Taxes and Moral Law
What passes for conversations about "tax reform"
usually is a matter of discussing what the tax brackets
and tax rates should be for the federal or state income
tax. But income taxes are neither moral nor otherwise
desirable: their perverse incentives are exceeded only by
their immoral quality — they take from the
individual that which he labors to create.
But taxes on land value are fundamentally different.
None of us created land, nor can we trace our title in
land to the one who created it. All of us were created
equal, and should share equally in the value of our
common assets, which includes the economic value of
America's land. Land's value comes from the presence of
each one of us, from naturally provided amenities, from
increases of population, and from the economic activity
of the society as a whole. Why on earth should its value
be subject to privatization? ("Tradition" is no better an
answer to this question than it was to the question of
whether chattel slavery was or is just in a society
devoted to the proposition that all of us are created
equal.!)
Land value taxation, unlike any other kind of
taxation, takes from individuals only that which SOCIETY,
NATURE and OUR FELLOWS have created, not what he himself
created. So it is supremely moral, unlike taxes on wages,
sales and buildings. Even better, the incentives it
creates are consistent with the common good, with widely
shared prosperity, with abolishing poverty.
That's the intersection of taxes and moral law.
Henry George: The Condition of Labor
— An Open Letter to Pope Leo XIII in response to
Rerum Novarum (1891)
Nor do we hesitate to say that this way of securing
the equal right to the bounty of the Creator and the
exclusive right to the products of labor is the way
intended by God for raising public revenues. For we are
not atheists, who deny God; nor semi-atheists, who deny
that he has any concern in politics and legislation.
It is true as you say — a salutary truth too
often forgotten — that “man is older than the
state, and he holds the right of providing for the life
of his body prior to the formation of any state.”
Yet, as you too perceive, it is also true that the state
is in the divinely appointed order. For He who foresaw
all things and provided for all things, foresaw and
provided that with the increase of population and the
development of industry the organization of human society
into states or governments would become both expedient
and necessary.
No sooner does the state arise than, as we all know,
it needs revenues. This need for revenues is small at
first, while population is sparse, industry rude and the
functions of the state few and simple. But with growth of
population and advance of civilization the functions of
the state increase and larger and larger revenues are
needed.
Now, He that made the world and placed man in it, He
that pre-ordained civilization as the means whereby man
might rise to higher powers and become more and more
conscious of the works of his Creator, must have foreseen
this increasing need for state revenues and have made
provision for it. That is to say: The increasing need for
public revenues with social advance, being a natural,
God-ordained need, there must be a right way of raising
them — some way that we can truly say is the way
intended by God. It is clear that this right way of
raising public revenues must accord with the moral
law.
Hence:
- It must not take from individuals what rightfully
belongs to individuals.
- It must not give some an advantage over others, as by
increasing the prices of what some have to sell and
others must buy.
- It must not lead men into temptation, by requiring
trivial oaths, by making it profitable to lie, to swear
falsely, to bribe or to take bribes.
- It must not confuse the distinctions of right and
wrong, and weaken the sanctions of religion and the state
by creating crimes that are not sins, and punishing men
for doing what in itself they have an undoubted right to
do.
- It must not repress industry. It must not check
commerce. It must not punish thrift. It must offer no
impediment to the largest production and the fairest
division of wealth.
Let me ask your Holiness to consider the taxes on the
processes and products of industry by which through the
civilized world public revenues are collected — the
octroi duties that surround Italian cities with barriers;
the monstrous customs duties that hamper intercourse
between so-called Christian states; the taxes on
occupations, on earnings, on investments, on the building
of houses, on the cultivation of fields, on industry and
thrift in all forms. Can these be the ways God has
intended that governments should raise the means they
need? Have any of them the characteristics indispensable
in any plan we can deem a right one?
All these taxes violate the moral law. They take by
force what belongs to the individual alone; they give to
the unscrupulous an advantage over the scrupulous; they
have the effect, nay are largely intended, to increase
the price of what some have to sell and others must buy;
they corrupt government; they make oaths a mockery; they
shackle commerce; they fine industry and thrift; they
lessen the wealth that men might enjoy, and enrich some
by impoverishing others.
Yet what most strikingly shows how opposed to
Christianity is this system of raising public revenues is
its influence on thought.
Christianity teaches us that all men are brethren;
that their true interests are harmonious, not
antagonistic. It gives us, as the golden rule of life,
that we should do to others as we would have others do to
us. But out of the system of taxing the products and
processes of labor, and out of its effects in increasing
the price of what some have to sell and others must buy,
has grown the theory of “protection,” which
denies this gospel, which holds Christ ignorant of
political economy and proclaims laws of national
well-being utterly at variance with his teaching. This
theory sanctifies national hatreds; it inculcates a
universal war of hostile tariffs; it teaches peoples that
their prosperity lies in imposing on the productions of
other peoples restrictions they do not wish imposed on
their own; and instead of the Christian doctrine of
man’s brotherhood it makes injury of foreigners a
civic virtue.
“By their fruits ye shall know them.” Can
anything more clearly show that to tax the products and
processes of industry is not the way God intended public
revenues to be raised?
But to consider what we propose — the raising of
public revenues by a single tax on the value of land
irrespective of improvements — is to see that in
all respects this does conform to the moral law.
Let me ask your Holiness to keep in mind that the
value we propose to tax, the value of land irrespective
of improvements, does not come from any exertion of labor
or investment of capital on or in it — the values
produced in this way being values of improvement which we
would exempt. The value of land irrespective of
improvement is the value that attaches to land by reason
of increasing population and social progress. This is a
value that always goes to the owner as owner, and never
does and never can go to the user; for if the user be a
different person from the owner he must always pay the
owner for it in rent or in purchase-money; while if the
user be also the owner, it is as owner, not as user, that
he receives it, and by selling or renting the land he
can, as owner, continue to receive it after he ceases to
be a user.
Thus, taxes on land irrespective of improvement cannot
lessen the rewards of industry, nor add to prices,* nor
in any way take from the individual what belongs to the
individual. They can take only the value that attaches to
land by the growth of the community, and which therefore
belongs to the community as a whole.
* As to this point it may be well to add
that all economists are agreed that taxes on land
values irrespective of improvement or use — or
what in the terminology of political economy is styled
rent, a term distinguished from the ordinary use of the
word rent by being applied solely to payments for the
use of land itself — must be paid by the owner
and cannot be shifted by him on the user. To explain in
another way the reason given in the text: Price is not
determined by the will of the seller or the will of the
buyer, but by the equation of demand and supply, and
therefore as to things constantly demanded and
constantly produced rests at a point determined by the
cost of production — whatever tends to increase
the cost of bringing fresh quantities of such articles
to the consumer increasing price by checking supply,
and whatever tends to reduce such cost decreasing price
by increasing supply. Thus taxes on wheat or tobacco or
cloth add to the price that the consumer must pay, and
thus the cheapening in the cost of producing steel
which improved processes have made in recent years has
greatly reduced the price of steel. But land has no
cost of production, since it is created by God, not
produced by man. Its price therefore is fixed
—
1 (monopoly rent), where land is held
in close monopoly, by what the owners can extract
from the users under penalty of deprivation and
consequently of starvation, and amounts to all that
common labor can earn on it beyond what is necessary
to life;
2 (economic rent proper), where there is no special
monopoly, by what the particular land will yield to
common labor over and above what may be had by like
expenditure and exertion on land having no special
advantage and for which no rent is paid; and,
3 (speculative rent, which is a species of monopoly
rent, telling particularly in selling price), by the
expectation of future increase of value from social
growth and improvement, which expectation causing
landowners to withhold land at present prices has the
same effect as combination.
Taxes on land values or economic rent can
therefore never be shifted by the landowner to the
land-user, since they in no wise increase the demand
for land or enable landowners to check supply by
withholding land from use. Where rent depends on mere
monopolization, a case I mention because rent may in
this way be demanded for the use of land even before
economic or natural rent arises, the taking by taxation
of what the landowners were able to extort from labor
could not enable them to extort any more, since
laborers, if not left enough to live on, will die. So,
in the case of economic rent proper, to take from the
landowners the premiums they receive, would in no way
increase the superiority of their land and the demand
for it. While, so far as price is affected by
speculative rent, to compel the landowners to pay taxes
on the value of land whether they were getting any
income from it or not, would make it more difficult for
them to withhold land from use; and to tax the full
value would not merely destroy the power but the desire
to do so.
To take land values for the state, abolishing all
taxes on the products of labor, would therefore leave to
the laborer the full produce of labor; to the individual
all that rightfully belongs to the individual. It would
impose no burden on industry, no check on commerce, no
punishment on thrift; it would secure the largest
production and the fairest distribution of wealth, by
leaving men free to produce and to exchange as they
please, without any artificial enhancement of prices; and
by taking for public purposes a value that cannot be
carried off, that cannot be hidden, that of all values is
most easily ascertained and most certainly and cheaply
collected, it would enormously lessen the number of
officials, dispense with oaths, do away with temptations
to bribery and evasion, and abolish man-made crimes in
themselves innocent.
But, further: That God has intended the state to
obtain the revenues it needs by the taxation of land
values is shown by the same order and degree of evidence
that shows that God has intended the milk of the mother
for the nourishment of the babe.
See how close is the analogy. In that primitive
condition ere the need for the state arises there are no
land values. The products of labor have value, but in the
sparsity of population no value as yet attaches to land
itself. But as increasing density of population and
increasing elaboration of industry necessitate the
organization of the state, with its need for revenues,
value begins to attach to land. As population still
increases and industry grows more elaborate, so the needs
for public revenues increase. And at the same time and
from the same causes land values increase. The connection
is invariable. The value of things produced by labor
tends to decline with social development, since the
larger scale of production and the improvement of
processes tend steadily to reduce their cost. But the
value of land on which population centers goes up and up.
Take Rome or Paris or London or New York or Melbourne.
Consider the enormous value of land in such cities as
compared with the value of land in sparsely settled parts
of the same countries. To what is this due? Is it not due
to the density and activity of the populations of those
cities — to the very causes that require great
public expenditure for streets, drains, public buildings,
and all the many things needed for the health,
convenience and safety of such great cities? See how with
the growth of such cities the one thing that steadily
increases in value is land; how the opening of roads, the
building of railways, the making of any public
improvement, adds to the value of land. Is it not clear
that here is a natural law — that is to say a
tendency willed by the Creator? Can it mean anything else
than that He who ordained the state with its needs has in
the values which attach to land provided the means to
meet those needs?
That it does mean this and nothing else is confirmed
if we look deeper still, and inquire not merely as to the
intent, but as to the purpose of the intent. If we do so
we may see in this natural law by which land values
increase with the growth of society not only such a
perfectly adapted provision for the needs of society as
gratifies our intellectual perceptions by showing us the
wisdom of the Creator, but a purpose with regard to the
individual that gratifies our moral perceptions by
opening to us a glimpse of his beneficence.
Consider: Here is a natural law by which as society
advances the one thing that increases in value is land
— a natural law by virtue of which all growth of
population, all advance of the arts, all general
improvements of whatever kind, add to a fund that both
the commands of justice and the dictates of expediency
prompt us to take for the common uses of society. Now,
since increase in the fund available for the common uses
of society is increase in the gain that goes equally to
each member of society, is it not clear that the law by
which land values increase with social advance while the
value of the products of labor does not increase, tends
with the advance of civilization to make the share that
goes equally to each member of society more and more
important as compared with what goes to him from his
individual earnings, and thus to make the advance of
civilization lessen relatively the differences that in a
ruder social state must exist between the strong and the
weak, the fortunate and the unfortunate? Does it not show
the purpose of the Creator to be that the advance of man
in civilization should be an advance not merely to larger
powers but to a greater and greater equality, instead of
what we, by our ignoring of his intent, are making it, an
advance toward a more and more monstrous inequality?...
read the whole
letter
Henry George: The Wages of
Labor
Consider the taxes on the processes and products
of industry by which public revenue is
collected:–
- The monstrous customs duties that hamper
intercourse between so-called Christian
States;
- the taxes on occupations, on earnings, on
investments;
- on the building of houses;
- on the cultivation of fields;
- on industry and thrift in all
forms.
Can these be the ways that God has
intended that Governments should raise the means they need?
Have any of them the characteristics indispensable in any
plan we can deem a right one?
All these taxes violate the moral
law.
- They take by force what belongs to the
individual;
- they give to the unscrupulous an advantage
over the scrupulous;
- their effect is, nay they are largely
intended, to increase the price of what some have to sell
and others must buy;
- they corrupt governments;
- they make oaths a mockery;
- they shackle commerce;
- they fine industry and thrift;
- they lessen the wealth that men might enjoy,
and
- enrich some by impoverishing
others.
What most strikingly shows how opposed to
Christianity is the existing system of raising public
revenue is its influence on thought.
Christianity teaches us that all men
are brethren; that their true interests are harmonious, not
antagonistic. It gives us, as the golden
rule of life, that we should do to others as we would have
others do to us. But, out of the
system of taxing the products and processes of labor, and
out of its effects in increasing the price of what some
have to sell and others must buy, has grown the theory of
“Protection,” which denies this gospel,
which holds Christ ignorant of political economy, and
proclaims laws for the nation utterly at variance with His
teaching.
This theory sanctifies national hatreds; it
inculcates a universal war of hostile tariffs; it teaches
peoples that their prosperity lies in imposing on the
productions of other peoples restrictions they do not
wish imposed, on their own; and, instead
of the Christian doctrine of man’s brotherhood, it
makes injury of foreigners a civic virtue.
... read
the whole article
Louis Post: Outlines
of Louis F. Post's Lectures, with Illustrative Notes and
Charts (1894)
c. Significance of the Upward Tendency of
Rent
Now, what is the meaning of this tendency of Rent to
rise with social progress, while Wages tend to fall? Is
it not a plain promise that if Rent be treated as common
property, advances in productive power shall be steps in
the direction of realizing through orderly and natural
growth those grand conceptions of both the socialist and
the individualist, which in the present condition of
society are justly ranked as Utopian? Is it not likewise
a plain warning that if Rent be treated as private
property, advances in productive power will be steps in
the direction of making slaves of the many laborers, and
masters of a few land-owners? Does it not mean that
common ownership of Rent is in harmony with natural law,
and that its private appropriation is disorderly and
degrading? When the cause of Rent and the tendency
illustrated in the preceding chart are considered in
connection with the self-evident truth that God made the
earth for common use and not for private monopoly, how
can a contrary inference hold? Caused and increased by
social growth, 97 the benefits of which should be common,
and attaching to land, the just right to which is equal,
Rent must be the natural fund for public expenses. 98
97. Here, far away from civilization, is
a solitary settler. Getting no benefits from
government, he needs no public revenues, and none of
the land about him has any value. Another settler
comes, and another, until a village appears. Some
public revenue is then required. Not much, but some.
And the land has a little value, only a little; perhaps
just enough to equal the need for public revenue. The
village becomes a town. More revenues are needed, and
land values are higher. It becomes a city. The public
revenues required are enormous, and so are the land
values.
98. Society, and society alone, causes
Rent. Rising with the rise, advancing with the growth,
and receding with the decline of society, it measures
the earning power of society as a whole as
distinguished from that of the individuals. Wages, on
the other hand, measure the earning power of the
individuals as distinguished from that of society as a
whole. We have distinguished the parts into which
Wealth is distributed as Wages and Rent; but it would
be correct, indeed it is the same thing, to regard all
wealth as earnings, and to distinguish the two kinds as
Communal Earnings and Individual Earnings. How, then,
can there be any question as to the fund from which
society should be supported? How can it be justly
supported in any other way than out of its own
earnings?
If there be at all such a thing as design in the
universe — and who can doubt it? — then has
it been designed that Rent, the earnings of the
community, shall be retained for the support of the
community, and that Wages, the earnings of the
individual, shall be left to the individual in proportion
to the value of his service. This is the divine law,
whether we trace it through complex moral and economic
relations, or find it in the eighth commandment.
... read the
book
Nic Tideman:
Improving Efficiency and Preventing Exploitation in Taxing
and Spending Decisions
A possible difficulty with classical liberalism as a
justification for government action is that it may
justify little if any government action. Taxes intrude
upon individual liberty. How is this intrusion to be
justified? One way to try to get around this difficulty
is by the claim that some expenditures on protecting
individual rights are so valuable that anyone would
understand that, for these expenditures, the reduction in
individual liberty from taxation is less than the
addition to individual liberty from the protection of
individual rights that is possible with taxation.
However, if improving the well-being of all citizens is
the justification, then one should ask whether there is
adequate justification for even these government actions
if they do not have unanimous support. ...
read the whole article
Nic Tideman:
The Morality of Taxation: The Local Case
There is a gentler side of taxation that provides some
explanation of our tolerance of this coercion. Taxation
can be the way that people achieve their common purposes.
People may agree to be taxed so that there will be money
to pay for public services that they want. From this
perspective, taxation may be considered no more than the
dues for belonging to a club that provides people with
things that they would rather pay their share of than do
without. However, to make this "voluntary exchange"
theory of taxation relevant, people must be able to
choose freely whether or not to "join the club," to be a
citizen of the taxing jurisdiction. With all land claimed
by some taxing jurisdiction, the choice isn't exactly
free.
The problem of morality in taxation is the
following:
- How do we retain the possibility of people pooling
their contributions to the cost of services that they
agree are worthwhile, while eliminating the possibility
of citizens treating their fellow citizens as targets
of plunder?
- What are the limits of obligations that we can
justly impose on our fellow citizens?
- And how do we set up a structure of government that
will ensure that these limits are observed?
The turn-of-the-century Swedish economist, Knut
Wicksell, had ideas that dealt with some of these
questions (Wicksell, 1958 [1896]). Wicksell argued that
if a public expenditure is worthwhile, then there must be
some allocation among citizens of the taxes that are
needed to finance the expenditure that would make
everyone better off. If legislatures were required to
achieve unanimity to pass spending programs, then they
would have to find allocations of taxes that were
unanimously acceptable before they could pass those
programs. In that case, majorities would have no
opportunity to exploit minorities, and inefficient
proposals would be prevented from passing as well.
Wicksell recognized that if complete unanimity were
required, strategic holdouts would be likely to prevent
any program from passing, so he was content to recommend
a rule of "near-unanimity," without being specific about
what this meant.
While Wicksell's insights are interesting, they do not
fully solve the problem of moral taxation, because any
departure from unanimity opens the door to exploitation
of minorities, and the requirement of more-than-majority
approval means that the costs of coalition-building will
leave some worthwhile activities unapproved. Still, we
would probably have a much more efficient public sector
if every public expenditure required two-thirds approval
in legislative bodies.
But to make taxation truly voluntary, the option to
leave must be viable. If people could move costlessly
from one jurisdiction to another, taking all of their
belongings with them, then competition among
jurisdictions would tend to eliminate oppressive
taxation. This would leave only the fees that people were
prepared to pay to have public services (Tiebout, 1956).
...
read the whole article
Weld Carter: An
Introduction to Henry George
The Ethics of Taxation
It was but a short step from the ethics of property to
the ethics of taxation. George's position here was that
as labor and capital rightfully and unconditionally own
what they produce, no one can rightfully appropriate any
of their earnings; nor can the State. On the other hand,
land value is always a socially created value, never the
result of action by the owner of the land. Therefore this
is a value that must be taken by society; otherwise,
those who comprise the social whole are deprived of what
is rightfully theirs. Furthermore, to charge the owner
for this value, in the form of taxation, is only to
collect from him the precise value of the benefit he
receives from society.
As to the justice of taxes on
products, George spoke of "...all taxes now levied on the
products and processes of industry -- which taxes, since
they take from the earnings of labor, we hold to be
infringements of the right of property."
Of the justice of
taxes on land values, he said, "Adam Smith speaks of
incomes as 'enjoyed under the protection of the state'; and
this is the ground upon which the equal taxation of all
species of property is commonly insisted upon -- that it is
equally protected by the state. The basis of this idea is
evidently that the enjoyment of property is made possible
by the state -- that there is a value created and
maintained by the community, which is justly called upon to
meet community expenses. Now of what values is this true?
Only of the value of land. This is a value that does not
arise until a community is formed, and that, unlike other
values, grows with the growth of the community. It exists
only as the community exists. Scatter again the largest
community, and land, now so valuable, would have no value
at all. With every increase of population the value of land
rises; with every decrease it falls. ...
"The tax upon land values is,
therefore, the most just and equal of all taxes. It falls
only upon those who receive from society a peculiar and
valuable benefit, and upon them in proportion to the
benefit they receive. It is the taking by the community,
for the use of the community, that value which is the
creation of the community. It is the application the common
property to common uses." ...read the
whole article
|
To share this page with a friend:
right click, choose "send," and add your
comments.
|
|
Red links have not been
visited; .
Green links are pages you've seen
|
Essential Documents pertinent
to this theme:
|
|