Many things we depend on ultimately come from the
earth. Land Value Taxation can lower the prices of those
items, both by its own action, and by replacing sales
taxes and other taxes which raise prices.
Rev. A. C. Auchmuty: Gems from George, a themed
collection of excerpts from the writings of Henry
George (with links to sources)
THE mode of taxation is quite as important as the
amount. As a small burden badly placed may distress a
horse that could carry with ease a much larger one
properly adjusted, so a people may be impoverished and
their power of producing wealth destroyed by taxation,
which, if levied in another way, could be borne with
ease. —
Progress & Poverty
— Book VIII, Chapter 3, Application of the Remedy:
The Proposition Tried by the Canons of Taxation
IF we impose a tax upon buildings, the users of
buildings must finally pay it, for the erection of
buildings will cease until building rents become high
enough to pay the regular profit and the tax besides. If
we impose a tax upon manufactures or imported goods, the
manufacturer or importer will charge it in a higher price
to the jobber, the jobber to the retailer, and the
retailer to the consumer. Now, the consumer, on whom the
tax thus ultimately falls, must not only pay the amount
of the tax, but also a profit on this amount to everyone
who has thus advanced it — for profit on the
capital he has advanced in paying taxes is as much
required by each dealer as profit on the capital he has
advanced in paying for goods. —
Progress & Poverty
— Book VIII, Chapter 3, Application of the Remedy:
The Proposition Tried by the Canons of Taxation
THE way taxes raise prices is by increasing the cost of
production, and checking supply. But land is not a thing
of human production, and taxes upon rent cannot check
supply. Therefore though a tax on rent compels the
landowners to pay more, it gives them no power to obtain
more for the use of their land, as it in no way tends to
reduce the supply of land. On the contrary, by compelling
those who hold land on speculation to sell or let for
what they can get, a tax on land values tends to increase
the competition between owners, and thus to reduce the
price of land. —
Progress & Poverty
— Book VIII, Chapter 3, Application of the Remedy:
The Proposition Tried by the Canons of Taxation
... go to "Gems from
George"
Louis Post: Outlines
of Louis F. Post's Lectures, with Illustrative Notes and
Charts (1894) — Appendix: FAQ
Q11. How can mines be taxed without increasing the
price of the out-put?
A. By taxing the royalty, or, what is essentially the
same, by taxing their capitalized value as mining
opportunities. This would tend to lower rather than
increase the price of the product. Read note 11.
Note 11: This is usually a stumbling
block to those who, without much experience in economic
thought, consider the single tax for the first time. As
soon as they grasp the idea that taxes upon commodities
shift to consumers they jump to the conclusion that
similarly taxes upon land values would shift to the
users. But this is a mistake, and the explanation is
simple. Taxes upon what men produce make production
more difficult and so tend toward scarcity in the
supply, which stimulates prices; but taxes upon land,
provided the taxes be levied in proportion to value,
tend toward plenty in supply (meaning market supply of
course), because they make it more difficult to hold
valuable land idle, and so depress prices.
"A tax on rent falls wholly on the
landlord. There are no means by which he can shift the
burden upon anyone else. . . A tax on rent, therefore,
has no effect other than its obvious one. It merely
takes so much from the landlord and transfers it to the
state." — John Stuart Mill's Prin. of Pol.
Ec., book v, ch. iii, sec. 1.
"A tax laid upon rent is borne solely by
the owner of land." — Bascom's Tr.,
p.159.
"Taxes which are levied on land . . .
really fall on the owner of the land." — Mrs.
Fawcett's Pol. Ec. for Beginners, pp.209, 210.
"A land tax levied in proportion to the
rent of land, and varying with every variation of
rents, . . . will fall wholly on the landlords."
— Walker's Pol. Ec., ed. of 1887, p. 413,
quoting Ricardo.
"The power of transferring a tax from the
person who actually pays it to some other person varies
with the object taxed. A tax on rents cannot be
transferred. A tax on commodities is always transferred
to the consumer." — Thorold Rogers's Pol.
Ec., ch. xxi, 2d ed., p. 285.
"Though the landlord is in all cases the
real contributor, the tax is commonly advanced by the
tenant, to whom the landlord is obliged to allow it in
payment of the rent." — Adam Smith's Wealth
of Nations, book v, ch. ii, part ii, art. i.
"The way taxes raise prices is by
increasing the cost of production and checking supply.
But land is not a thing of human production, and taxes
upon rent cannot check supply. Therefore, though a tax
upon rent compels land-owners to pay more, it gives
them no power to obtain more for the use of their land,
as it in no way tends to reduce the supply of land. On
the contrary, by compelling those who hold land on
speculation to sell or let for what they can get, a tax
on land values tends to increase the competition
between owners, and thus to reduce the price of land."
— Progress and Poverty, book viii, ch. iii,
subd. i.
Sometimes this point is raised as a
question of shifting the tax in higher rent to the
tenant, and at others as a question of shifting it to
the consumers of goods in higher prices. The principle
is the same. Merchants cannot charge higher prices for
goods than their competitors do, merely because they
pay higher ground rents. A country storekeeper whose
business lot is worth but few dollars charges as much
for sugar, probably more, than a city grocer whose lot
is worth thousands. Quality for quality and quantity
for quantity, goods sell for about the same price
everywhere. Differences in price are altogether in
favor of places where land has a high value. This is
due to the fact that the cost of getting goods to
places of low land value, distant villages for example,
is greater than to centers, which are places of high
land value. Sometimes it is true that prices for some
things are higher where land values are high. Tiffany's
goods, for instance, may be more expensive than goods
of the same quality at a store on a less expensive
site. But that is not due to the higher land value; it
is because the dealer has a reputation for technical
knowledge and honesty (or has become a fad among rich
people), for which his customers are willing to pay
whether his store is on a high priced-lot or a
low-priced one.
Though land value has no effect upon the
price of good, it is easier to sell goods in some
locations than in others. Therefore, though the price
and the profit of each sale be the same, or even less,
in good locations than in poorer ones, aggregate
receipts and aggregate profits are much greater at the
good location. And it is out of his aggregate, and not
out of each profit, that rent is paid, For example: A
cigar store on a thoroughfare supplies a certain
quality of cigar for fifteen cents. On a side street
the same quality of cigar can be bought no cheaper.
Indeed, the cigars there are likely to be poorer, and
therefore really dearer. Yet ground rent on the
thoroughfare is very high compared with ground rent on
the sidestreet. How, then, can the first dealer, he who
pays the high ground rent, afford to sell as good or
better cigars for fifteen cents than his competitor of
the low priced location? Simply because he is able to
make so many more sales with a given outlay of labor
and capital in a given time that his aggregate profit
is greater. This is due to the advantage of his
location, and for that advantage he pays a premium in
higher ground rent. But that premium is not charged to
smokers; the competing dealer of the side street
protects them. It represents the greater ease, the
lower cost, of doing a given volume of business upon
the site for which it is paid; add if the state should
take any of it, even the whole of it, in taxation, the
loss would be finally borne by the owner of the
advantage which attaches to that site — by the
landlord. Any attempt to shift it to tenant or buyer
would be promptly checked by the competition of
neighboring but cheaper land.
"A land-tax, levied in proportion to the
rent of land, and varying with every variation of rent,
is in effect a tax on rent; and as such a tax will not
apply to that land which yields no rent, nor to the
produce of that capital which is employed on the land
with a view to profit merely, and which never pays
rent; it will not in any way affect the price of raw
produce, but will fall wholly on the landlords."
— McCulloch's Ricardo (3d ed.), p. 207
...
Q31. Will not the capitalist be able under the
single tax to undersell the laborer — to sell
goods for less than cost, at least temporarily —
and thereby force him to accept the capitalist's
terms?
A. With capitalists continually hunting for men to help
them fill their orders, and bidding against each other
to get men, as would be the case under the single tax,
such a contingency would be in the highest degree
improbable. It is practically impossible. Nothing short
of a trust, an absolutely perfect trust, of all the
owners of capital the world over could produce it. And
even then, plenty of very useful land of all kinds
being free and labor products being exempt from
taxation, all people who were outside of the trust
would resort co-operatively to the land, and the trust
would be obliged to take them in as the alternative of
falling to pieces under their competition. ... read the book
Charles B. Fillebrown: A Catechism of Natural
Taxation, from Principles of Natural Taxation
(1917)
Q19. Why should buildings and all other
improvements and personal property and capital be exempt
from taxes?
A. Because a tax on them falls upon industry, and so
increases the cost of living, while continuing the
invidious exemption of the present net land value.
Q22. What is privilege?
A. Strictly defined, privilege is, according to the
Century Dictionary, "a special and exclusive power
conferred by law on particular persons or classes of
persons and ordinarily in derogation of the common
right."
Q23. What is today the popular conception of
privilege?
A. That it is the law-given power of one man to profit at
another man's expense.
Q24. What are the principal forms of
privilege?
A. The appropriation by individuals, or by public service
corporations, of the net rent of land created by the
growth and activity of the community without payment for
the same. Also, the less important privileges connected
with patents, tariff, and the currency.
Q25. Where in does privilege differ from
capital?
A. Capital is a material thing, a product of labor,
stored-up wages; an instrument of production paid for in
human labor, and destined to wear out. Capital is the
natural ally of labor, and is harmless except as allied
to privilege. Privilege is none of these, but is
an intangible statutory power, an unpaid-for and
perpetual lien upon the future labor of this and
succeeding generations. Capital is paid for and
ephemeral. Privilege is unpaid for and
eternal. A man accumulated in his profession
$5,000 capital, which he invested in land in Canada. Ten
years later he sold the same land for $200,000. Here is
an instance of $5,000 capital allied with $195,000
privilege. This illustrates that privilege and not
capital is the real enemy of labor.
Q26. How may franchises be treated?
A. Franchise privileges may be abated, or gradually
abolished by lower rates, or by taxation, or by both, in
the interest of the community.
Q27. Why should privilege be especially
taxed?
A. Because such payment is fairly due from
grantee to the grantor of privilege and also because a
tax upon privilege can never be a burden upon industry or
commerce, nor can it ever operate to reduce the wages of
labor or increase prices to the consumer.
Q28. How are landlords privileged?
A. Because, in so far as their land tax is an "old" tax,
it is a burdenless tax, and because their buildings' tax
is shifted upon their tenants; most landlords who let
land and also the tenement houses and business blocks
thereon avoid all share in the tax burden.
Q29. How does privilege affect the distribution of
wealth?
A. Wealth as produced is now distributed substantially in
but two channels, privilege and wages. The abolition of
privilege would leave but the one proper channel, viz.,
wages of capital, hand, and brain.
Q30. How would the single tax increase
wages?
A. By gradually transferring to wages that portion of the
current wealth that now flows to privilege. In other
words, it would widen and deepen the channel of wages by
enlarging opportunities for labor, and by increasing the
purchasing power of nominal wages through reduction of
prices. On the other hand it would narrow the channel of
privilege by making the man who has a privilege pay for
it.
Q31. How can this transfer be effected?
A. By the taxation of privilege.
Q32. How much ultimately may wages be thus
increased?
A. Fifty percent would be a low estimate.
Q33. What are fair prices and fair
wages?
A. Prices unenhanced by privilege, and wages undiminished
by taxation.
Q34. Why does not an increase in ground rent tend
to cause an increase in prices?
A. Usually sales increase faster proportionately than
rent, thus reducing the ratio of rent to sales. The
larger the product, the lower the individual costs. The
larger the gross sales, the lower the competitive
prices.
... read
the whole article
Jeff Smith: What
the Left Must Do: Share the Surplus
Increasing taxes, fees, or dues upon land,
resources, and privileges won’t force firms to
raise prices; the ones who try to will lose customers to
those who don’t; in the end, all will have to
settle for smaller profits. On the other hand, de-taxing
labor and capital, by lowering overhead, lets firms lower
the price of their products, while competition drives
them to. The resultant lower cost of living –
coupled with higher wages and the social salary –
lets those with enough stuff work less, so those without
enough stuff can work more.
Read the whole
article
Winston Churchill: Land Prices as a Cause of
Poverty
The immemorial custom of nearly every modern State,
the mature conclusions of many of the greatest thinkers,
have placed the tenure, transfer, and obligations of land
in a wholly different category from other classes of
property. The mere obvious physical distinction between
land, which is a vital necessity of every human being and
which at the same time is strictly limited in extent, and
other property is in itself sufficient to justify a clear
differentiation in its treatment, and in the view taken
by the State of the conditions which should govern the
tenure of land from that which should regulate traffic in
other forms of property. ... read the whole
speech
|
To share this page with a friend:
right click, choose "send," and add your
comments.
|
|
Red links have not been
visited; .
Green links are pages you've seen
|
Essential Documents pertinent
to this theme:
essential_documents
|
|