Incentives
I have friends who take great pains to conserve water
and nonrenewable energy, and I admire them. And yet I
find myself troubled by the extent to which they expend
their personal thought and energy to "act locally" under
circumstances where at the societal level the biggest
users of water and energy have no particular incentive to
behave similarly. (Household water use represents perhaps
1% of national consumption.) Until we manage to align our
incentives with what we as a society want to achieve, the
sacrifices of principled individuals will be overshadowed
by the advantage taken by others off whom the pressure is
taken.
What do we want to reward? What do we want to
discourage? How does our system of taxation align with
that?
Land, unlike labor and capital, is in fixed supply,
and some land is far more desirable than other land. Who
is entitled to the value of the land? Are some of us more
entitled than others? What entitled some to it?
Henry George: The
Common Sense of Taxation (1881 article)
Evidently this regard for the general good is the true
principle of taxation. The more it is examined the more
clearly it will be seen that there is no valid reason why
we should, in any case, attempt to tax all property. That
equality should be the rule and aim of taxation is true,
and this for the reason given in the Declaration of
Independence, that all men are created equal. But
equality does not require that all men should be taxed
alike, or that all things should be taxed alike. It
merely requires that whatever taxes are imposed shall be
equally imposed upon the persons or things in like
conditions or situations; it merely requires that no
citizen shall be given an advantage, or put at a
disadvantage, as compared with other citizens.
The true purposes of government are well stated in the
preamble to the Constitution of the United States, as
they are in the Declaration of Independence. To insure
the general peace, to promote the general welfare, to
secure to each individual the inalienable rights to life,
liberty, and the pursuit of happiness — these are
the proper ends of government, and are therefore the ends
which in every scheme of taxation should be kept in mind.
...
And the reason of this difference is clear. The
possession of wealth is the inducement to the exertion
necessary to the production and maintenance of wealth.
Men do not work for the pleasure of working, but to get
the things their work will give them. And to tax the
things that are produced by exertion is to lessen the
inducement to exertion. But over and above the benefit to
the possessor, which is the stimulating motive to the
production of wealth, there is a benefit to the
community, for no matter how selfish he may be, it is
utterly impossible for any one to entirely keep to
himself the benefit of any desirable thing he may
possess. These diffused benefits when localized
give value to land, and this may be taxed without in any
wise diminishing the incentive to production.
... read the whole
article
H.G. Brown: Significant
Paragraphs from Henry George's Progress &
Poverty: 10. Effect of Remedy Upon Wealth
Production (in the unabridged P&P:
Part IX — Effects of the Remedy: Chapter 1 — Of
the effect upon the production of wealth)
Consider the effect upon the production of wealth.
To abolish the taxation which, acting and reacting,
now hampers every wheel of exchange and presses upon
every form of industry, would be like removing an immense
weight from a powerful spring. Imbued with fresh energy,
production would start into new life, and trade would
receive a stimulus which would be felt to the remotest
arteries. The present method of taxation operates upon
exchange like artificial deserts and mountains;
- it costs more to get goods through a custom house
than it does to carry them around the world.
- It operates upon energy, and industry, and skill,
and thrift, like a fine upon those qualities.
- If I have worked harder and built myself a good
house while you have been contented to live in a hovel,
the taxgatherer now comes annually to make me pay a
penalty for my energy and industry, by taxing me more
than you.
- If I have saved while you wasted, I am mulct, while
you are exempt.
- If a man build a ship we make him pay for his
temerity, as though he had done an injury to the
state;
- if a railroad be opened, down comes the tax
collector upon it, as though it were a public
nuisance;
- if a manufactory be erected we levy upon it an
annual sum which would go far toward making a handsome
profit.
- We say we want capital, but if any one accumulate
it, or bring it among us, we charge him for it as
though we were giving him a privilege.
- We punish with a tax the man who covers barren
fields with ripening grain,
- we fine him who puts up machinery, and him who
drains a swamp.
How heavily these taxes burden production only those
realize who have attempted to follow our system of
taxation through its ramifications, for, as I have before
said, the heaviest part of taxation is that which falls
in increased prices.
To abolish these taxes would be to lift the whole
enormous weight of taxation from productive industry. The
needle of the seamstress and the great manufactory; the
cart horse and the locomotive; the fishing boat and the
steamship; the farmer's plow and the merchant's stock,
would be alike untaxed. All would be free to make or to
save, to buy or to sell, unfined by taxes, unannoyed by
the taxgatherer. Instead of saying to the producer, as it
does now, "The more you add to the general wealth the
more shall you be taxed!" the state would say to the
producer, "Be as industrious, as thrifty, as enterprising
as you choose, you shall have your full reward! You shall
not be fined for making two blades of grass grow where
one grew before; you shall not be taxed for adding to the
aggregate wealth."
And will not the community gain by thus refusing to
kill the goose that lays the golden eggs; by thus
refraining from muzzling the ox that treadeth out the
corn; by thus leaving to industry, and thrift, and skill,
their natural reward, full and unimpaired? For there is
to the community also a natural reward. The law of
society is, each for all, as well as all for each. No one
can keep to himself the good he may do, any more than he
can keep the bad. Every productive enterprise, besides
its return to those who undertake it, yields collateral
advantages to others. If a man plant a fruit tree, his
gain is that he gathers the fruit in its time and season.
But in addition to his gain, there is a gain to the whole
community. Others than the owner are benefited by the
increased supply of fruit; the birds which it shelters
fly far and wide; the rain which it helps to attract
falls not alone on his field; and, even to the eye which
rests upon it from a distance, it brings a sense of
beauty. And so with everything else. The building of a
house, a factory, a ship, or a railroad, benefits others
besides those who get the direct profits.
... Well may the community leave to the individual
producer all that prompts him to exertion; well may it
let the laborer have the full reward of his labor, and
the capitalist the full return of his capital. For the
more that labor and capital produce, the greater grows
the common wealth in which all may share. And in the
value or rent of land is this general gain expressed in a
definite and concrete form. Here is a fund which the
state may take while leaving to labor and capital their
full reward. With increased activity of production this
would commensurately increase.
And to shift the burden of taxation from production
and exchange to the value or rent of land would not
merely be to give new stimulus to the production of
wealth; it would be to open new opportunities. For under
this system no one would care to hold land unless to use
it, and land now withheld from use would everywhere be
thrown open to improvement.
The selling price of land would fall; land speculation
would receive its death blow; land monopolization would
no longer pay.* Millions and millions of acres from which
settlers are now shut out by high prices would be
abandoned by their present owners or sold to settlers
upon nominal terms. And this not merely on the frontiers,
but within what are now considered well settled
districts.
* The fact that a tax on the rental value
of land cannot be shifted by landowners to tenants,
though recognized by all competent economists, is
sometimes a stumbling block to persons untrained in
economics. The reason such a tax cannot be shifted is
that it cannot limit the supply of land. Landowners are
presumably, before the tax is laid, charging all the
rent they can get. There is nothing in a tax on the
rental value of land to make tenants willing to pay
more or to make land more difficult to hire. On the
contrary, more land will be on the market, because of
such a tax, rather than less, since the tax puts a
heavy penalty on holding land out of use and unimproved
for mere speculation. The competition of former vacant
land speculators to get their land used will make land
cheaper to rent rather than more expensive. And since
only the net rent remaining after the tax is subtracted
is capitalized into salable value, land will be very
much cheaper to buy. H.G.B.
And it must be remembered that this would apply, not
merely to agricultural land, but to all land. Mineral
land would be thrown open to use, just as agricultural
land; and in the heart of a city no one could afford to
keep land from its most profitable use, or on the
outskirts to demand more for it than the use to which it
could at the time be put would warrant. Everywhere that
land had attained a value, taxation, instead of
operating, as now, as a fine upon improvement, would
operate to force improvement. Whoever planted an orchard,
or sowed a field, or built a house, or erected a
manufactory, no matter how costly, would have no more to
pay in taxes than if he kept so much land idle.
- The monopolist of agricultural land would be taxed
as much as though his land were covered with houses and
barns, with crops and with stock.
- The owner of a vacant city lot would have to pay as
much for the privilege of keeping other people off of
it until he wanted to use it, as his neighbor who has a
fine house upon his lot.
- It would cost as much to keep a row of tumble-down
shanties upon valuable land as though it were covered
with a grand hotel or a pile of great warehouses filled
with costly goods.
Thus, the bonus that wherever labor is most productive
must now be paid before labor can be exerted would
disappear.
- The farmer would not have to pay out half his
means, or mortgage his labor for years, in order to
obtain land to cultivate;
- the builder of a city homestead would not have to
lay out as much for a small lot as for the house he
puts upon it*;
- the company that proposed to erect a manufactory
would not have to expend a great part of its capital
for a site.
- And what would be paid from year to year to the
state would be in lieu of all the taxes now levied upon
improvements, machinery, and stock.
*Many persons, and among them some
professional economists, have never succeeded in
getting a thorough comprehension of this point. Thus,
the editor has heard the objection advanced that the
greater cheapness of land is no advantage to the poor
man who is trying to save enough from his earnings to
buy a piece of land; for, it is said, the higher
taxes on the land after it is acquired, offset the
lower purchase price. What such objectors do not see
is that even if the lower price of land does no more
than balance the higher tax on it, (and this
overlooks, for one thing, the discouragement to
speculation in land), the reduction or removal of
other taxes is all clear gain. It is easier to save
in proportion as earnings and commodities are
relieved of taxation. It is easier to buy land,
because its selling price is lower, if the land is
taxed. And although the land, after its purchase,
continues to be taxed, not only can this tax be fully
paid out of the annual interest on the saving in the
purchase price, but also there is to be reckoned the
saving in taxes on buildings and other improvements
and in whatever other taxes are thus rendered
unnecessary. H.G.B.
Consider the effect of such a change upon the labor
market. Competition would no longer be one-sided, as now.
Instead of laborers competing with each other for
employment, and in their competition cutting down wages
to the point of bare subsistence, employers would
everywhere be competing for laborers, and wages would
rise to the fair earnings of labor. For into the labor
market would have entered the greatest of all competitors
for the employment of labor, a competitor whose demand
cannot be satisfied until want is satisfied — the
demand of labor itself. The employers of labor would not
have merely to bid against other employers, all feeling
the stimulus of greater trade and increased profits, but
against the ability of laborers to become their own
employers upon the natural opportunities freely opened to
them by the tax which prevented monopolization.
With natural opportunities thus free to labor;
- with capital and improvements exempt from tax, and
exchange released from restrictions, the spectacle of
willing men unable to turn their labor into the things
they are suffering for would become impossible;
- the recurring paroxysms which paralyze industry
would cease;
- every wheel of production would be set in
motion;
- demand would keep pace with supply, and supply with
demand;
- trade would increase in every direction, and wealth
augment on every hand. ... read the whole
chapter
Henry George:
Concentrations of Wealth Harm America
(excerpt from Social
Problems)
(1883)
I am not denouncing the rich, nor seeking, by
speaking of these things, to excite envy and hatred; but
if we would get a clear understanding of social problems,
we must recognize the fact that it is due
- to monopolies which we permit and
create,
- to advantages which we give one man over
another,
- to methods of extortion sanctioned by law and
by public opinion,
that some men are enabled to get so enormously
rich while others remain so miserably poor. If we look around us and note the elements of
monopoly, extortion and spoliation which go to the
building up of all, or nearly all, fortunes, we see on
the one hand now disingenuous are those who preach to us
that there is nothing wrong in social relations and that
the inequalities in the distribution of wealth spring
from the inequalities of human nature; and on the other
hand, we see how wild are those who talk as though
capital were a public enemy, and propose plans for
arbitrarily restricting the acquisition of wealth.
Capital is a good; the capitalist is a
helper, if he is not also a monopolist. We can safely let
any one get as rich as he can if he will not despoil
others in doing so. There are deep wrongs
in the present constitution of society, but they are not
wrongs inherent in the constitution of man nor in those
social laws which are as truly the laws of the Creator as
are the laws of the physical universe. They are
wrongs resulting from bad adjustments which it is within
our power to amend. The ideal social
state is not that in which each gets an equal amount of
wealth, but in which each gets in proportion to his
contribution to the general stock. And in such a social state there would not be less
incentive to exertion than now; there would be far more
incentive. Men will be more industrious and more
moral, better workmen and better citizens, if each takes
his earnings and carries them home to his family, than
where they put their earnings in a "pot" and gamble for
them until some have far more than they could have
earned, and others have little or nothing.
...
Read the entire
article
Louis Post: Outlines
of Louis F. Post's Lectures, with Illustrative Notes and
Charts (1894)
4. CONFORMITY TO GENERAL PRINCIPLES
OF TAXATION
The single tax conforms most closely to the essential
principles of Adam Smith's four classical maxims, which
are stated best by Henry George 19 as follows:
The best tax by which public revenues can be raised is
evidently that which will closest conform to the
following conditions:
- That it bear as lightly as possible upon production
— so as least to check the increase of the
general fund from which taxes must be paid and the
community maintained. 20
- That it be easily and cheaply collected, and fall
as directly as may be upon the ultimate payers —
so as to take from the people as little as possible in
addition to what it yields the government. 21
- That it be certain — so as to give the least
opportunity for tyranny or corruption on the part of
officials, and the least temptation to law-breaking and
evasion on the part of the tax-payers. 22
- That it bear equally — so as to give no
citizen an advantage or put any at a disadvantage, as
compared with others. 23
a. Interference with Production
Indirect taxes tend to check production and cause
scarcity, by obstructing the processes of production.
They fall upon men as they work, as
they do business, as they invest capital
productively. 24 But the single tax, which must
be paid and be the same in amount regardless of whether
the payer works or plays, of whether he invests his
capital productively or wastes it, of whether he uses his
land for the most productive purposes 25 or in lesser
degree or not at all, removes fiscal penalties from
industry and thrift, and tends to leave production free.
It therefore conforms more closely than indirect taxation
to the first maxim quoted above.
24. "Taxation which falls upon the
processes of production interposes an artificial
obstacle to the creation of wealth. Taxation which
falls upon labor as it is exerted, wealth as it is used
as capital, land as it is cultivated, will manifestly
tend to discourage production much more powerfully than
taxation to the same amount levied upon laborers
whether they work or play, upon wealth whether used
productively or unproductively, or upon land whether
cultivated or left waste" — Progress and
Poverty, book viii, ch. iii, subd. I.
25. It is common, besides taxing
improvements, as fast as they are made, to levy higher
taxes upon land when put to its best use than when put
to partial use or to no use at all. This is upon the
theory that when his land is used the owner gets full
income from it and can afford to pay high taxes; but
that he gets little or no income when the land is out
of use, and so cannot afford to pay much. It is an
absurd but perfectly legitimate illustration of the
pretentious doctrine of taxation according to ability
to pay.
Examples are numerous. Improved building
lots, and even those that are only plotted for
improvement, are usually taxed more than contiguous
unused and unplotted land which is equally in demand
for building purposes and equally valuable. So coal
land, iron land, oil land, and sugar land are as a rule
taxed less as land when opened up for appropriate use
than when lying idle or put to inferior uses, though
the land value be the same. Any serious proposal to put
land to its appropriate use is commonly regarded as a
signal for increasing the tax upon it.
...
d. Equality
In respect of the fourth maxim the single tax bears
more equally— that is to say, more justly —
than any other tax. It is the only tax that falls upon
the taxpayer in proportion to the pecuniary benefits he
receives from the public; 29 and its tendency,
accelerating with the increase of the tax, is to leave
every one the full fruit of his own productive enterprise
and effort. 30
29 The benefits of government are
not the only public benefits whose value attaches
exclusively to land. Communal development from whatever
cause produces the same effect. But as it is under the
protection of government that land-owners are able to
maintain ownership of land and through that to enjoy
the pecuniary benefits of advancing social conditions,
government confers upon them as a class not only the
pecuniary benefits of good government but also the
pecuniary benefits of progress in general.
30. "Here are two men of equal
incomes — that of the one derived from the
exertion of his labor, that of the other from the rent
of land. Is it just that they should equally contribute
to the expenses of the state? Evidently not. The income
of the one represents wealth he creates and adds to the
general wealth of the state; the income of the other
represents merely wealth that he takes from the general
stock, returning nothing." — Progress and
Poverty, book viii, ch. iii, subd. 4. ...
f. The Single Tax Retains Rent for Common
Use.
To retain Rent for common use it is not necessary to
abolish land-titles, nor to let land out to the highest
bidder, nor to invent some new mechanism of taxation, nor
in any other way to directly change existing modes of
holding land for use, or existing machinery for
collecting public revenues. "Great changes can be best
brought about under old forms."109 Let land be held
nominally as it is now. Let taxes be collected by the
same kind of machinery as now. But abolish all taxes
except those that fall upon actual and potential Rent,
that is to say, upon land values.
109. "Such dupes are men to custom, and
so prone
To rev'rence what is ancient and can plead
A course of long observance for its use,
That even servitude, the worst of ills,
Because delivered down from sire to son
Is kept and guarded as a sacred thing."
—Cowper.
It is only custom that makes the
ownership of land seem reasonable. I have frequently
had occasion to tell of the necessity under which the
city of Cleveland, Ohio, found itself, of paying a
land-owner several thousand dollars for the right to
swing a bridge-draw over his land. When I described the
matter in that way, the story attracted no attention;
it seemed perfectly reasonable to the ordinary lecture
audience. But when I described the transaction as a
payment by the city to a land-owner of thousands of
dollars for the privilege of swinging the draw "through
that man's air," the audience invariably manifested its
appreciation of the absurdity of such an ownership. The
idea of owning air was ridiculous; the idea of owning
land was not. Yet who can explain the difference,
except as a matter of custom?
To the same effect was the question of
the Rev. F. L. Higgins to a friend. While stationed at
Galveston, Tex., Mr. Higgins fell into a discussion
with his friend as to the right of government to make
land private property. The friend argued that no matter
what the abstract right might be, the government had
made private property of land, and people had bought
and sold upon the strength of the government title, and
therefore land titles were morally absolute.
"Suppose," said Mr. Higgins, "that the
government should vest in a corporation title to the
Gulf of Mexico, so that no one could fish there, or
sail there, or do anything in or upon the waters of the
Gulf without permission from the corporation. Would
that be right?"
"No," answered the friend.
"Well, suppose the corporation should
then parcel out the Gulf to different parties until
some of the people came to own the whole Gulf to the
exclusion of everybody else, born and unborn. Could any
such title be acquired by these purchasers, or their
descendants or assignees, as that the rest of the
people if they got the power would not have a moral
right to abrogate it?"
"Certainly not," said the friend.
"Could private titles to the Gulf
possibly become absolute in morals?"
"No."
"Then tell me," asked Mr. Higgins, "what
difference it would make if all the water were taken
off the Gulf and only the bare land left."
If that were done it is doubtful if land-owners could
any longer confiscate enough Rent to be worth the
trouble. Even though some surplus were still kept by
them, it would be so much more easy to secure Wealth by
working for it than by confiscating Rent to private use,
to say nothing of its being so much more respectable,
that speculation in land values would practically be
abandoned. At any rate, the question of a surplus —
Rent in excess of the requirements of the community
— may be readily determined when the principle that
Rent justly belongs to the community and Wages to the
individual shall have been recognized by society in the
adoption of the Single Tax. 110
110. Thomas G. Shearman, Esq., of New
York, author of the famous magazine article on "Who
Owns the United States," estimates that sixty-five per
cent of the present annual value of the land in the
United States would pay all the present expenses of
American government — federal, state, county, and
municipal. ...
Q32. Is not ownership of land necessary to induce
its improvement? Does not history show that private
ownership is a step in advance of common
ownership?
A. No. Private use was doubtless a step in advance of
common use. And because private use seems to us to have
been brought about under the institution of private
ownership, private ownership appears to the superficial
to have been the real advance. But a little observation
and reflection will remove that impression. Private
ownership of land is not necessary to its private use.
And so far from inducing improvement, private ownership
retards it. When a man owns land he may accumulate wealth
by doing nothing with the land, simply allowing the
community to increase its value while he pays a merely
nominal tax, upon the plea that he gets no income from
the property. But when the possessor has to pay the value
of his land every year, as he would have to under the
single tax, and as ground renters do now, he must improve
his holding in order to profit by it. Private possession
of land, without profit except from use, promotes
improvement; private ownership, with profit regardless of
use, retards improvement. Every city in the world, in its
vacant lots, offers proof of the statement. It is the
lots that are owned, and not those that are held upon
ground-lease, that remain vacant.
Q48. Would you let money escape taxation, and so
favor money lenders?
A. It is a curious fact that this question is most
popular among people who clamor for cheap money. How they
expect to cheapen money by taxing its lenders on their
loans is past finding out. To tax money lenders is to
discourage money lending, and thereby to increase
interest on loans. Yes, we should let money escape
taxation. It escapes taxation now, which in itself is a
politic reason for exempting it; but we should exempt it
(by taxing nothing but land values) for the additional
and better reason that a man's money is his own and the
community has no right to it, while a man's land value is
the community's and the man has no right to it. This
would not favor money lenders in any invidious sense. It
would favor both lenders and borrowers; borrowers by
enabling them to borrow on easier terms, and lenders by
making their loans more secure. ... read the book
Charles B. Fillebrown: A Catechism of Natural
Taxation, from Principles of Natural Taxation
(1917)
Q19. Why should buildings and all other
improvements and personal property and capital be exempt
from taxes?
A. Because a tax on them falls upon industry, and so
increases the cost of living, while continuing the
invidious exemption of the present net land value.
Q50. How could the landowner escape the alleged
burden of an increase in his land tax?
A. Simply by assuming the legitimate role of a model
landlord, by putting his land to suitable use, in
providing for tenants at lowest possible price the best
accommodations and facilities appropriate to the
situation that money can buy. ... read the whole
article
Weld Carter: An
Introduction to Henry George
However, what is the effect on production of taxes
levied on products and of taxes levied on the value of
land?
Of taxes levied on products, George
said: "The present method of taxation operates upon
exchange like artificial deserts and mountains; it costs
more to get goods through a custom house than it does to
carry them around the world. It operates upon energy, and
industry, and skill, and thrift, like a fine upon those
qualities. If I have worked harder and built myself a good
house while you have been contented to live in a hovel, the
taxgatherer now comes annually to make me pay a penalty for
my energy and industry, by taxing me more than you. If I
have saved while you wasted, I am mulct, while you are
exempt. If a man build a ship we make him pay for his
temerity, as though he had done an injury to the state; if
a railroad be opened, down comes the taxcollector upon it,
as though it were a public nuisance; if a manufactory be
erected we levy upon it an annual sum which would go far
toward making a handsome profit. We say we want capital,
but if anyone accumulate it, or bring it among us, we
charge him for it as though we were giving him a privilege.
We punish with a tax the man who covers barren fields with
ripening grain, we fine him who puts up machinery, and him
who drains a swamp. How heavily these taxes burden
production only those realize who have attempted to follow
our system of taxation through its ramifications, for, as I
have before said, the heaviest part of taxation is that
which falls in increased prices."
Turning to taxation levied on the
value of land, George went on to say:
For this simple device of placing all
taxes on the value of land would be in effect putting up
the land at auction to whosoever would pay the highest rent
to the state. The demand for land fixes its value, and
hence, if taxes were placed so as very nearly to consume
that value, the man who wished to hold land without using
it would have to pay very nearly what it would be worth to
anyone who wanted to use it.
And it must be remembered that this
would apply, not merely to agricultural land, but to all
land. Mineral land would be thrown open to use, just as
agricultural land; and in the heart of a city no one could
afford to keep land from its most profitable use, or on the
outskirts to demand more for it than the use to which it
could at the time be put would warrant. Everywhere that
land had attained a value, taxation, instead of operating,
as now, as a fine upon improvement, would operate to force
improvement (1879, rpt. 1958, p. 437).
A few pages before this he had told
us that, "It is sufficiently evident that with regard to
production, the tax upon the value of land is the best tax
that can be imposed. Tax manufactures, and the effect is to
check manufacturing; tax improvements, and the effect is to
lessen improvement; tax commerce, and the effect is to
prevent exchange; tax capital, and the effect is to drive
it away. But the whole value of land may be taken in
taxation, and the only effect will be to stimulate
industry, to open new opportunities to capital, and to
increase the production of wealth" (1879, rpt. 1958, p.
414).
In other words, according to George,
taxation of products checks production, whereas taxation of
land values stimulates production. ... read the
whole article
Bill Batt: Stemming
Sprawl: The Fiscal Approach
Stemming Sprawl: Command-and-Control
Measures
Policymakers have two modes of leverage by which to
implement public will: 1) so-called command-and-control
approaches that are typically enforced by what state and
federal constitutions group under "police powers" and 2)
fiscal approaches that typically involve a variety of
taxes, fees, fines, and other charges that derive
constitutionally from either police powers or "tax
powers." When governments administer either of these
powers, they are legitimate and authoritative. Fiscal
measures available to governments can come from either
ground. The charges that the private sector usually
impose differ in that they usually are responsive to
market forces. Prices that are established by government,
however, are not necessarily responsive to market forces,
nor are they intended to be. Rather, they are set in
order to accomplish specific public policy
goals.[19] They can be
no less efficient, however, when responsibly
instituted.
19. One recent exploration of this is a
chapter titled "Catalytic Government: Steering Rather
Than Rowing," in Reinventing Government: How the
Entrepreneurial Spirit Is Transforming the Public
Sector, ed. David Osborne and Ted Gaebler (New York:
Penguin, 1993).
Governments face the challenge of knowing which of the
tools at their disposal — command-and-control
approaches or "pricing" approaches — will best
serve effective and efficient achievement of public
policies. Only in recent years, however, has there been a
renewed interest in fiscal levers to achieve goals that
policymakers seek to achieve. There is particular
interest among students of welfare economics in
incorporating costs earlier regarded as externalities,
especially in designing environmental policies. Moreover,
the use of pricing approaches to recover costs of
government services that have a high level of private
good about them can bring about more attractive and
achievable goals than reliance on conventional police
power approaches. User fees, environmental fees, and
other such fiscal tools have become more fascinating
— at least to students of public policy —
than conventional taxes.
The renewed interest in fiscal approaches comes in
recognition of the fact that traditional
command-and-control approaches have not been successful.
Government authority is far more effective at prohibiting
and controlling than it is inducing and
channeling.[20] Three
illustrations of failed command-and-control approaches
will demonstrate this: zoning, urban growth boundaries,
and altering (usually expanding) political jurisdictions.
... read the whole
article
Fred E. Foldvary — The Ultimate Tax Reform: Public
Revenue from Land Rent
Impact on behavior
Income taxes impose on the economy a large
administrative cost by government and a cost to payers of
filling out forms, paying lawyers and accountants, and
trying to comprehend the complex requirements. The
compliance cost of lost time in the U.S. is 5 billion
hours per year, the equivalent of two million people
working full time just to process the income tax. In
dollar terms, the compliance cost is estimated to be more
than $200 billion per year.29
Reformers who want to impose a national retail sales
tax are well aware of the substantial impact taxes have
on human behavior. That, indeed, is often why such
reforms are proposed: The reformer wishes to discourage
borrowing, reduce consumption, or encourage savings, for
example. But moving to a national retail sales tax
results in little improvement.
Most people use their wage income to pay for goods and
services and sales taxes. Switching from an income to a
sales tax is like taxing you when you leave a room
instead of when you enter the room.
Income taxes punish savings, but sales taxes punish
borrowing. If you borrow $10,000 to buy a car and there
is a 20 percent sales tax, you need to borrow an extra
$2,000 to pay the tax. Some folks might decide to not buy
the car, spending the $10,000 on something else, without
borrowing $2,000.
There is no good economic reason to tax-punish
consumption or borrowing. The purpose of production is
consumption! If we punish consumption, we punish
production. Consumption is not an evil to be thwarted,
but the very benefit we get from the economy. We may as
well also tax fun and joy! Those seeking to tax
consumption act as though they have a Puritan streak that
considers enjoying goods to be evil and working and
saving to be good for their own sake.
Tapping rent or land value, by contrast, avoids the
manipulation of an individual’s choice to save or
borrow, consume or invest. A well-constructed land value
levy has no distortive effect at all on human action or
decisions, since it taps a pure surplus, what is left
over after paying for the economic costs of production.
The effect of shifting public revenue from labor and
capital to land would be to liberate human action from
the disincentives currently imposed by other taxes.
As Henry George noted,
The advantages which would be gained by substituting
for the numerous taxes by which the public revenues are
now raised, a single tax levied upon the value of land,
will appear more and more important the more they are
considered ... With all the burdens removed which now
oppress industry and hamper exchange, the production of
wealth would go on with a rapidity undreamed of ... [It
would be] like removing an immense weight from a
powerful spring.30
... An ideal public revenue policy respects a
person’s right to privacy, does not discourage work
or savings, and does not induce dishonesty. While income,
sales, and value-added taxes fall woefully short of this
ideal, land value taxation meets each requirement.
Imagine the increased prosperity and opportunities for
advancement that would exist if people could keep all of
the money they earn; if billions of dollars wasted on
efforts to avoid high income taxes were suddenly turned
to productive endeavors; and if the growth of government
were constrained by a tax system that would raise only
enough to pay for services actually provided. ...
read the whole
document
Wyn Achenbaum: Eminent Domain and Government
Giveaways
It seems to me that there are better ways than eminent
domain to provide the incentives that will lead the
private sector to develop choice land.
...
While at one time this area might have been an
appropriate place for a neighborhood of single family
homes, it appeared to me that that time had passed a
decade or so ago. It seemed to me that the path of
progress would -- if the incentives were logical and the
market responsive to signals -- have caused the private
sector to have redeveloped that site. Such re-development
might have been painful to the residents of the
neighborhood, but would have put now-choice land to a
higher and better use than single-family homes.
But our system wasn't designed to send signals all that
well -- Connecticut law required properties to be
reassessed once every decade (and I've heard that once in
early '70s and once in the late 80's was construed to
satisfy that requirement). Now assessments are required
every 4 years (though my town decided it didn't like the
2003 revaluation and is keeping the 1999 for a few more
years).
But if the properties had been reassessed on a regular
basis, with market-based values assigned first to the
land and the residual being assigned to the existing
buildings, the homeowners themselves would have been in a
position to make their own rational decisions on whether
it was worth it to them to continue to occupy extremely
valuable land (and pay the taxes on it), or more to their
advantage to accept an offer from someone who was
prepared to put it to a higher and better use, and take
that equity and buy elsewhere. ...
Our land, particularly the best-located land, is a
common asset on which we are all dependent. Allowing
individuals or corporations to occupy it without
compensating the rest of us for its value is the
underlying problem, and solving that problem through good
assessment and rational (that is, land value) taxes is
the way to solve it. When we do that, a lot of problems
will begin to fall away. Read the whole
article
A tension remains, reflecting the Georgist orientation
towards taxes rather than more directly regulatory
interventions. Whether the use of the price mechanism in
this ‘environmental fine tuning’ is
sufficient for dealing with pervasive environment threats
is a moot point. The nature and severity of environmental
stresses is such that more directly proscriptive
environmental policies are commonly needed to protect
natural resources. The creation and maintenance of
national parks, for example, constitutes a necessary
direct regulation of land-use: the market, even when
modified by taxes, cannot absolutely guarantee the
conservation of such crucial assets. In other words,
protection of ‘natural capital’ may commonly
require regulation as well as taxation. ... read the whole
article
Peter Barnes:
Capitalism 3.0 — Chapter 1: Time to Upgrade (pages
3-14)
All thought processes start with premises and flow to
conclusions. Here are the main premises of this book.
1. WE HAVE A CONTRACT
...
2. WE ARE NOT ALONE ...
3. ILLTH HAPPENS ...
4. FIX THE CODE, NOT THE SYMPTOMS—
If we want to reduce illth on an economy-wide scale, we
need to change the code that produces it. Ameliorating
symptoms after the fact is a losing strategy. Unless the
code itself is changed, our economic machine will always
create more illth than it cleans up. Moreover, illth
prevention is a lot cheaper than illth cleanup.
5. REVISE WISELY ...
6. MONEY ISN’T EVERYTHING ...
7. GET THE INCENTIVES RIGHT
Notwithstanding the above, an economic system works
best when it rewards desired behavior. As Mary Poppins
put it, “A spoonful of sugar helps the medicine go
down” (and as I’ve never forgotten, offering
a free pint of Ben & Jerry’s was the best way
Working Assets ever found to get customers). While
we’re looking for methods to protect nature and
future generations, we need to make the incentives work
for living humans as well.
If you disagree with any of these premises,
you’re unlikely to fancy my conclusions. If, on the
other hand, these premises make sense to you, then
welcome to these pages. I won’t bore you with
statistics, or tell you, yet again, that our planet is
going to hell; I’m tired, as I suspect you are, of
numbers and gloom. Nor will I tell you we can save the
planet by doing ten easy things; you know it’s not
that simple. What I will tell you is how we can retool
our economic system, one step at a time, so that after a
decent interval, it respects nature and the human psyche,
and still provides abundantly for our material needs.
Perhaps capitalism will always involve a Faustian deal
of some sort: if we want the goods, we must accept the
bads. But if we must make a deal with the devil, I
believe we can make a much better one than we presently
have. We’ll have to be shrewd, tough, and bold.
But I’m confident that, if we understand how to
get a better deal, we will get one. After all, our
children and lots of other creatures are counting on us.
...
read the whole chapter
Peter Barnes:
Capitalism 3.0 — Chapter 4: The Limits of
Privatization (pages 49-63)
Socially Responsible
Corporations
To survive over time, every organization needs to take in
more money than it spends. (The only possible exception
may be the U.S. government.) This means that even
nonprofit organizations must, in a sense, make a profit.
But making a profit isn’t the same as
maximizing profit. In the first instance, profit
is a means to an end; in the latter, it’s the
purpose that trumps all others. Millions of organizations
earn enough money to stay alive, yet pursue goals other
than profit. Is it possible for publicly traded
corporations to be like that? Can they have
multiple bottom lines? Can they, in other words,
rise above their profit-maximizing algorithm?
There are several ways this might be possible:
enlightened managers might choose a higher goal than
profit, shareholders might insist on it, and government
might require it. Let’s consider each
possibility.
ENLIGHTENED MANAGERS
Managers are human beings; they don’t care just
about money, they also care about the larger world. The
problem is, they’re trapped in a cold-hearted
system. Managers are paid to do one thing, and to do it
well. At best, they can be public-spirited as long as
they don’t harm the bottom line. This gives them
some range to operate — for example, if using
recycled paper adds minimally to their costs without
reducing quality, they might use it. But if it adds
substantially to their costs, they won’t — or
more accurately, can’t — sacrifice profit for
the sake of a few trees. What matters at the end of the
day isn’t the managers’ personal values, but
the difference in price between recycled paper and paper
made from newly felled trees.
There are other reasons not to rely upon the voluntary
benevolence of corporate executives. As The
Economist has written, “The great virtue of
the single bottom line is that it holds managers to
account for something. The triple bottom line does not.
It is not so much a license to operate as a license to
obfuscate.”
As a businessperson, I find this argument compelling.
Every large organization, to be managed well, needs a
mission. That mission should be as clear as possible.
It’s hard enough to manage to one bottom line;
it’s more than thrice as hard to manage to three.
How do managers know, much less quantify, the external
consequences of what they do? And even if they know, what
do they do when goals conflict? Does profit trump nature
or vice versa? If managers are accountable to
shareholders for profit-based performance, to whom are
they accountable for commons-based performance?
Hypothetical answers to such questions can no doubt be
drafted, but what would happen in the real world, I
suspect, is what The Economist surmises: profit
maximization would dominate, accompanied by obfuscation
about other goals. Corporate communications departments
would try to maximize the appearance of social
responsibility for the lowest actual cost. We’d see
beautiful ads and reports, but little change in core
behavior.
It’s important to remember that the
profit-maximizing algorithm is enforced not just by laws,
but by a variety of carrots and sticks. For example, CEO
compensation is typically based on a list of goals
established by the board. These often include
nonfinancial goals, but the goal that carries the most
weight, and is least amenable to obfuscation, is profit.
Further, the CEO and other top managers usually receive
stock options. Since stock prices are driven by reported
quarterly earnings, managers who own stock or stock
options strive to maximize these.
When carrots fail to motivate, sticks come into play
— and they can be brutal. An
“underperforming” corporation will be
devalued by the stock market. This makes it susceptible
to takeover. A classic example is the Pacific Lumber
Company of California, the largest private owner of
old-growth redwood trees in the world. Prior to 1985,
Pacific Lumber was a family-run business that took a
long-term perspective. When it logged, it left up to half
the trees standing, creating natural canopies and keeping
much of the soil stable. It was also generous to its
workers, renting them housing at below-market rates and
refraining from layoffs during downturns.
Sadly, however, Pacific Lumber’s responsible
behavior made it easy prey for a takeover. Its concern
for nature and its employees diminished its profits and
hence its share price. Because of its cutting practices,
it held tremendous stands of virgin redwoods that could
be liquidated quickly. In addition, its pension plan was
overfunded. Spotting all this, corporate raider Charles
Hurwitz offered to buy the company in 1985 through a
holding company called Maxxam. At first the directors
refused, but when Hurwitz threatened to sue them for
violating their fiduciary duty to shareholders, the
directors succumbed.
Hurwitz financed his purchase with junk bonds, the
interest on which was more than the historical profits of
the company. To service this debt, he terminated the
workers’ pension plan and began harvesting trees at
twice the previous rate. Such were the fruits of the
previous managers’ enlightened practices.
It is possible for a company to pursue multiple bottom
lines if it’s closely held by a group of
like-minded shareholders — that was the case at my
former company, Working Assets. But once a corporation
goes public — that is, sells stock to strangers
— the die is pretty much cast. Strangers want a
stock that will rise when they plunk down their money,
and profit is the sure path to doing that. It’s
just a matter of time, then, until the profit-maximizing
algorithm kicks in.
I’ve spent a good part of my life talking with
people who wish publicly traded companies could be
socially responsible — not just cosmetically, but
sufficiently to make a difference. They contend that
corporations were once dedicated to public purposes,
escaped their bounds, and can be put back in. They recall
a time when companies were rooted in their communities,
hired workers for life, and contributed to local
charities. The trouble is, those days are irreversibly
gone. Today, owners live nowhere near workers, labor and
nature are costs to be minimized, and it’s hard to
see what might displace profit as the organizing
principle for publicly traded corporations. ...
MANDATORY RESPONSIBILITY
I don’t think it will ever happen, but consider
this scenario. Imagine Congress passes a law requiring
every corporation — in exchange for limited
liability — to have a triple bottom line. The law
also says that at least a third of corporate directors
should represent workers, nature, and communities in
which the company operates. And it protects directors
from lawsuits if they favor nature over profit.
You’re the CEO of Acme Corporation. What changes do
you make after the law takes effect?
Well, you might start by increasing your accounting
budget. You’ll need, henceforth, to keep track not
only of money but also of your nonmonetary impacts on
society and nature. This isn’t easy, though
presumably shortcuts will be developed. Next, you assign
people to find ways to reduce Acme’s negative
impacts on nature and society, ranking the proposals by
years to payback. You budget a modest sum for the most
cost-effective projects, giving preference to those with
public relations value. You publish ads and reports,
patting yourself on the back for doing what the law
requires. And you remind your board of directors that, if
they choose, they can snub offers from the likes of
Charles Hurwitz and forgo large capital gains for
shareholders.
All this would be well and good. But given the
algorithms that still rule, how much difference would it
make? And even if it did have some effect, would it make
enough difference in the right ways? After all, you might
spend your small green budget on one thing, while nature
most needs something else.
Now, as an alternative, imagine that the price
of nature is no longer zero. All of a sudden, it
costs big bucks to pollute or degrade ecosystems.
Overnight, your managers scramble to cut pollution and
waste. The higher the price, the faster their behavior
changes. And it changes in response to specific natural
scarcities, as indicated by specific prices.
The question is, which of these approaches would work
better — mandatory social responsibility, or
increases in the price of nature? The answer, without
doubt, is the latter. ...
read the whole chapter
Peter Barnes:
Capitalism 3.0 — Chapter 6: Trusteeship of Creation
(pages 79-100)
By contrast, if pollution rights are assigned to
trusts representing pollutees and future generations, and
if these trusts then sell these rights to polluters, the
trusts rather than the polluters will capture the commons
rent. If the trusts split this money between per capita
dividends and expenditures on public goods, everyone
benefits.
At this moment, based on pollution rights allocated so
far, polluting corporations are getting most of the
commons rent. But the case for trusts getting the rent in
the future is compelling. If this is done, consumers will
pay commons rent not to corporations or government, but
to themselves as beneficiaries of commons trusts. Each
citizen’s dividend will be the same, but his
payments will depend on his purchases of pollution-laden
products. The more he pollutes, the more rent he’ll
pay. High polluters will get back less than they put in,
while low polluters will get back more. The microeconomic
incentives, in other words, will be perfect. (See figure
6.1.)
What’s equally significant, though less obvious,
is that the macroeconomic incentives will be perfect too.
That is, it will be in everyone’s interest to
reduce the total level of pollution. Remember how rent
for scarce things works: the lower the supply, the higher
the rent. Now, imagine you’re a trustee of an
ecosystem, and leaving aside (for the sake of argument)
your responsibility to preserve the asset for future
generations, you want to increase dividends. Do you raise
the number of pollution permits you sell, or lower it?
The correct, if counterintuitive answer is: you lower the
number of permits. ...
read the whole chapter
Peter Barnes:
Capitalism 3.0 — Chapter 9: Building the Commons
Sector (pages 135-154)
According to a near-unanimous consensus of scientists,
the world is very close to a tipping point on atmospheric
carbon: we must drastically curtail our carbon burning or
climate hell will soon break loose. This means every
nation must install economy-wide valves for reducing
their carbon use. I described earlier how America might
do this using a carbon, or sky trust. Since we
can’t halt global warming by ourselves, however,
the necessary complement to such an American trust is a
global trust.
A global carbon trust would require national governments
to recognize that, just as they can, and should, delegate
internal trusteeship duties to trusts, so should they
delegate global trusteeship duties. The alternative,
I’d argue, is paralysis in the face of clear and
present danger.
Consider the long and tortuous climate negotiations
that began in the early 1990s. They produced, first, a
toothless pledge by all nations — the Rio
Convention of 1992 — to voluntarily reduce their
greenhouse gas emissions to the 1990 level by 2010. Five
years later, they produced a slightly toothier protocol
in Kyoto, which took another five years to ratify and
translate into operational rules. An equally prolonged
negotiation now looms for the successor to Kyoto, which
expires in 2012.
No doubt these negotiations could move faster if the
current U.S. administration weren’t so obstinately
opposed to them. But the deeper problem is that nearly
two hundred sovereign nations are trying to negotiate a
deal that satisfies everyone. The process is inherently
cumbersome, and not surprisingly, the results fall far
short of what scientists say is necessary. Perhaps,
therefore, it’s time to delegate. I can imagine a
global atmosphere trust working something like this. It
would be governed by a smallish board of trustees and a
general membership consisting of all signatory nations.
The general membership would appoint the trustees. There
might be, as in the U.N. Security Council, a number of
seats reserved for “great powers” (in this
case, large emitters) and another number set aside for
regions. However, once trustees are appointed, their
loyalty would shift from individual nations or regions to
future generations. This is critical.
The trustees would decide, based on peer-reviewed
scientific evidence, where to set a global cap on carbon
emissions. Each year, they’d issue tradeable carbon
emission permits up to that year’s limit. A portion
of these permits (initially, a majority) would be
distributed at no cost to participating nations based on
a pre-agreed formula. The remainder would be auctioned by
the trust, with the revenue used to remediate damage
caused by climate change and aid the inevitable victims.
The trust would determine on a yearly basis how many
permits were needed for these purposes, and how the
remediation funds would be spent.
The trustees would make decisions by majority vote,
with no vetoes. Like a court, they’d explain their
decisions in writing, showing exactly how they protect
future generations. The general membership could override
a trustee decision by, say, a two-thirds majority. In
this way, signatory nations could put short-term
interests over long-term ones, but they’d have to
do so explicitly, and implicitly admit to stealing or
borrowing from future generations.
The knotty question is, What formula should be used to
distribute carbon emission permits among nations? The key
to crafting such a formula, given the disparate interests
of so many nations, is to ground it on some universal
principle of equity. The Kyoto Protocol didn’t do
this; it was a hodgepodge of deals and escape hatches
aimed at pleasing the United States, which in the end
didn’t ratify anyway. The next international
regime, however, must appeal to the poor and the
up-and-coming, as well as to the United States and other
developed countries. Without an organizing principle
based on equity, it’s hard to see how any deal can
be reached.
Fortunately, an equitable organizing principle has
been advanced: it’s known as contract and converge.
Here’s how it would work.
First, an overall reduction schedule would be agreed
to; this is the contract part of the equation. Then,
rights to the global atmospheric commons would be divided
among nations in proportion to their populations —
in other words, one person, one share.
However, absolute proportionality wouldn’t kick
in for a decade or two, during which time the allocation
formula would converge toward proportionality. The rate
of convergence would be a topic for negotiation; the goal
of per capita equity would be accepted at the outset.
Before and after convergence, poor and populous
countries with more permits than emissions could sell
their excess permits to rich and relatively
underpopulated countries that are short on them. In this
way, nations could pollute at different levels, with
overusers of the atmosphere paying underusers for the
privilege. Americans could, in other words, extend our
present level of carbon use for another decade or so, but
we’d have to pay poor countries to do so.
Would a global atmospheric trust be too great a
surrender of national sovereignty? I think not.
We’re not talking about world government here.
We’re talking about a trust to manage a specific
worldwide commons. The one and only job of that trust
would be to set and enforce limits on certain emissions
into that commons. Some loss of sovereignty is involved,
but less than we’ve already yielded to the World
Trade Organization. Compared to the benefit we and all
nations would gain — a stabilized climate —
our loss of sovereignty would be small potatoes.
If a global atmosphere trust could be established, it
would be a watershed twenty-first-century event.
Geopolitically, it could lay the foundation for a
harmonious century, much as the Versailles Treaty paved
the way for a disharmonious one in the twentieth. It
would also help the world deal gracefully with the
decline in global oil production that experts say is
imminent.
Economically, a global atmosphere trust would spur
some important changes. Corporations the world over would
immediately pour money into energy efficiency and
noncarbon energy infrastructure. There’d be a rush
to deploy new technologies. Economies — including
ours — would boom, not despite higher carbon
prices, but because of them.
Why would this happen? The simplest reason is
that a global atmosphere trust would remove an enormous
cloud of uncertainty. Businesses would see the future of
carbon burning, and be more confident that a price shock
— more damaging than a gradual rise —
wouldn’t derail their plans. Such a trust would
also remove a major source of international tension
— the scramble for declining oil supplies —
that could easily lead to war. In addition, the flow of
money to poor countries (from sales of emission permits
to rich countries) would lift their economies and wages,
help U.S. exports and slow U.S. job loss. All these
things would ensure that while high-carbon activity
declines, low-carbon activity rises at a comparable
rate.
But growth in aggregate economic activity isn’t
the only benefit we’d see; qualitative improvements
would also occur. Thus, as long-distance transport costs
rose, manufacturers would shift from global to local
production. Farmers would return to practices they used
before cheap petrochemicals became available.
They’d grow more food organically and sell more
through farmers’ markets and urban buying clubs,
cutting out middlemen and keeping more of their
products’ value. For nonperishables, consumers
would shop more on the Internet and less at
drive-and-haul malls. Thanks to eBay, Craigslist, and
similar services, they’d also buy more secondhand
goods and dump fewer into landfills. More workers would
ride bikes, jitneys, and trains, and work online from
home. Cities would favor footpower, suburbs would
reorganize around transit hubs, and new forms of
co-housing would spread. All these changes would be
profitable and even exciting. And they’d proceed
with relative smoothness if we placed the global
atmosphere in trust.
On the other hand, if we leave our atmosphere as an
unmanaged waste dump, our glorious industrial party will
abruptly end, brought to its knees by oil price shocks,
climate disasters, or a monetary panic. After that, no
one can know what will happen. That’s the stark
choice we face. ...
read the whole chapter
Bill Batt: Comment on Parts of the
NYS Legislative Tax Study Commission's 1985 study
“Who Pays New York Taxes?”
Henry George’s Solution: Taxing the Flow of Land
Rent
If land values are really the present values of
anticipated future ground rents, one can certainly treat
them as flows rather than stocks, just as community
services are continuous flows. The amount of rent flowing
through a site and through the economy is not negligible;
what estimates have been made, where indeed the economic
data allow it to be made, suggest that it is roughly a
third of a nation’s GDP.29 The question is whether
it makes more sense to. Should we elect to continue
property tax regimes as we do, it would make better sense
to tax buildings as stocks and lands as rent flows. But
this raises the question whether real property should be
exempt from all taxes, as some have argued.30 What
rationale exists for taxing lands, whether as stocks or
flows; and why do we tax buildings? I will argue below
that taxing buildings and the failure to adequately tax
land both have deleterious consequences for the whole
economy.
Little justification exists for taxing
buildings, or improvements of any sort, so this question
is easily disposed of. The practice is explained largely
as a matter of historical inertia. Only in the
recent century or two have buildings represented any
significant capital value; prior to the rise of major
cities, the value of real property lay essentially in
land. American cities today typically record aggregate
assessed land values – at least when the valuations
are well-done – at about 40% to 60% of total
taxable value, that is, of land and buildings taken
together.31 Skyscrapers reflect enormous capital
investment, and this expenditure is warranted because of
the enormous value of locational sites. Each site gets
its market price from the fact that the total
neighborhood context creates an attractive market
presence and ambience. By taxing buildings, however, we
impose a penalty on their optimum development as well as
on the incentives for their maintenance. Moreover,
taxes on buildings take away from whatever burden
would otherwise be imposed on sites, with the result that
incentives for their highest and best use is
weakened. Lastly, the technical and
administrative challenges of properly assessing the value
of improvements is daunting, particularly since they must
be depreciated for tax and accounting purposes, evaluated
for potential replacement, and so on. In fact most costs
associated with administration of property taxation and
appeal litigation involve disputes over the valuation of
structures, not land values. ... read the whole
commentary
|
To share this page with a friend:
right click, choose "send," and add your
comments.
|
|
Red links have not been
visited; .
Green links are pages you've seen
|
Essential Documents pertinent
to this theme:
|
|