Paying the Wrong Party
Henry George: The Condition of
Labor — An Open Letter to Pope Leo XIII in response
to Rerum Novarum (1891)
Your use, in so many passages of your Encyclical, of
the inclusive term “property” or
“private” property, of which in morals
nothing can be either affirmed or denied, makes your
meaning, if we take isolated sentences, in many places
ambiguous. But reading it as a whole, there can be no
doubt of your intention that private property in land
shall be understood when you speak merely of private
property. With this interpretation, I find that the
reasons you urge for private property in land are eight.
Let us consider them in order of presentation. You
urge:
1. That what is bought with rightful property is
rightful property. (RN, paragraph 5) ...
2. That private property in land proceeds from
man’s gift of reason. (RN, paragraphs 6-7.)
...
3. That private property in land deprives no one of the
use of land. (RN, paragraph 8.) ...
4. That Industry expended on land gives ownership in the
land itself. (RN, paragraphs 9-10.) ...
5. That private property in land has the support of the
common opinion of mankind, and has conduced to peace and
tranquillity, and that it is sanctioned by Divine Law.
(RN, paragraph 11.) ...
6. That fathers should provide for their children and
that private property in land is necessary to enable them
to do so. (RN, paragraphs 14-17.) ...
7. That the private ownership of land stimulates
industry, increases wealth, and attaches men to the soil
and to their country. (RN, paragraph 51.) ...
8. That the right to possess private property in land is
from nature, not from man; that the state has no right to
abolish it, and that to take the value of landownership
in taxation would be unjust and cruel to the private
owner. (RN, paragraph 51.) ...
4. That Industry expended on land gives
ownership in the land itself. (9-10.)
Your Holiness next contends that industry expended on
land gives a right to ownership of the land, and that the
improvement of land creates benefits indistinguishable
and inseparable from the land itself.
This contention, if valid, could only justify the
ownership of land by those who expend industry on it. It
would not justify private property in land as it exists.
On the contrary, it would justify a gigantic no-rent
declaration that would take land from those who now
legally own it, the landlords, and turn it over to the
tenants and laborers. And if it also be that improvements
cannot be distinguished and separated from the land
itself, how could the landlords claim consideration even
for improvements they had made?
But your Holiness cannot mean what your words imply.
What you really mean, I take it, is that the original
justification and title of landownership is in the
expenditure of labor on it. But neither can this justify
private property in land as it exists. For is it not all
but universally true that existing land titles do not
come from use, but from force or fraud?
Take Italy! Is it not true that the greater part of
the land of Italy is held by those who so far from ever
having expended industry on it have been mere
appropriators of the industry of those who have? Is this
not also true of Great Britain and of other countries?
Even in the United States, where the forces of
concentration have not yet had time fully to operate and
there has been some attempt to give land to users, it is
probably true today that the greater part of the land is
held by those who neither use it nor propose to use it
themselves, but merely hold it to compel others to pay
them for permission to use it.
And if industry give ownership to land what are the
limits of this ownership? If a man may acquire the
ownership of several square miles of land by grazing
sheep on it, does this give to him and his heirs the
ownership of the same land when it is found to contain
rich mines, or when by the growth of population and the
progress of society it is needed for farming, for
gardening, for the close occupation of a great city? Is
it on the rights given by the industry of those who first
used it for grazing cows or growing potatoes that you
would found the title to the land now covered by the city
of New York and having a value of thousands of millions
of dollars?
But your contention is not valid. Industry expended on
land gives ownership in the fruits of that industry, but
not in the land itself, just as industry expended on the
ocean would give a right of ownership to the fish taken
by it, but not a right of ownership in the ocean. Nor yet
is it true that private ownership of land is necessary to
secure the fruits of labor on land; nor does the
improvement of land create benefits indistinguishable and
inseparable from the land itself. That secure possession
is necessary to the use and improvement of land I have
already explained, but that ownership is not necessary is
shown by the fact that in all civilized countries land
owned by one person is cultivated and improved by other
persons. Most of the cultivated land in the British
Islands, as in Italy and other countries, is cultivated
not by owners but by tenants. And so the costliest
buildings are erected by those who are not owners of the
land, but who have from the owner a mere right of
possession for a time on condition of certain payments.
Nearly the whole of London has been built in this way,
and in New York, Chicago, Denver, San Francisco, Sydney
and Melbourne, as well as in continental cities, the
owners of many of the largest edifices will be found to
be different persons from the owners of the ground. So
far from the value of improvements being inseparable from
the value of land, it is in individual transactions
constantly separated. For instance, one-half of the land
on which the immense Grand Pacific Hotel in Chicago
stands was recently separately sold, and in Ceylon it is
a not infrequent occurrence for one person to own a
fruit-tree and another to own the ground in which it is
implanted.
There is, indeed, no improvement of land, whether it
be clearing, plowing, manuring, cultivating, the digging
of cellars, the opening of wells or the building of
houses, that so long as its usefulness continues does not
have a value clearly distinguishable from the value of
the land. For land having such improvements will always
sell or rent for more than similar land without them.
If, therefore, the state levy a tax equal to what the
land irrespective of improvement would bring, it will
take the benefits of mere ownership, but will leave the
full benefits of use and improvement, which the
prevailing system does not do. And since the holder, who
would still in form continue to be the owner, could at
any time give or sell both possession and improvements,
subject to future assessment by the state on the value of
the land alone, he will be perfectly free to retain or
dispose of the full amount of property that the exertion
of his labor or the investment of his capital has
attached to or stored up in the land.
Thus, what we propose would secure, as it is
impossible in any other way to secure, what you properly
say is just and right — “that the results of
labor should belong to him who has labored.” But
private property in land — to allow the holder
without adequate payment to the state to take for himself
the benefit of the value that attaches to land with
social growth and improvement — does take the
results of labor from him who has labored, does turn over
the fruits of one man’s labor to be enjoyed by
another. For labor, as the active factor, is the producer
of all wealth. Mere ownership produces nothing. A man
might own a world, but so sure is the decree that
“by the sweat of thy brow shalt thou eat
bread,” that without labor he could not get a meal
or provide himself a garment. Hence, when the owners of
land, by virtue of their ownership and without laboring
themselves, get the products of labor in abundance, these
things must come from the labor of others, must be the
fruits of others’ sweat, taken from those who have
a right to them and enjoyed by those who have no right to
them.
The only utility of private ownership of land as
distinguished from possession is the evil utility of
giving to the owner products of labor he does not earn.
For until land will yield to its owner some return beyond
that of the labor and capital he expends on it —
that is to say, until by sale or rental he can without
expenditure of labor obtain from it products of labor,
ownership amounts to no more than security of possession,
and has no value. Its importance and value begin only
when, either in the present or prospectively, it will
yield a revenue — that is to say, will enable the
owner as owner to obtain products of labor without
exertion on his part, and thus to enjoy the results of
others’ labor.
What largely keeps men from realizing the
robbery involved in private property in land is that in
the most striking cases the robbery is not of
individuals, but of the community. For, as I have before
explained, it is impossible for rent in the economic
sense — that value which attaches to land by reason
of social growth and improvement — to go to the
user. It can go only to the owner or to the community.
Thus those who pay enormous rents for the use of land in
such centers as London or New York are not individually
injured. Individually they get a return for what they
pay, and must feel that they have no better right to the
use of such peculiarly advantageous localities without
paying for it than have thousands of others. And so, not
thinking or not caring for the interests of the
community, they make no objection to the
system.
It recently came to light in New York that a man
having no title whatever had been for years collecting
rents on a piece of land that the growth of the city had
made very valuable. Those who paid these rents had never
stopped to ask whether he had any right to them. They
felt that they had no right to land that so many others
would like to have, without paying for it, and did not
think of, or did not care for, the rights of all. ...
read the
whole letter
Louis Post:
Outlines of Louis F. Post's Lectures, with Illustrative
Notes and Charts (1894)
II. THE SINGLE TAX AS A
FISCAL REFORM
1. DIRECT AND INDIRECT
TAXATION
Taxes are either direct or indirect; or, as they have
been aptly described, "straight" or "crooked." Indirect
taxes are those that may be shifted by the first payer
from himself to others; direct taxes are those that
cannot be shifted.5
5. "Taxes are either direct or indirect.
A direct tax is one which is demanded from the very
persons who, it is intended or desired, should pay it.
Indirect taxes are those which are demanded from one
person in the expectation and intention that he shall
indemnify himself at the expense of another." —
John Stuart Mill's Prin. of Pol. Ec., book v, ch. iii,
sec. I.
"Direct taxes are those which are levied
on the very persons who it is intended or desired
should pay them, and which they cannot put off upon
others by raising the prices of the taxed article.. . .
Indirect taxes on the other hand are those which are
levied on persons who expect to get back the amount of
the tax by raising the price of the taxed article."
— Laughlin's Elements, par. 249.
Taxes are direct "when the payment is
made by the person who is intended to bear the
sacrifice." Indirect taxes are recovered from final
purchasers. — Jevons's Primer, sec. 96.
"Indirect taxes are so called because
they are not paid into the treasury by the person who
really bears the burden. The payer adds the amount of
the tax to the price of the commodity taxed, and thus
the taxation is concealed under the increased price of
some article of luxury or convenience." —
Thompson's Pol. Ec., sec. 175.
The shifting of indirect taxes is accomplished by
means of their tendency to increase the prices of
commodities on which they fall. Their magnitude and
incidence 6 are thereby disguised. It was for this reason
that a great French economist of the last century
denounced them as "a scheme for so plucking geese as to
get the most feathers with the least squawking."7
6. Jevons defines the incidence of a tax
as "the manner in which it falls upon different classes
of the population." — Jevons's Primer, sec.
96.
Sometimes called "repercussion," and refers "to the
real as opposed to the nominal payment of taxes."
— Ely's Taxation, p. 64.
7. Though his language was blunt, the
sentiment does not essentially differ from that of
"statesmen" of our day who meet all the moral and
economic objections to indirect taxation with the one
reply that the people would not consent to pay enough
or the support of government if public revenues were
collected from them directly. This means nothing but
that the people are actually hoodwinked by indirect
taxation into sustaining a government that they would
not support if they knew it was maintained at their
expense; and instead of being a reason for continuing
indirect taxation, would, if true, be one of the
strongest of reasons for abolishing it. It is
consistent neither with the plainest principles of
democracy nor the simplest conceptions of morality.
Indirect taxation costs the real tax-payers much more
than the government receives, partly because the
middlemen through whose hands taxed commodities pass are
able to exact compound profits upon the tax,8 and partly
on account of extraordinary expenses of original
collection;9 it favors corruption in government by
concealing from the people the fact that they contribute
to the support of government; and it tends, by
obstructing production, to crush legitimate industry and
establish monopolies.10 The questions it raises are of
vastly more concern than is indicated by the sum total of
public expenditures.
8. A tax upon shoes, paid in the first
instance by shoe manufacturers, enters into
manufacturers' prices, and, together with the usual
rate of profit upon that amount of investment, is
recovered from wholesalers. The tax and the
manufacturers' profit upon it then constitute part of
the wholesale price and are collected from retailers.
The retailers in turn collect the tax with all
intermediate profits upon it, together with their
:usual rate of profit upon the whole, from final
purchasers -- the consumers of shoes. Thus what appears
on the surface to be a tax upon shoe manufacturers
proves upon examination to be an indirect tax upon shoe
consumers, who pay in an accumulation of profits upon
the tax considerably more than the government
receives.
The effect would be the same if a tax
upon their leather output were imposed upon tanners.
Tanners would add to the price of leather the amount of
the tax, plus their usual rate of profit upon a like
investment, and collect the whole, together with the
cost of hides, of transportation, of tanning and of
selling, from shoe manufacturers, who would collect
with their profit from retailers, who would collect
with their profit from shoe consumers. The principle
applies also when taxes are levied upon the stock or
the sales of merchants, or the money or credits of
bankers; merchants add the tax with the usual profit to
the prices of their goods, and bankers add it to their
interest and discounts.
For example; a tax of $100,000 upon the
output of manufacturers or importers would, at 10 per
cent as the manufacturing profit, cost wholesalers
$110,000; at a profit of 10 per cent to wholesalers it
would cost retailers $121,000, and at 20 percent profit
to retailers it would finally impose a tax burden of
$145,200 — being 45 per cent more than the
government would get. Upon most commodities the number
of profits exceeds three, so that indirect taxes may
frequently cost as much as 100 per cent, even when
imposed only upon what are commercially known as
finished goods; when imposed upon materials also, the
cost of collection might well run far above 200 percent
in addition to the first cost of maintaining the
machinery of taxation.
It must not be supposed, however, that
the recovery of indirect taxes from the ultimate
consumers of taxed goods is arbitrary. When shoe
manufacturers, or tanners, or merchants add taxes to
prices, or bankers add them to interest, it is not
because they might do otherwise but choose to do this;
it is because the exigencies of trade compel them.
Manufacturers, merchants, and other tradesmen who carry
on competitive businesses must on the average sell
their goods at cost plus the ordinary rate of profit,
or go out of business. It follows that any increase in
cost of production tends to increase the price of
products. Now, a tax upon the output of business men,
which they must pay as a condition of doing their
business, is as truly part of the cost of their output
as is the price of the materials they buy or the wages
of the men they hire. Therefore, such a tax upon
business men tends to increase the price of their
products. And this tendency is more or less marked as
the tax is more or less great and competition more or
less keen.
It is true that a moderate tax upon
monopolized products, such as trade-mark goods,
proprietary medicines, patented articles and copyright
publications is not necessarily shifted to consumers.
The monopoly manufacturer whose prices are not checked
by cost of production, and are therefore as a rule
higher than competitive prices would be, may find it
more profitable to bear the burden of a tax that leaves
him some profit, by preserving his entire custom, than
to drive off part of his custom by adding the tax to
his usual prices. This is true also of a moderate
import tax to the extent it falls upon goods that are
more cheaply transported from the place of production
to a foreign market where the import tax is imposed
than to a home market where the goods would be free of
such a tax — products, for instance, of a farm in
Canada near to a New York town, but far away from any
Canadian town. If the tax be less than the difference
in the cost of transportation the producer will bear
the burden of it; otherwise he will not. The ultimate
effect would be a reduction in the value of the
Canadian land. Examples which may be cited in
opposition to the principle that import taxes are
indirect, will upon examination prove to be of the
character here described. Business cannot be carried on
at a loss — not for long.
9. "To collect taxes, to prevent and
punish evasions, to check and countercheck revenue
drawn from so many distinct sources, now make up
probably three-fourths, perhaps seven-eighths, of the
business of government outside of the preservation of
order, the maintenance of the military arm, and the
administration of justice." — Progress and
Poverty, book iv, ch: v
10. For a brief and thorough exposition
of indirect taxation read George's "Protection or Free
Trade," ch. viii, on " Tariffs for Revenue."
Whoever calmly reflects and candidly decides upon the
merits of indirect taxation must reject it in all its
forms. But to do that is to make a great stride toward
accepting the single tax. For the single tax is a form of
direct taxation; it cannot be shifted.11
11. This is usually a stumbling block to
those who, without much experience in economic thought,
consider the single tax for the first time. As soon as
they grasp the idea that taxes upon commodities shift
to consumers they jump to the conclusion that similarly
taxes upon land values would shift to the users. But
this is a mistake, and the explanation is simple. Taxes
upon what men produce make production more difficult
and so tend toward scarcity in the supply, which
stimulates prices; but taxes upon land, provided the
taxes be levied in proportion to value, tend toward
plenty in supply (meaning market supply of course),
because they make it more difficult to hold valuable
land idle, and so depress prices.
"A tax on rent falls wholly on the
landlord. There are no means by which he can shift the
burden upon anyone else. . . A tax on rent, therefore,
has no effect other than its obvious one. It merely
takes so much from the landlord and transfers it to the
state." — John Stuart Mill's Prin. of Pol. Ec.,
book v, ch. iii, sec. 1.
"A tax laid upon rent is borne solely by
the owner of land." — Bascom's Tr., p.159.
"Taxes which are levied on land . . .
really fall on the owner of the land." — Mrs.
Fawcett's Pol. Ec. for Beginners, pp.209, 210.
"A land tax levied in proportion to the
rent of land, and varying with every variation of
rents, . . . will fall wholly on the landlords."
— Walker's Pol. Ec., ed. of 1887, p. 413, quoting
Ricardo.
"The power of transferring a tax from the
person who actually pays it to some other person varies
with the object taxed. A tax on rents cannot be
transferred. A tax on commodities is always transferred
to the consumer." — Thorold Rogers's Pol. Ec.,
ch. xxi, 2d ed., p. 285.
"Though the landlord is in all cases the
real contributor, the tax is commonly advanced by the
tenant, to whom the landlord is obliged to allow it in
payment of the rent." — Adam Smith's Wealth of
Nations, book v, ch. ii, part ii, art. i.
"The way taxes raise prices is by
increasing the cost of production and checking supply.
But land is not a thing of human production, and taxes
upon rent cannot check supply. Therefore, though a tax
upon rent compels land-owners to pay more, it gives
them no power to obtain more for the use of their land,
as it in no way tends to reduce the supply of land. On
the contrary, by compelling those who hold land on
speculation to sell or let for what they can get, a tax
on land values tends to increase the competition
between owners, and thus to reduce the price of land."
— Progress and Poverty, book viii, ch. iii, subd.
i.
Sometimes this point is raised as a
question of shifting the tax in higher rent to the
tenant, and at others as a question of shifting it to
the consumers of goods in higher prices. The principle
is the same. Merchants cannot charge higher prices for
goods than their competitors do, merely because they
pay higher ground rents. A country storekeeper whose
business lot is worth but few dollars charges as much
for sugar, probably more, than a city grocer whose lot
is worth thousands. Quality for quality and quantity
for quantity, goods sell for about the same price
everywhere. Differences in price are altogether in
favor of places where land has a high value. This is
due to the fact that the cost of getting goods to
places of low land value, distant villages for example,
is greater than to centers, which are places of high
land value. Sometimes it is true that prices for some
things are higher where land values are high. Tiffany's
goods, for instance, may be more expensive than goods
of the same quality at a store on a less expensive
site. But that is not due to the higher land value; it
is because the dealer has a reputation for technical
knowledge and honesty (or has become a fad among rich
people), for which his customers are willing to pay
whether his store is on a high priced-lot or a
low-priced one.
Though land value has no effect upon the
price of good, it is easier to sell goods in some
locations than in others. Therefore, though the price
and the profit of each sale be the same, or even less,
in good locations than in poorer ones, aggregate
receipts and aggregate profits are much greater at the
good location. And it is out of his aggregate, and not
out of each profit, that rent is paid, For example: A
cigar store on a thoroughfare supplies a certain
quality of cigar for fifteen cents. On a side street
the same quality of cigar can be bought no cheaper.
Indeed, the cigars there are likely to be poorer, and
therefore really dearer. Yet ground rent on the
thoroughfare is very high compared with ground rent on
the sidestreet. How, then, can the first dealer, he who
pays the high ground rent, afford to sell as good or
better cigars for fifteen cents than his competitor of
the low priced location? Simply because he is able to
make so many more sales with a given outlay of labor
and capital in a given time that his aggregate profit
is greater. This is due to the advantage of his
location, and for that advantage he pays a premium in
higher ground rent. But that premium is not charged to
smokers; the competing dealer of the side street
protects them. It represents the greater ease, the
lower cost, of doing a given volume of business upon
the site for which it is paid; add if the state should
take any of it, even the whole of it, in taxation, the
loss would be finally borne by the owner of the
advantage which attaches to that site — by the
landlord. Any attempt to shift it to tenant or buyer
would be promptly checked by the competition of
neighboring but cheaper land.
"A land-tax, levied in proportion to the
rent of land, and varying with every variation of rent,
is in effect a tax on rent; and as such a tax will not
apply to that land which yields no rent, nor to the
produce of that capital which is employed on the land
with a view to profit merely, and which never pays
rent; it will not in any way affect the price of raw
produce, but will fall wholly on the landlords."
— McCulloch's Ricardo (3d ed.), p. 207
2. THE TWO KINDS OF DIRECT
TAXATION
Direct taxes fall into two general classes: (1) Taxes
that are levied upon men in proportion to their ability
to pay, and (2) taxes that are levied in proportion to
the benefits received by the tax-payer from the public.
Income taxes are the principal ones of the first class,
though probate and inheritance taxes would rank high. The
single tax is the only important one of the second
class.
There should be no difficulty in choosing between the
two. To tax in proportion to ability to pay, regardless
of benefits received, is in accord with no principle of
just government; it is a device of piracy. The single
tax, therefore, as the only important tax in proportion
to benefits, is the ideal tax.
But here we encounter two plausible objections. One
arises from the mistaken but common notion that men are
not taxed in proportion to benefits unless they pay taxes
upon every kind of property they own that comes under the
protection of government; the other is founded in the
assumption that it is impossible to measure the value of
the public benefits that each individual enjoys. Though
the first of these objections ostensibly accepts the
doctrine of taxation according to benefits,12 yet, as it
leads to attempts at taxation in proportion to wealth,
it, like the other, is really a plea for the piratical
doctrine of taxation according to ability to pay. The two
objections stand or fall together.
12. It is often said, for instance, by
its advocates, that house owners should in justice
contribute to the support of the fire departments that
protect them and it is even gravely argued that houses
are more appropriate subjects of taxation than land;
because they need protection, whereas land needs none.
Read note 8.
Let it once be perceived that the value of the service
which government renders to each individual would be
justly measured by the single tax, and neither objection
would any longer have weight. We should then no more
think of taxing people in proportion to their wealth or
ability to pay, regardless of the benefits they receive
from government than an honest merchant would think of
charging his customers in proportion to their wealth or
ability to pay, regardless of the value of the goods they
bought of him." 13
13. Following is an interesting
computation of the cost and loss to the city of Boston
of the present mixed system of taxation as compared
with the single tax; The computation was made by James
R. Carret, Esq., the leading conveyancer of Boston:
Valuation of Boston, May 1,
1892 Land... ... . .. ...
.. ... .. $399,170,175 Buildings ... ... ... ... ..$281,109,700
Total assessed value of real estate
$680,279,875 Assessed
value of personal estate $213,695,829
.... .... ... ... ... ... ...
... .... .... .... ... .... ...
$893,975,704 Rate of
taxation, $12.90 per $1000
Total tax levy, May 1, 1892 $11,805,036
Amount of taxes levied in respect of the
different subjects of taxation and percentages of the
same:
Land .... .... .... .... $5,149,295 43.62%
Buildings .... .... .. $3,626,295 30.72%
Personal estate .. $2,756,676 23.35%
Polls ... .... ... .... .... ...272,750
2.31%
But to ascertain the total cost to the
people of Boston of the present system of taxation for
the taxable year, beginning May 1, 1892, there should
be added to the taxes assessed upon them what it cost
them to pay the owners of the land of Boston for the
use of the land, being the net ground rent, which I
estimate at four per cent on the land value.
Total tax levy, May 1, 1892 ... ...
... ... .... .... .... .... .... ..... .... .... ....
.... .... .... ..$11,805,036 Net ground rent, four percent, on the land value
($399,170,175)..... ... ... ...$15,966,807
Total cost of the present system to
the people of Boston for that year ...
$27,771,843
To contrast this with what the single tax
system would have cost the people of Boston for that
year, take the gross ground rent, found by adding to
the net ground rent the taxation on land values for
that year, being $12.90 per $1000, or 1.29 per cent
added to 4 per cent = 5.29 per cent.
Total cost of present system as
above .. .... .... .... .... .... .... .... ....
....$27,771,843 Single
tax, or gross ground rent, 5.29 per cent on
$399,170,175 ... ..$21,116,102
Excess cost of present system, which
is the sum of taxes in
respect of buildings, personal property, and polls ....
...... .. $6,655,741
But the present system not only costs the
people more than the single tax would, but produces
less revenue:
Proceeds of single tax ... ... ...
... ..... .... .... ..... .... .... .... ..... .....
.... $21,116,102 Present
tax levy ... ... ... ... ... .... .... .... ..... ....
.... .... .... .... .... ....
....$11,805,036 Loss to
public treasury by present system ... .... .... ....
.... .. ..... ..$9,311,066
This, however, is not a complete contrast
between the present system and the single tax, for
large amounts of real estate are exempt from taxation,
being held by the United States, the Commonwealth, by
the city itself, by religious societies and
corporations, and by charitable, literary, and
scientific institutions. The total amount of the value
of land so held as returned by the assessors for the
year 1892 is $60,626,171.
Reasons can be given why all lands within
the city should be assessed for taxation to secure a
just distribution of the public burdens, which I cannot
take the space to enter into here. There is good reason
to believe also that lands in the city of Boston are
assessed to quite an appreciable extent below their
fair market value. As an indication of this see an
editorial in the Boston Daily Advertiser for
October 3, 1893, under the title, "Their Own
Figures."
The vacant lands, marsh lands, and flats
in Boston were valued by the assessors in 1892 (page 3
of their annual report) at $52,712,600. I believe that
this represents not more than fifty per cent of their
true market value.
Taking this and the undervaluation of
improved property and the exemptions above mentioned
into consideration, I think $500,000,000 to be a fair
estimate of the land values of Boston. Making this the
basis of contrast, we have:
Proceeds of single tax 5.29 per
cent on $500,000,000 ... .... .... ....
$26,450,000 Present tax
levy ... .... ... .... .... .... .... .... ..... ....
.... .... .... ..... .... ....
..$11,805,036 Loss to
public treasury by present system ... ... ... ... ....
.... .... ....$14,644,974
3. THE SINGLE TAX FALLS IN
PROPORTION TO BENEFITS
To perceive that the single tax would justly measure the
value of government service we have only to realize that
the mass of individuals everywhere and now, in paying for
the land they use, actually pay for government service in
proportion to what they receive. He who would enjoy the
benefits of a government must use land within its
jurisdiction. He cannot carry land from where government
is poor to where it is good; neither can he carry it from
where the benefits of good government are few or enjoyed
with difficulty to where they are many and fully enjoyed.
He must rent or buy land where the benefits of government
are available, or forego them. And unless he buys or
rents where they are greatest and most available he must
forego them in degree. Consequently, if he would work or
live where the benefits of government are available, and
does not already own land there, he will be compelled to
rent or buy at a valuation which, other things being
equal, will depend upon the value of the government
service that the site he selects enables him to enjoy. 14
Thus does he pay for the service of government in
proportion to its value to him. But he does not pay the
public which provides the service; he is required to pay
land-owners.
14. Land values are lower in all
countries of poor government than in any country of
better government, other things being equal. They are
lower in cities of poor government, other things being
equal, than in cities of better government. Land values
are lower, for example, in Juarez, on the Mexican side
of the Rio Grande, where government is bad, than in El
Paso, the neighboring city on the American side, where
government is better. They are lower in the same city
under bad government than under improved government.
When Seth Low, after a reform campaign, was elected
mayor of Brooklyn, N.Y., rents advanced before he took
the oath of office, upon the bare expectation that he
would eradicate municipal abuses. Let the city
authorities anywhere pave a street, put water through
it and sewer it, or do any of these things, and lots in
the neighborhood rise in value. Everywhere that the
"good roads" agitation of wheel men has borne fruit in
better highways, the value of adjacent land has
increased. Instances of this effect as results of
public improvements might be collected in abundance.
Every man must be able to recall some within his own
experience.
And it is perfectly reasonable that it
should be so. Land and not other property must rise in
value with desired improvements in government, because,
while any tendency on the part of other kinds of
property to rise in value is checked by greater
production, land can not be reproduced.
Imagine an utterly lawless place, where
life and property are constantly threatened by
desperadoes. He must be either a very bold man or a
very avaricious one who will build a store in such a
community and stock it with goods; but suppose such a
man should appear. His store costs him more than the
same building would cost in a civilized community;
mechanics are not plentiful in such a place, and
materials are hard to get. The building is finally
erected, however, and stocked. And now what about this
merchant's prices for goods? Competition is weak,
because there are few men who will take the chances he
has taken, and he charges all that his customers will
pay. A hundred per cent, five hundred per cent, perhaps
one or two thousand per cent profit rewards him for his
pains and risk. His goods are dear, enormously dear
— dear enough to satisfy the most contemptuous
enemy of cheapness; and if any one should wish to buy
his store that would be dear too, for the difficulties
in the way of building continue. But land is
cheap! This is the type of community in which may
be found that land, so often mentioned and so seldom
seen, which "the owners actually can't give away, you
know!"
But suppose that government improves. An
efficient administration of justice rids the place of
desperadoes, and life and property are safe. What about
prices then? It would no longer require a bold or
desperately avaricious man to engage in selling goods
in that community, and competition would set in. High
profits would soon come down. Goods would be cheap
— as cheap as anywhere in the world, the cost of
transportation considered. Builders and building
materials could be had without difficulty, and stores
would be cheap, too. But land would be dear!
Improvement in government increases the value of that,
and of that alone.
Now, the economic principle pursuant to which
land-owners are thus able to charge their fellow-citizens
for the common benefits of their common government points
to the true method of taxation. With the exception of
such other monopoly property as is analogous to land
titles, and which in the purview of the single tax is
included with land for purposes of taxation, 15 land is
the only kind of property that is increased in value by
government; and the increase of value is in proportion,
other influences aside, to the public service which its
possession secures to the occupant. Therefore, by taxing
land in proportion to its value, and exempting all other
property, kindred monopolies excepted — that is to
say, by adopting the single tax — we should be
levying taxes according to benefits.16
15. Railroad franchises, for example, are
not usually thought of as land titles, but that is what
they are. By an act of sovereign authority they confer
rights of control for transportation purposes over
narrow strips of land between terminals and along
trading points. The value of this right of way is a
land value.
16. Each occupant would pay to his
landlord the value of the public benefits in the way of
highways, schools, courts, police and fire protection,
etc., that his site enabled him to enjoy. The landlord
would pay a tax proportioned to the pecuniary benefits
conferred upon him by the public in raising and
maintaining the value of his holding. And if occupant
and owner were the same, he would pay directly
according to the value of his land for all the public
benefits he enjoyed, both intangible and pecuniary.
And in no sense would this be class taxation. Indeed,
the cry of class taxation is a rather impudent one for
owners of valuable land to raise against the single tax,
when it is considered that under existing systems of
taxation they are exempt. 17 Even the poorest and the
most degraded classes in the community, besides paying
land-owners for such public benefits as come their way,
are compelled by indirect taxation to contribute to the
support of government. But landowners as a class go free.
They enjoy the protection of the courts, and of police
and fire departments, and they have the use of schools
and the benefit of highways and other public
improvements, all in common with the most favored, and
upon the same specific terms; yet, though they go through
the form of paying taxes, and if their holdings are of
considerable value pose as "the tax-payers" on
all important occasions, they, in effect and considered
as a class, pay no taxes, because government, by
increasing the value of their land, enables them to
recover back in higher rents and higher prices more than
their taxes amount to. Enjoying the same tangible
benefits of government that others do, many of them as
individuals and all of them as a class receive in
addition a tangible pecuniary benefit which government
confers upon no other property-owners. The value of their
property is enhanced in proportion to the benefits of
government which its occupants enjoy. To tax them alone,
therefore, is not to discriminate against them; it is to
charge them for what they get.18
17. While the landholders of the City of
Washington were paying something less than two per cent
annually in taxes, a Congressional Committee
(Report of the Select Committee to Investigate Tax
Assessments in the District of Columbia, composed of
Messrs. Johnson, of Ohio, Chairman, Wadsworth, of New
York, and Washington, of Tennessee. Made to the House
of Representatives, May 24, 1892. Report No.
1469), brought out the fact that the value of
their land had been increasing at a minimum rate of ten
per cent per annum. The Washington land-owners as a
class thus appear to have received back in higher land
values, actually and potentially, about ten dollars for
every two dollars that as land-owners they paid in
taxes. If any one supposes that this condition is
peculiar to Washington let him make similar estimates
for any progressive locality, and see if the
land-owners there are not favored in like manner.
But the point is not dependent upon
increase in the capitalized value of land. If the land
yields or will yield to its owner an income in the
nature of actual or potential ground rent, then to the
extent that this actual or possible income is dependent
upon government the landlord is in effect exempt from
taxation. No matter what tax he pays on account of his
ownership of land, the public gives it back to him to
that extent.
18. Take for illustration two towns, one
of excellent government and the other of inefficient
government, but in all other respects alike. Suppose
you are hunting for a place of residence and find a
suitable site in the town of good government. For
simplicity of illustration let us suppose that the land
there is not sold outright but is let upon ground rent.
You meet the owner of the lot you have selected and ask
him his terms. He replies:
"Two hundred and fifty dollars a
year."
"Two hundred and fifty dollars a year!"
you exclaim. "Why, I can get just as good a site in
that other town for a hundred dollars a year."
"Certainly you can," he will say. "But if
you build a house there and it catches fire it will
burn down; they have no fire department. If you go out
after dark you will be 'held up' and robbed; they have
no police force. If you ride out in the spring, your
carriage will stick in the mud up to the hubs, and if
you walk you may break your legs and will be lucky if
you don t break your neck; they have no street
pavements and their sidewalks are dangerously out of
repair. When the moon doesn't shine the streets are in
darkness, for they have no street lights. The water you
need for your house you must get from a well; there is
no water supply there. Now in our town it is different.
We have a splendid fire department, and the best police
force in the world. Our streets are macadamized, and
lighted with electricity; our sidewalks are always in
first class repair; we have a water system that equals
that of New York; and in every way the public benefits
in this town are unsurpassed. It is the best governed
town in all this region. Isn't it worth a hundred and
fifty dollars a year more for a building site here than
over in that poorly governed town?"
You recognize the advantages and agree to
the terms. But when your house is built and the
assessor visits you officially, what would be the
conversation if your sense of the fitness of things
were not warped by familiarity with false systems of
taxation? Would it not be something like what
follows?
"How much do you regard this house as
worth? " asks the assessor.
"What is that to you?" you inquire.
"I am the town assessor and am about to
appraise your property for taxation."
"Am I to be taxed by this town? What
for?"
"What for?" echoes the assessor in
surprise. "What for? Is not your house protected from
fire by our magnificent fire department? Are not you
protected from robbery by the best police force in the
world? Do not you have the use of macadamized
pavements, and good sidewalks, and electric street
lights, and a first class water supply? Don't you
suppose these things cost something? And don't you
think you ought to pay your share?"
"Yes," you answer, with more or
less calmness; "I do have the benefit of these things,
and I do think that I ought to pay my share toward
supporting them. But I have already paid my share for
this year. I have paid it to the owner of this lot. He
charges me two hundred and fifty dollars a year -- one
hundred and fifty dollars more than I should pay or he
could get but for those very benefits. He has
collected my share of this year's expense of
maintaining town improvements; you go and collect from
him. If you do not, but insist upon collecting from me,
I shall be paying twice for these things, once to him
and once to you; and he won't be paying at all, but
will be making money out of them, although he derives
the same benefits from them in all other respects that
I do." ...
d. Effect of Confiscating Rent to Private
Use.
By giving Rent to individuals society ignores this
most just law, 99 thereby creating social disorder and
inviting social disease. Upon society alone, therefore,
and not upon divine Providence which has provided
bountifully, nor upon the disinherited poor, rests the
responsibility for poverty and fear of poverty.
99. "Whatever dispute arouses the
passions of men, the conflict is sure to rage, not so
much as to the question 'Is it wise?' as to the
question 'Is it right?'
"This tendency of popular discussions to
take an ethical form has a cause. It springs from a law
of the human mind; it rests upon a vague and
instinctive recognition of what is probably the deepest
truth we can grasp. That alone is wise which is just;
that alone is enduring which is right. In the narrow
scale of individual actions and individual life this
truth may be often obscured, but in the wider field of
national life it everywhere stands out.
"I bow to this arbitrament, and accept
this test." — Progress and Poverty, book vii, ch.
i.
The reader who has been deceived into
believing that Mr. George's proposition is in any
respect unjust, will find profit in a perusal of the
entire chapter from which the foregoing extract is
taken.
Let us try to trace the connection by means of a
chart, beginning with the white spaces on page 68. As
before, the first-comers take possession of the best
land. But instead of leaving for others what they do not
themselves need for use, as in the previous
illustrations, they appropriate the whole space, using
only part, but claiming ownership of the rest. We may
distinguish the used part with red color, and that which
is appropriated without use with blue. Thus: [chart]
But what motive is there for appropriating more of the
space than is used? Simply that the appropriators may
secure the pecuniary benefit of future social growth.
What will enable them to secure that? Our system of
confiscating Rent from the community that earns it, and
giving it to land-owners who, as such, earn
nothing.100
100. It is reported from Iowa that a few
years ago a workman in that State saw a meteorite fall,
and. securing possession of it after much digging, he
was offered $105 by a college for his "find." But the
owner of the land on which the meteorite fell claimed
the money, and the two went to law about it. After an
appeal to the highest court of the State, it was
finally decided that neither by right of discovery, nor
by right of labor, could the workman have the money,
because the title to the meteorite was in the man who
owned the land upon which it fell.
Observe the effect now upon Rent and Wages. When other
men come, instead of finding half of the best land still
common and free, as in the corresponding chart on page
68, they find all of it owned, and are obliged either to
go upon poorer land or to buy or rent from owners of the
best. How much will they pay for the best? Not more than
1, if they want it for use and not to hold for a higher
price in the future, for that represents the full
difference between its productiveness and the
productiveness of the next best. But if the first-comers,
reasoning that the next best land will soon be scarce and
theirs will then rise in value, refuse to sell or to rent
at that valuation, the newcomers must resort to land of
the second grade, though the best be as yet only partly
used. Consequently land of the first grade commands Rent
before it otherwise would.
As the sellers' price, under these circumstances, is
arbitrary it cannot be stated in the chart; but the
buyers' price is limited by the superiority of the best
land over that which can be had for nothing, and the
chart may be made to show it: [chart]
And now, owing to the success of the appropriators of
the best land in securing more than their fellows for the
same expenditure of labor force, a rush is made for
unappropriated land. It is not to use it that it is
wanted, but to enable its appropriators to put Rent into
their own pockets as soon as growing demand for land
makes it valuable.101 We may, for illustration, suppose
that all the remainder of the second space and the whole
of the third are thus appropriated, and note the effect:
[chart]
At this point Rent does not increase nor Wages fall,
because there is no increased demand for land for use.
The holding of inferior land for higher prices, when
demand for use is at a standstill, is like owning lots in
the moon — entertaining, perhaps, but not
profitable. But let more land be needed for use, and
matters promptly assume a different appearance. The new
labor must either go to the space that yields but 1, or
buy or rent from owners of better grades, or hire out.
The effect would be the same in any case. Nobody for the
given expenditure of labor force would get more than 1;
the surplus of products would go to landowners as Rent,
either directly in rent payments, or indirectly through
lower Wages. Thus: [chart]
101. The text speaks of Rent only as a
periodical or continuous payment — what would be
called "ground rent." But actual or potential Rent may
always be, and frequently is, capitalized for the
purpose of selling the right to enjoy it, and it is to
selling value that we usually refer when dealing in
land.
Land which has the power of yielding Rent
to its owner will have a selling value, whether it be
used or not, and whether Rent is actually derived from
it or not. This selling value will be the
capitalization of its present or prospective power of
producing Rent. In fact, much the larger proportion of
laud that has a selling value is wholly or partly
unused, producing no Rent at all, or less than it would
if fully used. This condition is expressed in the chart
by the blue color.
"The capitalized value of land is the
actuarial 'discounted' value of all the net incomes
which it is likely to afford, allowance being made on
the one hand for all incidental expenses, including
those of collecting the rents, and on the other for its
mineral wealth, its capabilities of development for any
kind of business, and its advantages, material, social,
and aesthetic, for the purposes of residence." —
Marshall's Prin., book vi, ch. ix, sec. 9.
"The value of land is commonly expressed
as a certain number of times the current money rental,
or in other words, a certain 'number of years'
purchase' of that rental; and other things being equal,
it will be the higher the more important these direct
gratifications are, as well as the greater the chance
that they and the money income afforded by the land
will rise." — Id., note.
"Value . . . means not utility, not any
quality inhering in the thing itself, but a quality
which gives to the possession of a thing the power of
obtaining other things, in return for it or for its
use. . . Value in this sense — the usual sense
— is purely relative. It exists from and is
measured by the power of obtaining things for things by
exchanging them. . . Utility is necessary to value, for
nothing can be valuable unless it has the quality of
gratifying some physical or mental desire of man,
though it be but a fancy or whim. But utility of itself
does not give value. . . If we ask ourselves the reason
of . . . variations in . . . value . . . we see that
things having some form of utility or desirability, are
valuable or not valuable, as they are hard or easy to
get. And if we ask further, we may see that with most
of the things that have value this difficulty or ease
of getting them, which determines value, depends on the
amount of labor which must be expended in producing
them ; i.e., bringing them into the place, form and
condition in which they are desired. . . Value is
simply an expression of the labor required for the
production of such a thing. But there are some things
as to which this is not so clear. Land is not produced
by labor, yet land, irrespective of any improvements
that labor has made on it, often has value. . . Yet a
little examination will show that such facts are but
exemplifications of the general principle, just as the
rise of a balloon and the fall of a stone both
exemplify the universal law of gravitation. . . The
value of everything produced by labor, from a pound of
chalk or a paper of pins to the elaborate structure and
appurtenances of a first-class ocean steamer, is
resolvable on analysis into an equivalent of the labor
required to produce such a thing in form and place;
while the value of things not produced by labor, but
nevertheless susceptible of ownership, is in the same
way resolvable into an equivalent of the labor which
the ownership of such a thing enables the owner to
obtain or save." —
Perplexed Philosopher, ch. v.
The figure 1 in parenthesis, as an item of Rent,
indicates potential Rent. Labor would give that much for
the privilege of using the space, but the owners hold out
for better terms; therefore neither Rent nor Wages is
actually produced, though but for this both might be.
In this chart, notwithstanding that but little space
is used, indicated with red, Wages are reduced to the
same low point by the mere appropriation of space,
indicated with blue, that they would reach if all the
space above the poorest were fully used. It thereby
appears that under a system which confiscates Rent to
private uses, the demand for land for speculative
purposes becomes so great that Wages fall to a minimum
long before they would if land were appropriated only for
use.
In illustrating the effect of confiscating Rent to
private use we have as yet ignored the element of social
growth. Let us now assume as before (page 73), that
social growth increases the productive power of the given
expenditure of labor force to 100 when applied to the
best land, 50 when applied to the next best, 10 to the
next, 3 to the next, and 1 to the poorest. Labor would
not be benefited now, as it appeared to be when on page
73 we illustrated the appropriation of land for use only,
although much less land is actually used. The prizes
which expectation of future social growth dangles before
men as the rewards of owning land, would raise demand so
as to make it more than ever difficult to get land. All
of the fourth grade would be taken up in expectation of
future demand; and "surplus labor" would be crowded out
to the open space that originally yielded nothing, but
which in consequence of increased labor power now yields
as much as the poorest closed space originally yielded,
namely, 1 to the given expenditure of labor force.102
Wages would then be reduced to the present productiveness
of the open space. Thus: [chart]
102. The paradise to which the youth of
our country have so long been directed in the advice,
"Go West, young man, go West," is truthfully described
in "Progress and Poverty," book iv, ch. iv, as follows
:
"The man who sets out from the eastern
seaboard in search of the margin of cultivation,
where he may obtain land without paying rent, must,
like the man who swam the river to get a drink, pass
for long distances through half-titled farms, and
traverse vast areas of virgin soil, before he reaches
the point where land can be had free of rent —
i.e., by homestead entry or preemption."
If we assume that 1 for the given expenditure of labor
force is the least that labor can take while exerting the
same force, the downward movement of Wages will be here
held in equilibrium. They cannot fall below 1; but
neither can they rise above it, no matter how much
productive power may increase, so long as it pays to hold
land for higher values. Some laborers would continually
be pushed back to land which increased productive power
would have brought up in productiveness from 0 to 1, and
by perpetual competition for work would so regulate the
labor market that the given expenditure of labor force,
however much it produced, could nowhere secure more than
1 in Wages.103 And this tendency would persist until some
labor was forced upon land which, despite increase in
productive power, would not yield the accustomed living
without increase of labor force. Competition for work
would then compel all laborers to increase their
expenditure of labor force, and to do it over and over
again as progress went on and lower and lower grades of
land were monopolized, until human endurance could go no
further.104 Either that, or they would be obliged to
adapt themselves to a lower scale of living.105
103. Henry Fawcett, in his work on
"Political Economy," book ii, ch. iii, observes with
reference to improvements in agricultural implements
which diminish the expense of cultivation, that they do
not increase the profits of the farmer or the wages of
his laborers, but that "the landlord will receive in
addition to the rent already paid to him, all that is
saved in the expense of cultivation." This is true not
alone of improvements in agriculture, but also of
improvements in all other branches of industry.
104. "The cause which limits speculation
in commodities, the tendency of increasing price to
draw forth additional supplies, cannot limit the
speculative advance in land values, as land is a fixed
quantity, which human agency can neither increase nor
diminish; but there is nevertheless a limit to the
price of land, in the minimum required by labor and
capital as the condition of engaging in production. If
it were possible to continuously reduce wages until
zero were reached, it would be possible to continuously
increase rent until it swallowed up the whole produce.
But as wages cannot be permanently reduced below the
point at which laborers will consent to work and
reproduce, nor interest below the point at which
capital will be devoted to production, there is a limit
which restrains the speculative advance of rent. Hence,
speculation cannot have the same scope to advance rent
in countries where wages and interest are already near
the minimum, as in countries where they are
considerably above it. Yet that there is in all
progressive countries a constant tendency in the
speculative advance of rent to overpass the limit where
production would cease, is, I think, shown by recurring
seasons of industrial paralysis." — Progress and
Poverty, book iv, ch. iv.
105. As Puck once put it, "the man who
makes two blades of grass to grow where but one grew
before, must not be surprised when ordered to 'keep off
the grass.' "
They in fact do both, and the incidental disturbances
of general readjustment are what we call "hard times."
106 These culminate in forcing unused land into the
market, thereby reducing Rent and reviving industry. Thus
increase of labor force, a lowering of the scale of
living, and depression of Rent, co-operate to bring on
what we call "good times." But no sooner do "good times"
return than renewed demands for land set in, Rent rises
again, Wages fall again, and "hard times" duly reappear.
The end of every period of "hard times" finds Rent higher
and Wages lower than at the end of the previous
period.107
106. "That a speculative advance in rent
or land values invariably precedes each of these
seasons of industrial depression is everywhere clear.
That they bear to each other the relation of cause and
effect, is obvious to whoever considers the necessary
relation between land and labor." — Progress and
Poverty, book v, ch. i.
107. What are called "good times" reach a
point at which an upward land market sets in. From that
point there is a downward tendency of wages (or a rise
in the cost of living, which is the same thing) in all
departments of labor and with all grades of laborers.
This tendency continues until the fictitious values of
land give way. So long as the tendency is felt only by
that class which is hired for wages, it is poverty
merely; when the same tendency is felt by the class of
labor that is distinguished as "the business interests
of the country," it is "hard times." And "hard times"
are periodical because land values, by falling, allow
"good times " to set it, and by rising with "good
times" bring "hard times" on again. The effect of "hard
times" may be overcome, without much, if any, fall in
land values, by sufficient increase in productive power
to overtake the fictitious value of land.
The dishonest and disorderly system under which
society confiscates Rent from common to individual uses,
produces this result. That maladjustment is the
fundamental cause of poverty. And progress, so long as
the maladjustment continues, instead of tending to remove
poverty as naturally it should, actually generates and
intensifies it. Poverty persists with increase of
productive power because land values, when Rent is
privately appropriated, tend to even greater increase.
There can be but one outcome if this continues: for
individuals suffering and degradation, and for society
destruction.
Q22. What difference would it make to tenants
whether they paid land rent to the community or to
private owners?
A. When they pay it to the community they are paying it
in part to themselves, and what others pay they share in;
for they are part of the community. They are also exempt
from taxes. And since there would be no inducement to
speculate in land if rent went to the community, land
would be more plentiful and rents would consequently be
lower. ...
read the book
Charles B. Fillebrown: A Catechism of
Natural Taxation, from Principles of Natural
Taxation (1917)
Q28. How are landlords privileged?
A. Because, in so far as their land tax is an "old" tax,
it is a burdenless tax, and because their buildings' tax
is shifted upon their tenants; most landlords who let
land and also the tenement houses and business blocks
thereon avoid all share in the tax burden.
Q51. Does not a land tax increase house rent or
store rent?
A. The landlord, as a rule, exacts the full ground rent
for the use of his land. Neither by taking three dollars
nor $30 per thousand in taxation can land to be made
worth any more for use.
Q55. How would the single tax effect the
tenant?
A. It would neither increase nor decrease his land rent.
It would reduce his house rent by the amount of the house
tax. ... read the whole
article
Peter Barnes:
Capitalism 3.0 — Chapter 1: Time to Upgrade (pages
3-14)
More than a century ago, English economist John Ruskin
observed that the same economic system that creates
glittering wealth also spawns what he called illth
— poverty, pollution, despair, illness. It makes
life comfortable for some, but does so at considerable
discomfort to others.
Modern economists’ term for illth is negative
externalities. By this they mean the costs of economic
transactions that are “external” to the
parties involved. The classic example is a factory that
dumps effluent into a river. Unlike homeowners who pay
for garbage pickup, the factory’s owners pay
nothing for disposing their waste into the river. But
humans and other creatures living downstream do pay a
cost. Plants and animals suffer and die, while cities
have to build expensive treatment plants. From the
standpoint of the factory owner, none of this matters.
But from the standpoints of nature and society, these are
negative externalities. (There can, sometimes, be
positive externalities — for example, if your
neighbor repaints her house, that may increase the value
of yours.)
For a long time, economists assured us that the wealth
spewed out by our economic machine was so great, and the
illth so trivial, that we didn’t need to worry
about negative externalities. If this was ever true,
it’s assuredly true no longer. Contemporary climate
change is, quintessentially, a problem of negative
externalities. We pay owners of land beneath
which fossil fuels lie. We pay drillers, refiners,
transporters, and retailers. But we don’t pay
nature, or anyone else, for dumping heat-trapping gases
into the atmosphere. We shift this cost to our children,
and take a free ride. We party, they pay. ...
read the whole chapter
|
To share this page with a friend:
right click, choose "send," and add your
comments.
|
|
Red links have not been
visited; .
Green links are pages you've seen
|
Essential Documents pertinent
to this theme:
essential_documents
|
|