Land Appreciates, Buildings
Depreciate
land appreciates — capital
rusts!
Few media stories about the real estate
market or the "housing bubble" — and probably few
economists— recognize the reality that while land
appreciates, buildings depreciate. Commercial
investors claim depreciation on their income tax
filings — in fact, the same building may be
depreciated over and over again by a series of owners,
each time probably from a higher starting point!
But few will acknowledge that what has actually
occurred is a decline in the value of the
building.
Electrical, plumbing, HVAC, roof, windows and other
systems deteriorate even when well maintained.
Equally important, features once considered
state-of-the-art become obsolete as technology moves
forward. Finally, a building that was highly
suitable for a Central Business District site at
midcentury is likely to be an underuse of the same site
at the turn of the century, if the local area is
healthy.
And in the same period of time, the Central Business
District is likely to have expanded, changing the
definition of "highest and best use" of sites in the
newer zone from residential to commercial, or
single-family residential to multi-family. Even a
well-maintained and updated mansion in the business
district may no longer be a good use of that
site.
It appears that when a new house is built, the cost of
the land represents 20% to 25% of the selling
price. In the first years, the house's
depreciation may be slow, because systems are new and
the owners may be adding amenities that the builder
didn't provide (a deck, closet and other fittings,
landscaping, etc). But within a few years, all
the improvements other than perhaps well-maintained
landscaping start to depreciate a bit. Meanwhile,
if the location is good, the site will
appreciate. If it is close to established
amenities of the central business district, that will
tend to be fairly steady. If it is in a fringe
area, with new schools, new firehouse, slowly
developing shopping and services, as those services
start to be developed, the site value will begin to
rise. Depending on the site's proximity to secure
and high-paying jobs, appreciation may be rapid.
Within a few years, land's share of the total property
value will pass 50% and then 75%. When it gets as
high as 85%, there may begin to be a trend toward
teardowns. (Think of the northern suburbs of Chicago.)
In some areas, sites get recycled rather
frequently. (Think of Hollywood.)
A May, 2006, Federal Reserve Board study
confirmed that single family houses depreciate at 1.5%
per year. Can commercial buildings be much different?
Certainly machinery will tend to depreciate, no matter
how well it is maintained. That same study said that,
in the top 46 metro markets, land averaged about 51% of
the total value of single family housing in 2004, with
a range from about 20% in Oklahoma City to over 88% in
San Francisco. (Interestingly, the average value of the
housing stock varied far less than the land values per
house!)
Henry George: The Condition of Labor
— An Open Letter to Pope Leo XIII in response to
Rerum Novarum (1891)
God’s laws do not change. Though their
applications may alter with altering conditions, the
same principles of right and wrong that hold when men
are few and industry is rude also hold amid teeming
populations and complex industries. In our cities of
millions and our states of scores of millions, in a
civilization where the division of labor has gone so
far that large numbers are hardly conscious that they
are land-users, it still remains true that we are all
land animals and can live only on land, and that land
is God’s bounty to all, of which no one can be
deprived without being murdered, and for which no one
can be compelled to pay another without being robbed.
But even in a state of society where the elaboration of
industry and the increase of permanent improvements
have made the need for private possession of land
wide-spread, there is no difficulty in conforming
individual possession with the equal right to land. For
as soon as any piece of land will yield to the
possessor a larger return than is had by similar labor
on other land a value attaches to it which is shown
when it is sold or rented. Thus, the value of
the land itself, irrespective of the value of any
improvements in or on it, always indicates the precise
value of the benefit to which all are entitled in its
use, as distinguished from the value which, as producer
or successor of a producer, belongs to the possessor in
individual right.
To combine the advantages of private possession with
the justice of common ownership it is only necessary
therefore to take for common uses what value attaches
to land irrespective of any exertion of labor on it.
The principle is the same as in the case referred to,
where a human father leaves equally to his children
things not susceptible of specific division or common
use. In that case such things would be sold or rented
and the value equally applied.
It is on this common-sense principle that we, who
term ourselves single-tax men, would have the community
act.
We do not propose to assert equal rights to land by
keeping land common, letting any one use any part of it
at any time. We do not propose the task, impossible in
the present state of society, of dividing land in equal
shares; still less the yet more impossible task of
keeping it so divided.
We propose — leaving land in the private
possession of individuals, with full liberty on their
part to give, sell or bequeath it — simply to
levy on it for public uses a tax that shall equal the
annual value of the land itself, irrespective of the
use made of it or the improvements on it. And since
this would provide amply for the need of public
revenues, we would accompany this tax on land values
with the repeal of all taxes now levied on the products
and processes of industry — which taxes, since
they take from the earnings of labor, we hold to be
infringements of the right of property.
This we propose, not as a cunning device of human
ingenuity, but as a conforming of human regulations to
the will of God.
God cannot contradict himself nor impose on his
creatures laws that clash.
If it be God’s command to men that they should
not steal — that is to say, that they should
respect the right of property which each one has in the
fruits of his labor;
And if he be also the Father of all men, who in his
common bounty has intended all to have equal
opportunities for sharing;
Then, in any possible stage of civilization, however
elaborate, there must be some way in which the
exclusive right to the products of industry may be
reconciled with the equal right to land.
If the Almighty be consistent with himself, it
cannot be, as say those socialists referred to by you,
that in order to secure the equal participation of men
in the opportunities of life and labor we must ignore
the right of private property. Nor yet can it be, as
you yourself in the Encyclical seem to argue, that to
secure the right of private property we must ignore the
equality of right in the opportunities of life and
labor. To say the one thing or the other is equally to
deny the harmony of God’s laws.
But, the private possession of land, subject to the
payment to the community of the value of any special
advantage thus given to the individual, satisfies both
laws, securing to all equal participation in the bounty
of the Creator and to each the full ownership of the
products of his labor. ...
Nor do we hesitate to say that this way of securing
the equal right to the bounty of the Creator and the
exclusive right to the products of labor is the way
intended by God for raising public revenues. For we are
not atheists, who deny God; nor semi-atheists, who deny
that he has any concern in politics and
legislation.
It is true as you say — a salutary truth too
often forgotten — that “man is older than
the state, and he holds the right of providing for the
life of his body prior to the formation of any
state.” Yet, as you too perceive, it is also true
that the state is in the divinely appointed order. For
He who foresaw all things and provided for all things,
foresaw and provided that with the increase of
population and the development of industry the
organization of human society into states or
governments would become both expedient and
necessary.
No sooner does the state arise than, as we all know,
it needs revenues. This need for revenues is small at
first, while population is sparse, industry rude and
the functions of the state few and simple. But with
growth of population and advance of civilization the
functions of the state increase and larger and larger
revenues are needed.
Now, He that made the world and placed man in it, He
that pre-ordained civilization as the means whereby man
might rise to higher powers and become more and more
conscious of the works of his Creator, must have
foreseen this increasing need for state revenues and
have made provision for it. That is to say: The
increasing need for public revenues with social
advance, being a natural, God-ordained need, there must
be a right way of raising them — some way that we
can truly say is the way intended by God. It is clear
that this right way of raising public revenues must
accord with the moral law.
Hence:
-
It must not take from individuals what rightfully
belongs to individuals.
-
It must not give some an advantage over others, as by
increasing the prices of what some have to sell and
others must buy.
-
It must not lead men into temptation, by requiring
trivial oaths, by making it profitable to lie, to
swear falsely, to bribe or to take bribes.
-
It must not confuse the distinctions of right and
wrong, and weaken the sanctions of religion and the
state by creating crimes that are not sins, and
punishing men for doing what in itself they have an
undoubted right to do.
-
It must not repress industry. It must not check
commerce. It must not punish thrift. It must offer no
impediment to the largest production and the fairest
division of wealth.
Let me ask your Holiness to consider the taxes on
the processes and products of industry by which through
the civilized world public revenues are collected
—
-
the octroi duties that surround Italian cities with
barriers;
-
the monstrous customs duties that hamper intercourse
between so-called Christian states;
-
the taxes on occupations, on earnings, on
investments, on the building of houses, on the
cultivation of fields, on industry and thrift in all
forms.
Can these be the ways God has intended that
governments should raise the means they need? Have
any of them the characteristics indispensable in any
plan we can deem a right one?
All these taxes violate the moral law. They take by
force what belongs to the individual alone; they give
to the unscrupulous an advantage over the scrupulous;
they have the effect, nay are largely intended, to
increase the price of what some have to sell and others
must buy; they corrupt government; they make oaths a
mockery; they shackle commerce; they fine industry and
thrift; they lessen the wealth that men might enjoy,
and enrich some by impoverishing others.
Yet what most strikingly shows how opposed to
Christianity is this system of raising public revenues
is its influence on thought.
Christianity teaches us that all men are brethren;
that their true interests are harmonious, not
antagonistic. It gives us, as the golden rule of life,
that we should do to others as we would have others do
to us. But out of the system of taxing the products and
processes of labor, and out of its effects in
increasing the price of what some have to sell and
others must buy, has grown the theory of
“protection,” which denies this gospel,
which holds Christ ignorant of political economy and
proclaims laws of national well-being utterly at
variance with his teaching. This theory sanctifies
national hatreds; it inculcates a universal war of
hostile tariffs; it teaches peoples that their
prosperity lies in imposing on the productions of other
peoples restrictions they do not wish imposed on their
own; and instead of the Christian doctrine of
man’s brotherhood it makes injury of foreigners a
civic virtue.
“By their fruits ye shall know them.”
Can anything more clearly show that to tax the products
and processes of industry is not the way God intended
public revenues to be raised?
But to consider what we propose — the raising
of public revenues by a single tax on the value of land
irrespective of improvements — is to see that in
all respects this does conform to the moral law.
Let me ask your Holiness to keep in mind that the
value we propose to tax, the value of land irrespective
of improvements, does not come from any exertion of
labor or investment of capital on or in it — the
values produced in this way being values of improvement
which we would exempt. The value of land
irrespective of improvement is the value that attaches
to land by reason of increasing population and social
progress. This is a value that always goes to
the owner as owner, and never does and never can go to
the user; for if the user be a different person from
the owner he must always pay the owner for it in rent
or in purchase-money; while if the user be also the
owner, it is as owner, not as user, that he receives
it, and by selling or renting the land he can, as
owner, continue to receive it after he ceases to be a
user.
Thus, taxes on land irrespective of improvement
cannot lessen the rewards of industry, nor add to
prices,* nor in any way take from the individual what
belongs to the individual. They can take only the value
that attaches to land by the growth of the community,
and which therefore belongs to the community as a
whole.
* As to this point it may be well to
add that all economists are agreed that taxes on land
values irrespective of improvement or use — or
what in the terminology of political economy is
styled rent, a term distinguished from the ordinary
use of the word rent by being applied solely to
payments for the use of land itself — must be
paid by the owner and cannot be shifted by him on the
user. To explain in another way the reason given in
the text: Price is not determined by the will of the
seller or the will of the buyer, but by the equation
of demand and supply, and therefore as to things
constantly demanded and constantly produced rests at
a point determined by the cost of production —
whatever tends to increase the cost of bringing fresh
quantities of such articles to the consumer
increasing price by checking supply, and whatever
tends to reduce such cost decreasing price by
increasing supply. Thus taxes on wheat or tobacco or
cloth add to the price that the consumer must pay,
and thus the cheapening in the cost of producing
steel which improved processes have made in recent
years has greatly reduced the price of steel. But
land has no cost of production, since it is created
by God, not produced by man. Its price therefore is
fixed —
1 (monopoly rent), where land is
held in close monopoly, by what the owners can
extract from the users under penalty of deprivation
and consequently of starvation, and amounts to all
that common labor can earn on it beyond what is
necessary to life;
2 (economic rent proper), where there is no special
monopoly, by what the particular land will yield to
common labor over and above what may be had by like
expenditure and exertion on land having no special
advantage and for which no rent is paid; and,
3 (speculative rent, which is a species of monopoly
rent, telling particularly in selling price), by
the expectation of future increase of value from
social growth and improvement, which expectation
causing landowners to withhold land at present
prices has the same effect as combination.
Taxes on land values or economic rent
can therefore never be shifted by the landowner to
the land-user, since they in no wise increase the
demand for land or enable landowners to check supply
by withholding land from use. Where rent depends on
mere monopolization, a case I mention because rent
may in this way be demanded for the use of land even
before economic or natural rent arises, the taking by
taxation of what the landowners were able to extort
from labor could not enable them to extort any more,
since laborers, if not left enough to live on, will
die. So, in the case of economic rent proper, to take
from the landowners the premiums they receive, would
in no way increase the superiority of their land and
the demand for it. While, so far as price is affected
by speculative rent, to compel the landowners to pay
taxes on the value of land whether they were getting
any income from it or not, would make it more
difficult for them to withhold land from use; and to
tax the full value would not merely destroy the power
but the desire to do so.
To take land values for the state, abolishing all
taxes on the products of labor, would therefore leave
to the laborer the full produce of labor; to the
individual all that rightfully belongs to the
individual. It would impose no burden on industry, no
check on commerce, no punishment on thrift; it would
secure the largest production and the fairest
distribution of wealth, by leaving men free to produce
and to exchange as they please, without any artificial
enhancement of prices; and by taking for public
purposes a value that cannot be carried off, that
cannot be hidden, that of all values is most easily
ascertained and most certainly and cheaply collected,
it would enormously lessen the number of officials,
dispense with oaths, do away with temptations to
bribery and evasion, and abolish man-made crimes in
themselves innocent.
But, further: That God has intended the state to
obtain the revenues it needs by the taxation of land
values is shown by the same order and degree of
evidence that shows that God has intended the milk of
the mother for the nourishment of the babe.
See how close is the analogy. In that
primitive condition ere the need for the state arises
there are no land values. The products of
labor have value, but in the sparsity of population no
value as yet attaches to land itself. But as
increasing density of population and increasing
elaboration of industry necessitate the organization of
the state, with its need for revenues, value begins to
attach to land. As population still increases and
industry grows more elaborate, so the needs for public
revenues increase. And at the same time and from the
same causes land values increase. The connection is
invariable. The value of things produced
by labor tends to decline
with social development, since the larger scale of
production and the improvement of processes tend
steadily to reduce their cost. But the value of
land on which population centers goes up and
up. Take Rome or Paris or London or New York
or Melbourne. Consider the enormous value of land in
such cities as compared with the value of land in
sparsely settled parts of the same countries. To what
is this due? Is it not due to the density
and activity of the populations of those cities —
to the very causes that require great public
expenditure for streets, drains, public buildings, and
all the many things needed for the health, convenience
and safety of such great cities? See how
with the growth of such cities the one thing that
steadily increases in value is land; how the opening of
roads, the building of railways, the making of any
public improvement, adds to the value of land. Is it
not clear that here is a natural law — that is to
say a tendency willed by the Creator? Can it mean
anything else than that He who ordained the state with
its needs has in the values which attach to land
provided the means to meet those needs?
That it does mean this and nothing else is confirmed
if we look deeper still, and inquire not merely as to
the intent, but as to the purpose of the intent. If we
do so we may see in this natural law by which land
values increase with the growth of society not only
such a perfectly adapted provision for the needs of
society as gratifies our intellectual perceptions by
showing us the wisdom of the Creator, but a purpose
with regard to the individual that gratifies our moral
perceptions by opening to us a glimpse of his
beneficence.
Consider: Here is a natural law by which as
society advances the one thing that increases in value
is land — a natural law by virtue of which all
growth of population, all advance of the arts, all
general improvements of whatever kind, add to a fund
that both the commands of justice and the dictates of
expediency prompt us to take for the common uses of
society. Now, since increase in the fund
available for the common uses of society is increase in
the gain that goes equally to each member of society,
is it not clear that the law by which land values
increase with social advance while the value of the
products of labor does not increase, tends with the
advance of civilization to make the share that goes
equally to each member of society more and more
important as compared with what goes to him from his
individual earnings, and thus to make the advance of
civilization lessen relatively the differences that in
a ruder social state must exist between the strong and
the weak, the fortunate and the unfortunate? Does it
not show the purpose of the Creator to be that the
advance of man in civilization should be an advance not
merely to larger powers but to a greater and greater
equality, instead of what we, by our ignoring of his
intent, are making it, an advance toward a more and
more monstrous inequality? ... read the whole
letter
Henry George: The Land Question
(1881)
When a man makes a fortune by the rise of real
estate, as in New York and elsewhere many men have done
within the past few months, what does it mean? It means
that he may have fine clothes, costly food, a grand
house luxuriously furnished, etc. Now, these things are
not the spontaneous fruits of the soil; neither do they
fall from heaven, nor are they cast up by the sea. They
are products of labor – can be produced only by
labor. And hence, if men who do no labor get them, it
must necessarily be at the expense of those who do
labor.
Louis Post: Outlines of Louis F. Post's
Lectures, with Illustrative Notes and Charts (1894)
— Appendix: FAQ
Q21. Do not the benefits of good government
increase the value of houses as well as of
land?
A. No. Houses are never worth any more than it
costs to reproduce them. Good government tends to
diminish the cost of house building; how, then, can
good government increase the value of houses?
You are confused by the fact that houses, being
attached to land, seem to increase in value, when it is
the land and not the house that really increases. It is
the same mistake that a somewhat noted economic
teacher, who advocates protection as his specialty,
made when he tried to show that there is an "unearned
increment" to houses as well as to lands. He did so by
instancing a lot of vacant land which had risen in
value from $5000 to $10,000, and comparing it with a
house on a neighboring lot which, as he said, had also
increased in value from $5000 to $10,000. At the moment
when he wrote, the house to which he referred could
have been reproduced for $5000; and had he been capable
of thinking out a proposition he must have discovered
that it was the lot on which the house stood, and not
the house itself, which had increased in value. ...
read the
book
Charles B. Fillebrown: A Catechism of Natural
Taxation, from Principles of Natural
Taxation (1917)
Q61. Do you think there would be any injustice
in taking by taxation the future increment in the value
of land?
A. Fifteen professors of political economy have
answered "Yes." Ninety-four have answered "No."
Q62. Would it be wise to take gradually in
taxation, say, 1/4, one half, or 3/4 of the future
increase in economic rent?
A. One hundred and one professors of political economy
have answered "Yes." Twenty-nine have answered "No."
... read the
whole article
Jeff Smith: What
To Do About the Real Estate Bubble
What’s bubbling, and until
when?
Sellers are happy. So are developers and
speculators. Real estate has gone all bubbly, and that
bubble has gone ballistic. What goes up, however, must
soon do something else.
...
Actually, it’s not housing whose price has
entered the stratosphere. Buildings age – get
older, more worn out. What’s getting more
valuable is the land, the location – whether it
has a building on it or not. Buildings you can make
more of, but land you can not, especially locations
along the coasts or on the good side of town. None of
that would matter if you could ever get buildings to
hover around in the air. Meanwhile however, speculators
are happy.
Read the whole
article
Michael Hudson and Kris Feder: Real Estate and the
Capital Gains Debate
... the Fed statistics37 understate land values for
methodological reasons. Starting with estimates for
overall real estate market prices, Fed statisticians
subtract estimated replacement prices for existing
buildings and capital improvements to derive land
values as a residual. These replacement prices are
based on the Commerce Department’s index of
construction costs. Thus, building values are estimated
to increase steadily over time, on the implicit
assumption that all such property is worth reproducing
at today’s rising costs.
37 Balance Sheets for
the U.S. Economy, 1945-94, Tables B. 11, B. 12 and R
11.
However, the value of any building tends
eventually to decline, until finally it is scrapped and
replaced. It is the value of land which tends to rise
as population and income grow (over the long run, with
cyclical swings), precisely because no more land can be
produced. Thus, capital gains in real estate result
mainly from land appreciation.
Building values fall because of physical
deterioration, but also because buildings undergo
locational obsolescence as neighborhood land uses
change over time, so market prices tend to fall below
replacement costs. It would not be economical to
rebuild many types of structures on the same site if
they were suddenly destroyed.38 In particular, where land use
is intensifying over the long run, rising land values
effectively drain the capital value out of old
buildings. This is because the salvage value of land
(its worth upon renewal) tends to rise, while the scrap
or salvage value of most immovable improvements is
negligible. Where land has alternative uses, rent is
not its current net income but its opportunity cost --
the minimum yield required by the market to warrant
keeping the land in its present use instead of
converting it to the best alternative use. As the land
value rises, a rising share of the property income must
be imputed to the land and a falling share remains to
be imputed to the improvements. Read the whole article
Herbert J. G. Bab: Property Tax -- Cause
of Unemployment (circa 1964)
... A defect of our property
tax system that is seldom mentioned is that it puts a
premium on obsolescence and penalizes new
housing. This is so because property taxes are
ad valorem taxes. Every piece
of real estate except land is subject to depreciation.
Thus the owners of old and obsolete
real estate will pay little in taxes, while newly
constructed buildings will bear the brunt of the
tax.
This characteristic of the property tax is obscured by
the rising trends of land values, which in many cases
offset the loss in value of the improvement. Increases
in tax rates and differences in assessment procedures
and practices further hide the fact that ad valorem
taxes favor obsolete real property. ...
Homeowners who bought their homes some time in the past
can reap large profits when selling them. Old homes
should sell at a lower price, because of the
depreciation of the building, but in most cases the
depreciation of the building is more than offset by the
increased value of the lot. This increased value forces
buyers to increase their down payments or to increase
their loan are higher, many families are priced out of
the market. ...
The administration of the property tax leaves very much
to be desired. Assessment procedures and practices are
in many cases erroneous, arbitrary and widely variant.
So is the ratio of assessed value to full market or
cash value. In many states no public records are
available indicating assessed values and the taxpayer
has no of knowing what his tax bill will be.
The most serious defect in the
administration of property taxation is the continuous,
widespread and enormous underassessment of land. A
survey made recently found that in 9 California
counties, vacant lots and acreage were assessed at only
5.3% of the cash value, while residential property was
assessed at 19.3% of its value. The illegal
underassessment of land deprives local governments of
millions of dollars of revenues. Moreover, it further
aggravates the serious defects of property
taxation.
We have analyzed the effects of
property taxation on improvements as distinguished from
those caused by the incidence of these taxes on
land.
- We have found that a high and burdensome tax
rate on improvements will discourage residential
construction, create unemployment, penalize
home-ownership, aggravate the housing shortage and
force up rents.
- Yet a low tax rate on land will have similar
if not identical effects: it will lead to a rise in
urban land values, which in turn will discourage
residential construction, create unemployment, penalize
home-ownership, aggravate the housing shortage and
force up rents.
... The
paradox of property taxation consists in the fact that
lower rates on improvements produce the same results as
higher rates on land and conversely higher rates on
improvements produce the same results as lower rates on
land. Read the whole
article
Charles T. Root — Not a Single Tax! (1925)
Now imagine for a moment the effect upon the
appearance of a city and upon the comfort of its
population which would result from the change of fiscal
policy which this article proposes. At present, a
tempting premium is placed upon keeping land unimproved
or inadequately improved, while a heavy penalty is
imposed upon improvement. Most land appreciates
constantly. All buildings depreciate from the moment of
completion. Yet the building is taxed equally with the
land.
What incentive does such a system offer the
speculative landowner to put up a commodious,
well-lighted modern structure in place of the old ruin
which now pays him so well? The old one cannot
depreciate much more, and while paying a trifling tax
because of its physical worthlessness, he is thereby
enabled to collect and pocket the economic rent of the
ground, which the community is continually rendering
more valuable. The new building would absorb a large
amount of capital, would begin to run down even before
it could be occupied, and would be taxed to the limit.
Why then is not the landlord justified in letting well
enough alone, enjoying the growing economic rent, and
waiting till he can get a fancy price for the right to
collect it?
But reverse the conditions. Reclaim for the
community its natural income, making it expensive
either to keep needed land vacant or to withhold it
from the ready and willing to improve it to the full
extent of its possibilities.
Does it require severe intellectual effort to
foresee the results? Better and better houses,
apartments, tenements, offices and stores, more
employment for labor in all enterprises now held back
by the shadow of the tax-gatherer, an end of all
tax-lying, tax-evasion and tax-injustice, and withal, a
public revenue adequate to all real public needs.
What a contrast to the existing plan of pouring
public money into the laps of individual landowners ...
read the whole
article
Bill Batt: Comment on Parts of
the NYS Legislative Tax Study Commission's 1985 study
“Who Pays New York Taxes?”
Except in the implicit recognition involved in their
analysis of shifting, the distinction between land and
improvements was opaque. This is a remarkable
oversight, because improvements typically depreciate at
the rate of 0.5 to 1.5 percent annually; only land
values appreciate.9 And in view of the fact that
assessments in New York localities have historically
been very infrequent, one can understand how the land
values are in reality a far higher proportion of parcel
value than assessments would suggest.10 This means that
in a period of seven years, for example, a property
parcel could easily increase in price by 50 percent,
far more if recent real estate market history is to be
illustrative. Moreover real estate prices varied
greatly in their rates of change during this time span;
upstate New York was largely stable, but downstate
localities experienced huge booms and busts.
Recognition of this would tend to favor what is
known as the “new view” of property tax
incidence, an acceptance of the idea that ”the
burden of the tax on improvements remains with the
owners of capital in the form of a lower net return
instead of being shifted to users of property in the
form of higher rents or prices.”11 Proponents
point out that “the tax on improvements is
essentially a nationwide tax on capital . . . [and
therefore] its incidence will depend on the
characteristics of supply and demand for capital
nationally rather than on a single market.”12 The
effect of this is to make the tax ”highly
progressive.”13 Nonetheless, in a small footnote,
Messrs. Pomp and Phares elected to go with the
“old view” in stating that, “it seems
most appropriate to assume that the new view does not
apply to the analysis of tax burdens within one
specific state (underlining in original). Thus, the old
or traditional view was adhered to in the analysis. . ;
that is, the excise effect of the tax was considered
dominant.”14 The ubiquity of New York's property
tax, and that it has over 1,300 local assessment and
tax districts, may well have escaped their notice. ...
read the
whole commentary
Arthur J. Ogilvy: A Colonist's Plea
for Land Nationalization (about 1890)
If I sell goods or perform work for another, then no
matter how high I may charge for the goods or the work,
I am rendering goods for goods, service for service,
earnings for earnings. What I offer is my labour, or
the fruits of it, and as the public are free to get the
same goods or services elsewhere if my terms don't
suit, or to go without them, the fact of their
accepting my terms shows that the thing I offer is,
under the circumstances, worth the money.
But in the case of this unearned increment on land
there is no pretence of any exchange. I offer for it
neither labour nor the produce of labour. All I do is
to place my hand on a certain portion of the earth's
surface, and say, "No one shall use this without paying
me for the mere permission to use it." I am rendering
no more service in return for this extra pound, either
to the purchaser or to society, than if I had acquired
exclusive title to the air, and charged people for
permission to breathe. And if, instead of selling my
land for an additional pound, I let it at a
proportionately additional rent the principle would be
the same.
The increase of value in my land has arisen from the
execution of public works and increase of population,
causing an increased demand for the land; in other
words, it has arisen from the national progress; and I,
so far from aiding in this progress have actually
hindered it, by keeping my property locked up and so
forcing on intending producers to inferior or less
accessible lands; and by holding so much land back have
helped to make land so much scarcer, and, therefore, so
much dearer, and so have helped to increase the tribute
which industry has to pay to monopoly for the mere
privilege of exerting itself....
The value of land, as of everything else, will
oscillate within certain limits, and even in some
exceptional cases, as in the sudden diversion of
traffic, fall for an indefinitely prolonged period; but
these occasional or exceptional perturbations are but
as the advance and recession of the waves in a flowing
tide. The tide still comes in.
In every country which has any enterprise and progress,
land values must rise. The movement may be fast or
slow, continuous or interrupted, but it is up not
down.
There is not a single factor in a nation's progress
that does not add to the value of land. Every road
improved and railway laid down; every machine invented
and process perfected; every opening of new markets;
every improvement in fiscal policy, in order and good
Government, in the knowledge and skill, in the morals,
manners, and even numbers of the people, every
conceivable element, in short that adds to the
productiveness of industry, adds to the value of land,
and increases the tribute which monopoly can wring from
industry; which the man who merely owns the land can
exact from him who uses it for the mere permission to
use it.
This is why the gradual rise of land value or rent
(ground rent only, remember), is called the unearned
increment. ...
Rent devours wages.
Suppose the labourer to ask for a rise and the farmer
to refuse, on the ground that he cannot afford
it.
But presently something happens. A railway is made or a
mine opened in the neighbourhood, or some improved
process enables a greater yield to be obtained at the
same cost, and there is now an appreciable surplus. The
labourer comes forward again and says, "You can afford
it now."
"Unfortunately, no," replies his employer. "I might
have done so, but my lease is nearly up, and these
advantages you refer to having made the land more
valuable, my landlord has notified that he means to
raise the rent; and as there certainly is a greater
surplus available for rent than there was, I must give
it, for if I don't someone else will; and so, as far as
I am concerned, the surplus you calculate upon has
vanished."
In short, whenever there is an increase in the
productiveness of industry creating an additional
surplus, and the labourer stretches forth his hand for
a share of it, the landlord pushes him aside, and takes
it all himself; but as he keeps well out of sight in
doing so, using the employer as his instrument, his
action is not perceived. And as it is in the present so
it has been in the past. Inventions and discoveries
have within the last century doubled the productiveness
of industry over and over again, but the labourer has
no more benefited by them than the employer has. The
increase has been enormous, but, in the primary
industries at any rate, the landlord has taken it
all.
But some will say, "The labourer's exertion is a fixed
quantity. The increased productiveness of his industry
is in no degree due to himself, but to the improved
appliances he works with, and, that being so, the
person who supplies these appliances that is, the
employer has a right to the increase.
There is enough prima facie appearance of
reason in this to have made it worth discussing if the
employer really got it, but he does not. He gets
interest, no doubt, on the additional expense he has
incurred in procuring the appliance, but he gets none
of the increase of wealth due to the increased
efficiency of labour when aided by the appliance, (once
the appliance has come into general use); that, as we
have seen, goes to increase the value of land and raise
rents, and while the employer does not gain, the
labourer in most cases actually loses; for the usual
result of labour-saving inventions, in the primary
industries at any rate, is not that the employer
retains the same hands to do more work, but that he
discharges some of his men and does the old amount of
work with fewer hands.
It is the landlord, who has neither invented, nor
supplied, nor put to use the appliances, who gets the
whole benefit of them. ... read the whole
paper.
|
To share this page with a friend:
right click, choose "send," and add your
comments.
|
|
Red links have not been
visited; .
Green links are pages you've seen
|
Essential Documents pertinent
to this theme:
|
|