It is that they lack bread — for in
that one word we most concisely and strongly express all
the manifold material satisfactions needed by humanity,
the absence of which constitutes poverty.
Now what is the prayer of Christendom — the
universal prayer; the prayer that goes up daily and
hourly wherever the name of Christ is honored; that
ascends from your Holiness at the high altar of St.
Peter’s, and that is repeated by the youngest child
that the poorest Christian mother has taught to lisp a
request to her Father in Heaven? It is, “Give us
this day our daily bread!”
Yet where this prayer goes up, daily and hourly, men
lack bread. Is it not the business of religion to say
why? If it cannot do so, shall not scoffers mock its
ministers as Elias mocked the prophets of Baal, saying,
“Cry with a louder voice, for he is a god; and
perhaps he is talking, or is in an inn, or on a journey,
or perhaps be is asleep, and must be awaked!” What
answer can those ministers give? Either there is no God,
or he is asleep, or else he does give men their daily
bread, and it is in some way intercepted.
Here is the answer, the only true answer: If men lack
bread it is not that God has not done his part in
providing it. If men willing to labor are cursed with
poverty, it is not that the storehouse that God owes men
has failed; that the daily supply he has promised for the
daily wants of his children is not here in abundance.
It is, that impiously violating the benevolent
intentions of their Creator, men have made land private
property, and thus given into the exclusive ownership of
the few the provision that a bountiful Father has made
for all.
Any other answer than that, no matter how it may be
shrouded in the mere forms of religion, is practically an
atheistical answer. ... read the whole
letter
Rev. A. C. Auchmuty: Gems
from George, a themed collection of excerpts from the
writings of Henry George (with links to sources)
IF we are all here by the equal permission of the
Creator, we are all here with an equal title to the
enjoyment of His bounty — with an equal right to
the use of all that nature so impartially offers. This is
a right which is natural and inalienable; it is a right
which vests in every human being as he enters the world,
and which, during his continuance in the world, can be
limited only by the equal rights of others. There is in
nature no such thing as a fee simple in land. There is on
earth no power which can rightfully make a grant of
exclusive ownership in land. If all existing men were to
unite to grant away their equal rights, they could not
grant away the right of those who follow them. For what
are we but tenants for a day? Have we made the earth that
we should determine the rights of those who after us
shall tenant it in their turn? The Almighty, who created
the earth for man and man for the earth, has entailed it
upon all the generations of the children of men by a
decree written upon the constitution of all things
— a decree which no human action can bar and no
prescription determine, Let the parchments be ever so
many, or possession ever so long, natural justice can
recognize no right in one man to the possession and
enjoyment of land that is not equally the right of all
his fellows. —
Progress & Poverty
— Book VII, Chapter 1, Justice of the Remedy:
Injustice of private property in land
HAS the first comer at a banquet the right to turn
back all the chairs and claim that none of the other
guests shall partake of the food provided, except as they
make terms with him? Does the first man who presents a
ticket at the door of a theater and passes in, acquire by
his priority the right to shut the doors and have the
performance go on for him alone? Does the first passenger
who enters a railroad car obtain the right to scatter his
baggage over all the seats and compel the passengers who
come in after him to stand up?
The cases are perfectly analogous. We arrive and we
depart, guests at a banquet continually spread,
spectators and participants in an entertainment where
there is room for all who come; passengers from station
to station, on an orb that whirls through space —
our rights to take and possess cannot be exclusive; they
must be bounded everywhere by the equal rights of others.
Just as the passenger in a railroad car may spread
himself and his baggage over as many seats as he pleases,
until other passengers come in, so may a settler take and
use as much land as he chooses, until it is needed by
others — a fact which is shown by the land
acquiring a value — when his right must be
curtailed by the equal rights of the others, and no
priority of appropriation can give a right which will bar
these equal rights of others. —
Progress & Poverty
— Book VII, Chapter 1, Justice of the Remedy:
Injustice of private property in land
NATURE acknowledges no ownership or control in man save
as the result of exertion. In no other way can her
treasures be drawn forth, her powers directed, or her
forces utilized or controlled. She makes no
discriminations among men, but is to all absolutely
impartial. She knows no distinction between master and
slave, king and subject, saint and sinner. All men to her
stand upon an equal footing and have equal rights. She
recognizes no claim but that of labor, and recognizes
that without respect to the claimant. If a pirate spread
his sails, the wind will fill them as well as it will
fill those of a peaceful merchantman or missionary bark;
if a king and a common man be thrown overboard, neither
can keep his head above the water except by swimming;
birds will not come to be shot by the proprietor of the
soil any quicker than they will come to be shot by the
poacher; fish will bite or will not bite at a hook in
utter disregard as to whether it is offered them by a
good little boy who goes to Sunday school, or a bad
little boy who plays truant; grain will grow only as the
ground is prepared and the seed is sown; it is only at
the call of labor that ore can be raised from the mine;
the sun shines and the rain falls alike upon just and
unjust. The laws of nature are the decrees of the
Creator. There is written in them no recognition of any
right save that of labor; and in them is written broadly
and clearly the equal right of all men to the use and
enjoyment of nature; to apply to her by their exertions,
and to receive and possess her reward. Hence, as nature
gives only to labor, the exertion of labor in production
is the only title to exclusive possession. —
Progress & Poverty
— Book VII, Chapter 1, Justice of the Remedy:
Injustice of private property in land
PRIVATE property is not of one species, and moral
sanction can no more be asserted universally of it than
of marriage. That proper marriage conforms to the law of
God does not justify the polygamic or polyandric or
incestuous marriages that are in some countries permitted
by the civil law. And as there may be immoral marriage,
so may there be immoral private property. —
The Condition of Labor, an Open Letter to Pope Leo
XIII
THAT any species of property is permitted by the State,
does not of itself give it moral sanction. The State has
often made things property that are not justly property
but involve violence and robbery. —
The Condition of Labor, an Open Letter to Pope Leo
XIII
TO attach to things created by God the same right of
private ownership that justly attaches to things produced
by labor, is to impair and deny the true rights of
property. For a man, who out of the proceeds of his labor
is obliged to pay another man for the use of ocean or air
or sunshine or soil, all of which are to men involved in
the single term land, is in this deprived of his rightful
property, and thus robbed. —
The Condition of Labor, an Open Letter to Pope Leo
XIII
HOW then is it that we are called deniers of the right of
property? It is for the same reason that caused
nine-tenths of the good people in the United States,
north as well as south, to regard abolitionists as
deniers of the right of property; the same reason that
made even John Wesley look on a smuggler as a kind of
robber, and on a custom-house seizer of other men's goods
as a defender of law and order. Where violations of
the right of property have been long sanctioned by
custom and law, it is inevitable that those who really
assert the right of property will at first be thought to
deny it. For under such circumstances the idea of
property becomes confused, and that is thought to be
property which is in reality a violation of property.
—
A Perplexed Philosopher
(The Right Of Property And The Right Of
Taxation)
LANDLORDS must elect to try their case either by human
law or by moral law. If they say that land is
rightly property because made so by human law, they
cannot charge those who would change that law with
advocating robbery. But if they charge that such
change in human law would be robbery, then they must show
that land is rightfully property irrespective of human
law. — The Reduction to Iniquity (a reply to
the Duke of Argyll), The Nineteenth Century, July,
1884
PRIVATE property in land, no less than private
property in slaves, is the violation of the true rights
of property. They are different forms of the same robbery
— twin devices, by which the perverted ingenuity of
man has sought to enable the strong and the cunning to
escape God's requirement of labor by forcing it on
others. —
The Condition of Labor, an Open Letter to Pope Leo
XIII
ROBINSON CRUSOE, as we all know, took Friday as his
slave. Suppose, however, that instead of taking Friday as
his slave, Robinson Crusoe had welcomed him as a man and
a brother; had read him a Declaration of Independence, an
Emancipation Proclamation and a Fifteenth Amendment, and
informed him that he was a free and independent citizen,
entitled to vote and hold office; but had at the same
time also informed him that that particular island was
his (Robinson Crusoe's) private and exclusive property.
What would have been the difference? Since Friday could
not fly up into the air nor swim off through the sea,
since if he lived at all he must live on the island, he
would have been in one case as much a slave as in the
other. Crusoe's ownership of the island would be
equivalent of his ownership of Friday. —
Social Problems
— Chapter 15, Slavery and Slavery
THEY no longer have to drive their slaves to work; want
and the fear of want do that more effectually than the
lash. They no longer have the trouble of looking out for
their employment or hiring out their labor, or the
expense of keeping them when they cannot work. That is
thrown upon the slaves. The tribute that they still wring
from labor seems like voluntary payment. In fact, they
take it as their honest share of the rewards of
production — since they furnish the land! And they
find so-called political economists, to say nothing of
so-called preachers of Christianity, to tell them so.
—
Social Problems
— Chapter 15, Slavery and Slavery
IF the two young Englishmen I have spoken of had come
over here and bought so many American citizens, they
could not have got from them so much of the produce of
labor as they now get by having bought land which
American citizens are glad to be allowed to till for half
the crop. And so, even if our laws permitted, it would be
foolish for an English duke or marquis to come over here
and contract for ten thousand American babies, born or to
be born, in the expectation that when able to work he
could get out of them a large return. For by purchasing
or fencing in a million acres of land that cannot run
away and do not need to be fed, clothed or educated, he
can, in twenty or thirty years, have ten thousand
full-grown Americans, ready to give him half of all that
their labor can produce on his land for the privilege of
supporting themselves and their families out of the other
half. This gives him more of the produce of labor than he
could exact from so many chattel slaves. —
Protection or Free Trade — Chapter 25: The
Robber That Takes All That Is Left -
econlib
OF the two systems of slavery, I think there can be no
doubt that upon the same moral level, that which makes
property of persons is more humane than that which
results from making private property of land. The
cruelties which are perpetrated under the system of
chattel slavery are more striking and arouse more
indignation because they are the conscious acts of
individuals. But for the suffering of the poor under the
more refined system no one in particular seems
responsible. . . . But this very fact permits cruelties
that would not be tolerated under the one system to pass
almost unnoticed under the other. Human beings are
overworked, are starved, are robbed of all the light and
sweetness of life, are condemned to ignorance and
brutishness, and to the infection of physical and moral
disease; are driven to crime and suicide, not by other
individuals, but by iron necessities for which it seems
that no one in particular is responsible.
To match from the annals of chattel slavery the horrors
that day after day transpire unnoticed in the heart of
Christian civilization, it would be necessary to go back
to ancient slavery, to the chronicles of Spanish conquest
in the New World, or to stories of the Middle passage.
—
Social Problems
— Chapter 15, Slavery and Slavery
THE general subjection of the many to the few, which
we meet with wherever society has reached a certain
development, has resulted from the appropriation of land
as individual property. It is the ownership of the soil
that everywhere gives the ownership of the men that live
upon it. It is slavery of this kind to which the enduring
pyramids and the colossal monuments of Egypt yet bear
witness, and of the institution of which we have,
perhaps, a vague tradition in the biblical story of the
famine during which the Pharaoh purchased up the lands of
the people. It was slavery of this kind to which, in the
twilight of history, the conquerors of Greece reduced the
original inhabitants of that peninsula, transforming them
into helots by making them pay rent for their lands. It
was the growth of the latifundia,
or great landed estates, which transmuted the population
of ancient Italy from a race of hardy husbandmen, whose
robust virtues conquered the world, into a race of
cringing bondsmen; it was the appropriation of the land
as the absolute property of their chieftains which
gradually turned the descendants of free and equal
Gallic, Teutonic and Hunnish warriors into colonii and
villains, and which changed the independent burghers of
Sclavonic village communities into the boors of Russia
and the serfs of Poland; which instituted the feudalism
of China and Japan, as well as that of Europe, and which
made the High Chiefs of Polynesia the all but absolute
masters of their fellows. How it came to pass that the
Aryan shepherds and warriors who, as comparative
philology tells us, descended from the common birth-place
of the Indo-Germanic race into the lowlands of India,
were turned into the suppliant and cringing Hindoo, the
Sanscrit verse which I have before quoted gives us a
hint. The white parasols and the elephants mad with pride
of the Indian Rajah are the flowers of grants of land.
—
Progress & Poverty
— Book VII, Chapter 1, Justice of the Remedy:
Injustice of private property in land
TRACE to their root the causes that are thus producing
want in the midst of plenty, ignorance in the midst of
intelligence, aristocracy in democracy, weakness in
strength — that are giving to our civilization a
one-sided and unstable development, and you will find it
something which this Hebrew statesman three thousand
years ago perceived and guarded against. Moses saw that
the real cause of the enslavement of the masses of Egypt
was, what has everywhere produced enslavement, the
possession by a class of the land upon which, and from
which, the whole people must live. He saw that to permit
in land the same unqualified private ownership that by
natural right attaches to the things produced by labor,
would be inevitably to separate the people into the very
rich and the very poor, inevitably to enslave labor
— to make the few the masters of. the many, no
matter what the political forms, to bring vice and
degradation, no matter what the religion.
And with the foresight of the philosophic statesman who
legislates not for the need of a day, but for all the
future, he sought, in ways suited to his times and
conditions, to guard against this error. —
Moses
THE women who by the thousands are bending over their
needles or sewing machines, thirteen, fourteen, sixteen
hours a day; these widows straining and striving to bring
up the little ones deprived of their natural
bread-winner; the children that are growing up in squalor
and wretchedness, under-clothed, under-fed,
under-educated, even in this city without any place to
play — growing up under conditions in which only a
miracle can keep them pure — under conditions which
condemn them in advance to the penitentiary or the
brothel — they suffer, they die, because we
permit them to be robbed, robbed of their birthright,
robbed by a system which disinherits the vast majority of
the children that come into the world. There is enough
and to spare for them. Had they the equal rights in the
estate which their Creator has given them, there would be
no young girls forced to unwomanly toil to eke out a mere
existence, no widows finding it such a bitter, bitter
struggle to put bread in the mouths of their little
children; no such misery and squalor as we may see here
in the greatest of American cities; misery and squalor
that are deepest in the largest and richest centers of
our civilization today. —
Thou Shalt Not Steal
THE poverty to which in advancing civilization great
masses of men are condemned, is not the freedom from
distraction and temptation which sages have sought and
philosophers have praised: it is a degrading and
embruting slavery, that cramps the higher nature, dulls
the finer feelings, and drives men by its pain to acts
which the brutes would refuse. It is into this helpless,
hopeless poverty, that crushes manhood and destroys
womanhood, that robs even childhood of its innocence and
joy, that the working classes are being driven by a force
which acts upon them like a resistless and unpitying
machine. The Boston collar manufacturer who pays his
girls two cents an hour may commiserate their condition,
but he, as they, is governed by the law of competition,
and cannot pay more and carry on his business, for
exchange is not governed by sentiment. And so, through
all intermediate gradations, up to those who receive the
earnings of labor without return, in the rent of land, it
is the inexorable laws of supply and demand, a power with
which the individual can no more quarrel or dispute than
with the winds and the tides, that seem to press down the
lower classes into the slavery of want.
But, in reality, the cause is that which always has, and
always must result in slavery — the monopolization
by some of what nature has designed for all. . . .
Private ownership of land is the nether millstone.
Material progress is the upper millstone. Between them;
with an increasing pressure, the working classes are
being ground. —
Progress & Poverty —
Book VII, Chapter 2, Justice of the Remedy: Enslavement
of laborers the ultimate result of private property in
land
IT is not in the relations of capital and labor; it is
not in the pressure of population against subsistence
that an explanation of the unequal development of our
civilization is to be found. The great cause of
inequality in the distribution of wealth is inequality in
the ownership of land. The ownership of land is the great
fundamental fact which ultimately determines the social,
the political and, consequently, the intellectual and
moral condition of a people. And it must be so. For land
is the habitation of man, the storehouse upon which he
must draw for all his needs, the material to which his
labor must be applied for the supply of all his desires;
for even the products of the sea cannot be taken, the
light of the sun enjoyed, or any of the forces of nature
utilized, without the use of land or its products. On the
land we are born, from it we live, to it we return again
— children of the soil as truly as is the blade of
grass or the flower of the field. —
Progress & Poverty
— Book V, Chapter 2: The Problem Solved: The
persistence of poverty amid advancing wealth
THERE is nothing strange or inexplicable in the phenomena
that are now perplexing the world. It is not that
material progress is not in itself a good, it is not that
nature has called into being children for whom she has
failed to provide; it is not that the Creator has left on
natural laws a taint of injustice at which even the human
mind revolts, that material progress brings such bitter
fruits. That amid our highest civilization men faint and
die with want is not due to the niggardliness of nature,
but to the injustice of man. Vice and misery, poverty and
pauperism, are not the legitimate results of increase of
population and industrial development; they only follow
increase of population and industrial development because
land is treated as private property — they are the
direct and necessary results of the violation of the
supreme law of justice, involved in giving to some men
the exclusive possession of that which nature provides
for all men. —
Progress & Poverty
— Book VII, Chapter 1, Justice of the Remedy:
Injustice of private property in land
IN the Old Testament we are told that, when the
Israelites journeyed through the desert, they were
hungered, and that God sent down out of the heavens
— manna. There was enough for all of them, and they
all took it and were relieved. But, supposing that desert
had been held as private property, as the soil of Great
Britain is held; as the soil even of our new states is
being held. Supposing that one of the Israelites had a
square mile, and another one had twenty square miles, and
another one had a hundred square miles, and the great
majority of the Israelites did not have enough to set the
soles of their feet upon, which they could call their own
— what would become of the manna? What good would
it have done to the majority? Not a whit. Though God had
sent down manna enough for all, that manna would have
been the property of the landholders; they would have
employed some of the others, perhaps, to gather it up in
heaps for them, and would have sold it to the hungry
brethren. Consider it: this purchase and sale of manna
might have gone on until the majority of the Israelites
had given up all they had, even to the clothes off their
backs. What then? Well, then they would not have had
anything left with which to buy manna, and the
consequence would have been that while they went hungry
the manna would be lying in great heaps, and the
landowners would be complaining about the over-production
of manna. There would have been a great harvest of manna
and hungry people, just precisely the Phenomenon that we
see today. — The Crime of
Poverty
PROPERTY in land, like property in slaves, is essentially
different from property in things that are the result of
labor. Rob a man or a people of money, or goods, or
cattle, and the robbery is finished there and then. The
lapse of time does not, indeed, change wrong into right,
but it obliterates the effects of the deed. That is done;
it is over; and, unless it be very soon righted, it
glides away into the past, with the men who were parties
to it, so swiftly that nothing save omniscience can trace
its effects; and in attempting to right it we would be in
danger of doing fresh wrong. The past is forever beyond
us. We can neither punish nor recompense the dead. But
rob a people of the land on which they must live, and the
robbery is continuous. It is a fresh robbery of every
succeeding generation — a new robbery every year
and every day; it is like the robbery which condemns to
slavery the children of the slave. To apply to it
the statute of limitations, to acknowledge for it the
title of prescription, is not to condone the past; it is
to legalese robbery in the present, to justify it in the
future. — The (Irish) Land
Question
AND while in the nature of things any change from
wrong-doing to right-doing must entail loss upon those
who profit by the wrong-doing, and this can no more be
prevented than can parallel lines be made to meet; yet it
must also be remembered that in the nature of things the
loss is merely relative, the gain absolute. Whoever will
examine the subject will see that in the abandonment of
the present unnatural and unjust method of raising public
revenues and the adoption of the natural and just method
even those who relatively lose will be enormous gainers.
— A Perplexed
Philosopher
(Compensation)
MANY landholders are laborers of one sort or another. And
it would be hard to find a landowner not a laborer, who
is not also a capitalist — while the general rule
is, that the larger the landowner the greater the
capitalist. So true is this that in common thought the
characters are confounded. Thus, to put all taxes on the
value of land, while it would be to largely reduce all
great fortunes, would in no case leave the rich man
penniless. The Duke of Westminster, who owns a
considerable part of the site of London, is probably the
richest landowner in the world. To take all his ground
rents by taxation would largely reduce his enormous
income, but would still leave him his buildings and all
the income from them, and doubtless much personal
property in various other shapes. He would still have all
he could by any possibility enjoy, and a much better
state of society in which to enjoy it. —
Progress & Poverty
— Book IX, Chapter 3, Effects of the Remedy: Of the
Effect Upon Individuals and Classes
THE existence of private property in land is a great
social wrong from which society at large suffers and of
which the very rich and the very poor are alike victims,
though at the opposite extremes.
Seeing this, it seems to us like a violation of Christian
charity to speak of the rich as though they individually
were responsible for the sufferings of the poor. Yet,
while you do this, you insist that the cause of monstrous
wealth and degrading poverty shall not be touched. Here
is a man with a disfiguring and dangerous excrescence.
One physician would kindly, gently, but firmly remove it.
Another insists that it shall not be removed, but at the
same time holds up the poor victim to hatred and
ridicule. Which is right- ? —
The Condition of Labor, an Open Letter to Pope Leo
XIII
...
go to "Gems from George"
Louis Post: Outlines of Louis F. Post's
Lectures, with Illustrative Notes and Charts (1894)
Note 56: The ownership of the land is
essentially the ownership of the men who must use it.
"Let the circumstances be what they may
— the ownership of land will always give the
ownership of men to a degree measured by the necessity
(real or artificial) for the use of land. Place one
hundred men on an island from which there is no escape,
and whether you make one of these men the absolute owner
of the other ninety-nine, or the absolute owner of the
soil of the island, will make no difference either to him
or to them." — Progress and Poverty, book vii, ch.
ii.
Let us imagine a shipwrecked sailor who,
after battling with the waves, touches land upon an
uninhabited but fertile island. Though hungry and naked
and shelterless, he soon has food and clothing and a
house — all of them rude, to be sure, but
comfortable. How does he get them? By applying his Labor
to the Land of the island. In a little while he lives as
comfortably as an isolated man can.
Now let another shipwrecked sailor be
washed ashore. As he is about to step out of the water
the first man accosts him:
"Hello, there! If you want to come ashore
you must agree to be my slave."
The second replies: "I can't. I come from
the United States, where they don't believe in
slavery."
"Oh, I beg your pardon. I didn't know you
came from the United States. I had no intention of
hurting your feelings, you know. But say, they believe in
owning land in the United States, don't they?"
"Yes."
"Very well; you just agree that this
island is mine, and you may come ashore a free man."
"But how does the island happen to be
yours? Did you make it?"
"No, I didn't make it."
"Have you a title from its maker?"
"No, I haven't any title from its
maker."
"Well, what is your title, anyhow?"
"Oh, my title is good enough. I got here
first."
Of course he got there first. But he
didn't mean to, and he wouldn't have done it if he could
have helped it. But the newcomer is satisfied, and
says:
"Well, that's a good United States title,
so I guess I'll recognize it and come ashore. But
remember, I am to be a free man."
"Certainly you are. Come right along up to
my cabin."
For a time the two get along well enough
together. But on some fine morning the proprietor
concludes that he would rather lie abed than scurry
around for his breakfast and not being in a good humor,
perhaps, he somewhat roughly commands his "brother man"
to cook him a bird.
"What?" exclaims the brother.
"I tell you to go and kill a bird and cook
it for my breakfast."
"That sounds big," sneers the second free
and equal member of the little community; "but what am I
to get for doing this?"
"Oh," the first replies languidly, "if you
kill me a fat bird and cook it nicely, then after I have
had my breakfast off the bird you may cook the gizzard
for your own breakfast. That's pay enough. The work is
easy."
"But I want you to understand that I am
not your slave, and I won't do that work for that pay.
I'll do as much work for you as you do for me, and no
more."
"Then, sir," the first comer shouts in
virtuous wrath, "I want you to understand that my charity
is at an end. I have treated you better than you deserved
in the past, and this is your gratitude. Now I don't
propose to have any loafers on my property. You will work
for the wages I offer or get off my land! You are
perfectly free. Take the wages or leave them. Do the work
or let it alone. There is no slavery here. But if you are
not satisfied with my terms, leave my island!"
The second man, if accustomed to the
usages of the labor unions, would probably go out and, to
the music of his own violent language about the "greed of
capital," destroy as many bows and arrows as he could, so
as to paralyze the bird-shooting industry; and this
proceeding he would call a strike for honest wages and
the dignity of labor. If he were accustomed to social
reform notions of the namby-pamby variety, he would
propose an arbitration, and be mildly indignant when told
that there was nothing to arbitrate — that he had
only to accept the other's offer or get off his property.
But if a sensible man, he would notify his comrade that
the privilege of owning islands in that latitude had
expired.
Note 57: While in the Pennsylvania coal
regions a few years ago I was told of an incident that
illustrates the power of perpetuating poverty which
resides in the absolute ownership of land.
The miners were in poverty. Despite the
lavish protection bestowed upon them by tariff laws at
the solicitation of monopolies which dictate our tariff
policy, the men were afflicted with poverty in many
forms. They were poor as to clothing, poor as to shelter,
poor as to food, and to be more specific, they were in
extreme poverty as to ice. When the summer months came
they lacked this thing because they could not afford to
buy, and they suffered.
Owing to the undermining of the ground and
the caving in of the surface here and there, there were
great holes into which the snow and the rain fell in
winter and froze, forming a passable quality of ice. Now
it is frequently said that intelligence, industry, and
thrift will abolish poverty. But these virtues were not
successful among the men of whom I speak. They were
intelligent enough to see that this ice if they saved it
would abolish their poverty as to ice, and they were
industrious enough and thrifty enough not only to be
willing to save it, but actually to begin the work.
Preparing little caves to preserve the ice in, they went
into the holes after a long day's work in the mines, and
gathered what so far as the need of ice was concerned was
to abolish their poverty in the ensuing summer. But the
owner of this part of the earth — a man who had
neither made the earth, nor the rain, nor the snow, nor
the ice, nor even the hole — telegraphed his agent
forbidding the removal of ice except upon payment of a
certain sum per ton.
The miners couldn't afford the condition.
They controlled the necessary Labor, and were willing to
give it to abolish their poverty; but the Land was placed
beyond their reach by an owner, and in consequence of
that, and not from any lack of intelligence, industry, or
thrift on their own part, their poverty as to ice was
perpetuated. ...
f. The Single Tax Retains Rent for Common
Use.
To retain Rent for common use it is not necessary to
abolish land-titles, nor to let land out to the highest
bidder, nor to invent some new mechanism of taxation, nor
in any other way to directly change existing modes of
holding land for use, or existing machinery for
collecting public revenues. "Great changes can be best
brought about under old forms."109 Let land be held
nominally as it is now. Let taxes be collected by the
same kind of machinery as now. But abolish all taxes
except those that fall upon actual and potential Rent,
that is to say, upon land values.
109. "Such dupes are men to custom, and
so prone
To rev'rence what is ancient and can plead
A course of long observance for its use,
That even servitude, the worst of ills,
Because delivered down from sire to son
Is kept and guarded as a sacred thing."
—Cowper.
It is only custom that makes the
ownership of land seem reasonable. I have frequently
had occasion to tell of the necessity under which the
city of Cleveland, Ohio, found itself, of paying a
land-owner several thousand dollars for the right to
swing a bridge-draw over his land. When I described the
matter in that way, the story attracted no attention;
it seemed perfectly reasonable to the ordinary lecture
audience. But when I described the transaction as a
payment by the city to a land-owner of thousands of
dollars for the privilege of swinging the draw "through
that man's air," the audience invariably manifested its
appreciation of the absurdity of such an ownership. The
idea of owning air was ridiculous; the idea of owning
land was not. Yet who can explain the difference,
except as a matter of custom?
To the same effect was the question of
the Rev. F. L. Higgins to a friend. While stationed at
Galveston, Tex., Mr. Higgins fell into a discussion
with his friend as to the right of government to make
land private property. The friend argued that no matter
what the abstract right might be, the government had
made private property of land, and people had bought
and sold upon the strength of the government title, and
therefore land titles were morally absolute.
"Suppose," said Mr. Higgins, "that the
government should vest in a corporation title to the
Gulf of Mexico, so that no one could fish there, or
sail there, or do anything in or upon the waters of the
Gulf without permission from the corporation. Would
that be right?"
"No," answered the friend.
"Well, suppose the corporation should
then parcel out the Gulf to different parties until
some of the people came to own the whole Gulf to the
exclusion of everybody else, born and unborn. Could any
such title be acquired by these purchasers, or their
descendants or assignees, as that the rest of the
people if they got the power would not have a moral
right to abrogate it?"
"Certainly not," said the friend.
"Could private titles to the Gulf
possibly become absolute in morals?"
"No."
"Then tell me," asked Mr. Higgins, "what
difference it would make if all the water were taken
off the Gulf and only the bare land left."
If that were done it is doubtful if land-owners could
any longer confiscate enough Rent to be worth the
trouble. Even though some surplus were still kept by
them, it would be so much more easy to secure Wealth by
working for it than by confiscating Rent to private use,
to say nothing of its being so much more respectable,
that speculation in land values would practically be
abandoned. At any rate, the question of a surplus —
Rent in excess of the requirements of the community
— may be readily determined when the principle that
Rent justly belongs to the community and Wages to the
individual shall have been recognized by society in the
adoption of the Single Tax. 110
110. Thomas G. Shearman, Esq., of New
York, author of the famous magazine article on "Who
Owns the United States," estimates that sixty-five per
cent of the present annual value of the land in the
United States would pay all the present expenses of
American government — federal, state, county, and
municipal. ...
Q32. Is not ownership of land necessary to induce
its improvement? Does not history show that private
ownership is a step in advance of common
ownership?
A. No. Private use was doubtless a step in advance of
common use. And because private use seems to us to have
been brought about under the institution of private
ownership, private ownership appears to the superficial
to have been the real advance. But a little observation
and reflection will remove that impression. Private
ownership of land is not necessary to its private use.
And so far from inducing improvement, private ownership
retards it. When a man owns land he may accumulate wealth
by doing nothing with the land, simply allowing the
community to increase its value while he pays a merely
nominal tax, upon the plea that he gets no income from
the property. But when the possessor has to pay the value
of his land every year, as he would have to under the
single tax, and as ground renters do now, he must improve
his holding in order to profit by it. Private possession
of land, without profit except from use, promotes
improvement; private ownership, with profit regardless of
use, retards improvement. Every city in the world, in its
vacant lots, offers proof of the statement. It is the
lots that are owned, and not those that are held upon
ground-lease, that remain vacant.
Q52. Is not the right of ownership of a gold ring
the same as the ownership of a gold mine? and if the
latter is wrong is not the former also wrong?
A. If it be wrong for you to own the spring of water
which you and your fellows use, is it therefore wrong for
you to own the water that you lift from the spring to
drink? If so how do you propose to slake your thirst? If
you argue in reply that it is not wrong for you to own
the spring, then how shall your fellows slake their
thirst when you treat them, as you would have a right to,
as trespassers upon your property? To own the source of
labor products is to own the labor of others; to own what
you produce from that source is to own only your own
labor. Nature furnishes gold mines, but men fashion gold
rings. The right of ownership is radically different.
Q62. If the ownership of land is immoral is it not
the duty of individuals who see its immorality to refrain
from profiting by it?
A. No. The immorality is institutional, not individual.
Every member of a community has a right to land and an
interest in the rent of land. Under the single tax both
rights would be conserved. But under existing social
institutions the only way of securing either is to own
land and profit by it. To refrain from doing so would
have no reformatory effect. It is one of the
eccentricities of narrow minds to believe or profess to
believe that institutional wrongs and individual wrongs
are upon the same plane and must be cured in the same way
— by individual reformation. But individuals cannot
change institutions by refraining from profiting by them,
any more than they could dredge a creek by refraining
from swimming in it. Institutional wrongs must be
remedied by institutional reforms. ... read the book
Charles B. Fillebrown: A Catechism of
Natural Taxation, from Principles of Natural
Taxation (1917)
Q12. Did not Henry George believe in the abolition
of private property in land?
A. Assuredly not. If he did, why was it that he suggested
no modification whatever of present land tenure or
"estate in land"? If he did, how could he have said that
the sole "sovereign" and sufficient remedy for the wrongs
of private property in land was "to appropriate rent by
taxation"? ... read the whole
article
Arthur J. Ogilvy: A Colonist's Plea
for Land Nationalization (about 1890)
LET us begin by taking the unearned increment in its
simplest and clearest form.
Suppose I buy Government land at £1 per acre, and
quietly holding on while roads are being pushed forward,
settlement extending and land values rising, refuse offer
after offer till the price reaches £2, when I sell
out. Of these £2, one I have acquired by direct
purchase; £1 worth of money for £1 worth of
land; but the other I have done nothing to acquire.
It is not interest on the purchase-money, for interest is
payment for the use of capital, and comes out of the use.
Who would expect interest on money tied up in an old rag?
There has been no use here.
It is not compensation for risk, for the land could not
disappear or deteriorate, and was sure to be
wanted.
It may be quite right for all that, that I should have
it. That is not the point at present. The point at
present is simply to explain the term, and to show not
only what it directly means, but what it indirectly
implies, for it implies a great deal much more than most
people have any idea of.
I have neither done anything to create this increase of
value nor rendered any service in return for it. If a
sovereign were suddenly to drop into my pocket from the
sky, it would not be more completely unearned.
But it has not only been unearned. If that were all, it
would be no great matter. If, like the sovereign, it had
dropped from the sky, then, though I might be
undeservedly the richer nobody else would be the poorer.
My gain would be a clear addition to the sum total of
human wealth, out of which others besides myself would in
one way or another derive benefit; and, whether or no
whatever benefits one without injuring another is fair
subject for congratulation.
But it has not only been unearned; it has been drawn from
the earnings of others. My gain is others' loss.
...
No doubt there are many other things besides land in
which a monopoly of the article will enable the possessor
to levy something resembling blackmail; but there are
points of difference that distinguish them all from the
pure and simple appropriation of land monopoly.
The first is that none of them excludes other people from
making a living or from making earnings to any extent by
other means than the article monopolised.
If by a day's labour or by pure accident I find a
diamond, I may ask a price entirely disproportionate to
the value of my labour; but then the public need not buy
my diamond unless they like. My finding a diamond does
not prevent other people from looking for diamonds with
as much chance of finding them as I had, and, if they
don't think they are likely to find any by looking for
them they can go without, and be none the worse.
But every piece of land appropriated shuts out so many
other people from that land, and as all the land
(practically speaking) is appropriated, or in one way or
another out of reach of the masses, they are at the mercy
of the landholders, and have no choice but either to rent
it from them as tenants or work for them as labourers on
the hardest terms to which competition can drive them;
which means that the landowner has the power of
appropriating the greater part of their earnings in
return for the mere permission to them to earn
anything.
Or suppose that, instead of finding a diamond, I buy tin,
and that next week the price goes up to double here there
is an additional distinction between my gains and the
land speculator's; for not only are the public under no
compulsion to buy tin (while they are to rent land), and
not only does tin represent the results of labour, and so
represent earnings (which land does not), but the
magnitude of my gain in most cases represents
compensation for great risk.
The earnings of farmers and of miners may average the
same, but the farmers' average is made up of pretty equal
profits all round, while the miners' average is made up
of a few big prizes and many blanks. And what applies to
the miner applies also to the speculator in mining
products. His occasional large profits represent
compensation for great risks, and is thus as much of the
nature of insurance as of profit.
No one would think of either mining or speculating in
mining products, unless the many blanks were compensated
by occasional large prizes. They are the necessary
inducements to engage in those callings, and therefore
fair earnings when they come. Land, however, is not a
speculation in this sense (though even if it were, its
profits would still be appropriation and not earnings for
reasons already given); it is a sure investment in the
sense that it is subject to no extraordinary risks: to no
more risks, that is, than such as are inseparable from
all human enterprise, even the safest. ... read the whole
paper.
|
To share this page with a friend:
right click, choose "send," and add your
comments.
|
|
Red links have not been
visited; .
Green links are pages you've seen
|
Essential Documents pertinent
to this theme:
essential_documents
|
|