Equity in Taxation
Henry George: The
Common Sense of Taxation (1881 article)
Evidently this regard for the general good is the true
principle of taxation. The more it is examined the more
clearly it will be seen that there is no valid reason why
we should, in any case, attempt to tax all property. That
equality should be the rule and aim of taxation is true,
and this for the reason given in the Declaration of
Independence, that all men are created equal. But
equality does not require that all men should be taxed
alike, or that all things should be taxed alike. It
merely requires that whatever taxes are imposed shall be
equally imposed upon the persons or things in like
conditions or situations; it merely requires that no
citizen shall be given an advantage, or put at a
disadvantage, as compared with other citizens.
The true purposes of government are well stated in the
preamble to the Constitution of the United States, as
they are in the Declaration of Independence. To insure
the general peace, to promote the general welfare, to
secure to each individual the inalienable rights to life,
liberty, and the pursuit of happiness — these are
the proper ends of government, and are therefore the ends
which in every scheme of taxation should be kept in mind.
...
To consider the nature of property of this kind is
again to see a clear distinction. That distinction is
not, as the lawyers have it, between movables and
immovables, between personal property and real estate.
The true distinction is between property which is, and
property which is not, the result of human labor; or, to
use the terms of political economy, between land and
wealth. For, in any precise use of the term, land is not
wealth, any more than labor is wealth. Land and labor are
the factors of production. Wealth is such result of their
union as retains the capacity of ministering to human
desire. A lot and the house which stands upon it are
alike property, alike have a tangible value, and are
alike classed as real estate. But there are between them
the most essential differences. The one is the free gift
of Nature, the other the result of human exertion; the
one exists from generation to generation, while men come
and go; the other is constantly tending to decay, and can
only be preserved by continual exertion. To the one, the
right of exclusive possession, which makes it individual
property, can, like the right of property in slaves, be
traced to nothing but municipal law; to the other, the
right of exclusive property springs clearly from those
natural relations which are among the primary perceptions
of the human mind. Nor are these mere abstract
distinctions. They are distinctions of the first
importance in determining what should and what should not
be taxed.
For, keeping in mind the fact that all wealth is the
result of human exertion, it is clearly seen that, having
in view the promotion of the general prosperity, it is
the height of absurdity to tax wealth for purposes of
revenue while there remains, unexhausted by taxation, any
value attaching to land. We may tax land values as much
as we please, without in the slightest degree lessening
the amount of land, or the capabilities of land, or the
inducement to use land. But we cannot tax wealth without
lessening the inducement to the production of wealth, and
decreasing the amount of wealth. We might take the whole
value of land in taxation, so as to make the ownership of
land worth nothing, and the land would still remain, and
be as useful as before. The effect would be to throw land
open to users free of price, and thus to increase its
capabilities, which are brought out by increased
population. But impose anything like such taxation upon
wealth, and the inducement to the production of wealth
would be gone. Movable wealth would be hidden or carried
off, immovable wealth would be suffered to go to decay,
and where was prosperity would soon be the silence of
desolation.
And the reason of this difference is clear. The
possession of wealth is the inducement to the exertion
necessary to the production and maintenance of wealth.
Men do not work for the pleasure of working, but to get
the things their work will give them. And to tax the
things that are produced by exertion is to lessen the
inducement to exertion. But over and above the benefit to
the possessor, which is the stimulating motive to the
production of wealth, there is a benefit to the
community, for no matter how selfish he may be, it is
utterly impossible for any one to entirely keep to
himself the benefit of any desirable thing he may
possess. These diffused benefits when localized give
value to land, and this may be taxed without in any wise
diminishing the incentive to production.
To illustrate: A man builds a fine house or large
factory in a poorly improved neighborhood. To tax this
building and its adjuncts is to make him pay for his
enterprise and expenditure — to take from him part
of his natural reward. But the improvement thus made has
given new beauty or life to the neighborhood, making it a
more desirable place than before for the erection of
other houses or factories, and additional value is given
to land all about. Now to tax improvements is not only to
deprive of his proper reward the man who has made the
improvement, but it is to deter others from making
similar improvements. But, instead of taxing
improvements, to tax these land values is to leave the
natural inducement to further improvement in full force,
and at the same time to keep down an obstacle to further
improvement, which, under the present system, improvement
itself tends to raise. For the advance of land values
which follows improvement, and even the expectation of
improvement, makes further improvement more costly.
See how unjust and short-sighted is this system. Here
is a man who, gathering what little capital he can, and
taking his family, starts West to find a place where he
can make himself a home. He must travel long distances;
for, though he will pass plenty of land nobody is using,
it is held at prices too high for him. Finally he will go
no further, and selects a place where, since the creation
of the world, the soil, so far as we know, has never felt
a plowshare. But here, too, in nine cases out of ten, he
will find the speculator has been ahead of him, for the
speculator moves quicker, and has superior means of
information to the emigrant. Before he can put this land
to the use for which nature intended it, and to which it
is for the general good that it should be put, he must
make terms with some man who in all probability never saw
the land, and never dreamed of using it, and who, it may
be, resides in some city, thousands of miles away. In
order to get permission to use this land, he must give up
a large part of the little capital which is seed-wheat to
him, and perhaps in addition mortgage his future labor
for years. Still he goes to work: he works himself, and
his wife works, and his children work — work like
horses, and live in the hardest and dreariest manner.
Such a man deserves encouragement, not discouragement;
but on him taxation falls with peculiar severity. Almost
everything that he has to buy — groceries,
clothing, tools — is largely raised in price by a
system of tariff taxation which cannot add to the price
of the grain or hogs or cattle that he has to sell. And
when the assessor comes around he is taxed on the
improvements he has made, although these improvements
have added not only to the value of surrounding land, but
even to the value of land in distant commercial centers.
Not merely this, but, as a general rule, his land,
irrespective of the improvements, will be assessed at a
higher rate than unimproved land around it, on the ground
that "productive property" ought to pay more than
"unproductive property" — a principle just the
reverse of the correct one, for the man who makes land
productive adds to the general prosperity, while the man
who keeps land unproductive stands in the way of the
general prosperity, is but a dog-in-the-manger, who
prevents others from using what he will not use
himself.
Or, take the case of the railroads. That railroads are
a public benefit no one will dispute. We want more
railroads, and want them to reduce their fares and
freight. Why then should we tax them? for taxes upon
railroads deter from railroad building, and compel higher
charges. Instead of taxing the railroads, is it not clear
that we should rather tax the increased value which they
give to land? To tax railroads is to check railroad
building, to reduce profits, and compel higher rates; to
tax the value they give to land is to increase railroad
business and permit lower rates. The elevated railroads,
for instance, have opened to the overcrowded population
of New York the wide, vacant spaces of the upper part of
the island. But this great public benefit is neutralized
by the rise in land values. Because these vacant lots can
be reached more cheaply and quickly, their owners demand
more for them, and so the public gain in one way is
offset in another, while the roads lose the business they
would get were not building checked by the high prices
demanded for lots. The increase of land values, which the
elevated roads have caused, is not merely no advantage to
them — it is an injury; and it is clearly a public
injury. The elevated railroads ought not to be taxed. The
more profit they make, with the better conscience can
they be asked to still further reduce fares. It is the
increased land values which they have created that ought
to be taxed, for taxing them will give the public the
full benefit of cheap fares.
So with railroads everywhere. And so not alone with
railroads, but with all industrial enterprises. So long
as we consider that community most prosperous which
increases most rapidly in wealth, so long is it the
height of absurdity for us to tax wealth in any of its
beneficial forms. We should tax what we want to repress,
not what we want to encourage. We should tax that which
results from the general prosperity, not that which
conduces to it. It is the increase of population, the
extension of cultivation, the manufacture of goods, the
building of houses and ships and railroads, the
accumulation of capital, and the growth of commerce that
add to the value of land — not the increase in the
value of land that induces the increase of population and
increase of wealth. It is not that the land of Manhattan
Island is now worth hundreds of millions where, in the
time of the early Dutch settlers, it was only worth
dollars, that there are on it now so many more people,
and so much more wealth. It is because of the increase of
population and the increase of wealth that the value of
the land has so much increased. Increase of land values
tends of itself to repel population and prevent
improvement. And thus the taxation of land values, unlike
taxation of other property, does not tend to prevent the
increase of wealth, but rather to stimulate it. It is the
taking of the golden egg, not the choking of the goose
that lays it.
Every consideration of policy and ethics squares with
this conclusion. The tax upon land values is the most
economically perfect of all taxes. It does not raise
prices; it maybe collected at least cost, and with the
utmost ease and certainty; it leaves in full strength all
the springs of production; and, above all, it consorts
with the truest equality and the highest justice. For, to
take for the common purposes of the community that value
which results from the growth of the community, and to
free industry and enterprise and thrift from burden and
restraint, is to leave to each that which he fairly
earns, and to assert the first and most comprehensive of
equal rights — the equal right of all to the land
on which, and from which, all must live.
Thus it is that the scheme of taxation which conduces
to the greatest production is also that which conduces to
the fairest distribution, and that in the proper
adjustment of taxation lies not merely the possibility of
enormously increasing the general wealth, but the
solution of these pressing social and political problems
which spring from unnatural inequality in the
distribution of wealth.
"There is," says M. de Laveleye, in concluding that
work in which he shows that the first perceptions of
mankind have everywhere recognized a most vital
distinction between property in land and property which
results from labor, — "there is in human affairs
one system which is the best; it is not that system which
always exists, otherwise why should we desire to change
it; but it is that system which should exist for the
greatest good of humanity. God knows it, and wills it;
man's duty it is to discover and establish it." ...
read the whole
article
Louis Post: Outlines
of Louis F. Post's Lectures, with Illustrative Notes and
Charts (1894)
4. CONFORMITY TO GENERAL PRINCIPLES OF
TAXATION
The single tax conforms most closely to the essential
principles of Adam Smith's four classical maxims, which
are stated best by Henry George 19 as follows:
The best tax by which public revenues can be raised is
evidently that which will closest conform to the
following conditions:
- That it bear as lightly as possible upon production
— so as least to check the increase of the
general fund from which taxes must be paid and the
community maintained. 20
- That it be easily and cheaply collected, and fall
as directly as may be upon the ultimate payers —
so as to take from the people as little as possible in
addition to what it yields the government. 21
- That it be certain — so as to give the least
opportunity for tyranny or corruption on the part of
officials, and the least temptation to law-breaking and
evasion on the part of the tax-payers. 22
- That it bear equally — so as to give no
citizen an advantage or put any at a disadvantage, as
compared with others. 23
19. "Progress and Poverty," book viii.
ch.iii.
20. This is the second part of Adam
Smith's fourth maxim. He states it as follows: "Every
tax ought to be so contrived as both to take out and to
keep out of the pockets of the people as little as
possible over and above what it brings into the public
treasury of the state. A tax may either take out or
keep out of the pockets of the people a great deal more
than it brings into the public treasury in the four
following ways: . . . Secondly, it may obstruct the
industry of the people, and discourage them from
applying to certain branches of business which might
give maintenance and employment to great multitudes.
While it obliges the people to pay, it may thus
diminish or perhaps destroy some of the funds which
might enable them more easily to do so."
21. This is the first part of Adam
Smith's fourth maxim, in which he condemns a tax that
takes out of the pockets of the people more than it
brings into the public treasury.
22. This is Adam Smith's second maxim. He
states it as follows: "The tax which each individual is
bound to pay ought to be certain and not arbitrary. The
time of payment, the manner of payment, the quantity to
be paid, ought all to be clear and plain to the
contributor and to every other person. Where it is
otherwise, every person subject to the tax is put more
or less in the power of the tax gatherer."
23. This is Adam Smith's first maxim. He
states it as follows: "The subjects of every state
ought to contribute towards the support of the
government as nearly as possible in proportion to their
respective abilities, that is to say, in proportion to
the revenue which they respectively enjoy under the
protection of the state. The expense of government to
the individuals of a great nation is like the expense
of management to the joint tenants of a great estate,
who are all obliged to contribute in proportion to
their respective interests in the estate. In the
observation or neglect of this maxim consists what is
called the equality or inequality of taxation."
In changing this Mr. George says
("Progress and Poverty," book viii, ch. iii, subd.
4): "Adam Smith speaks of incomes as enjoyed
'under the protection of the state'; and this is the
ground upon which the equal taxation of all species of
property is commonly insisted upon — that it is
equally protected by the state. The basis of this idea
is evidently that the enjoyment of property is made
possible by the state — that there is a value
created and maintained by the community; which is
justly called upon to meet community expenses. Now, of
what values is this true? Only of the value of land.
This is a value that does not arise until a community
is formed, and that, unlike other values, grows with
the growth of the community. It only exists as the
community exists. Scatter again the largest community,
and land, now so valuable, would have no value at all.
With every increase of population the value of land
rises; with every decrease it falls. This is true of
nothing else save of things which, like the ownership
of land, are in their nature monopolies."
Adam Smith's third maxim refers only to
conveniency of payment, and gives countenance to
indirect taxation, which is in conflict with the
principle of his fourth maxim. Mr. George properly
excludes it. ...
c. Certainty
No other tax, direct or indirect, conforms so closely
to the third maxim. "Land lies out of doors." It cannot
be hidden; it cannot be "accidentally" overlooked. Nor
can its value be seriously misstated. Neither
under-appraisement nor over-appraisement to any important
degree is possible without the connivance of the whole
community. 27 The land values of a neighborhood are
matters of common knowledge. Any intelligent resident can
justly appraise them, and every other intelligent
resident can fairly test the appraisement. Therefore, the
tyranny, corruption, fraud, favoritism, and evasions that
are so common in connection with the taxation of imports,
manufactures, incomes, personal property, and buildings
— the values of which, even when the object itself
cannot be hidden, are so distinctly matters of minute
special knowledge that only experts can fairly appraise
them — would be out of the question if the single
tax were substituted for existing fiscal methods. 28
...
d. Equality
In respect of the fourth maxim the single tax bears
more equally— that is to say, more justly —
than any other tax. It is the only tax that falls upon
the taxpayer in proportion to the pecuniary benefits he
receives from the public; 29 and its tendency,
accelerating with the increase of the tax, is to leave
every one the full fruit of his own productive enterprise
and effort. 30
29 The benefits of government are not the
only public benefits whose value attaches exclusively
to land. Communal development from whatever cause
produces the same effect. But as it is under the
protection of government that land-owners are able to
maintain ownership of land and through that to enjoy
the pecuniary benefits of advancing social conditions,
government confers upon them as a class not only the
pecuniary benefits of good government but also the
pecuniary benefits of progress in general.
30. "Here are two men of equal incomes
— that of the one derived from the exertion of
his labor, that of the other from the rent of land. Is
it just that they should equally contribute to the
expenses of the state? Evidently not. The income of the
one represents wealth he creates and adds to the
general wealth of the state; the income of the other
represents merely wealth that he takes from the general
stock, returning nothing." — Progress and
Poverty, book viii, ch. iii, subd. 4.
... read the
book
Bill Batt: Painless
Taxation
Abstract Real tax reform could
do away with those taxes that are resented by the large
proportion of our population. We could replace all taxes
on wages and on interest by instead taxing economic rent.
Rent is windfall income; it is income that arises not
from the efforts of any person or corporation; it comes
about as a surplus gain from common social enterprise.
There is ample moral warrant for society to lay claim to
that which it has created, as well as to that which no
individual or party has earned. Analysis increasingly
makes clear that economic rent in all its forms is far
larger than official government figures indicate; in fact
it is likely sufficient to supplant all current taxes on
labor and capital (wages and interest) which are
acknowledged to have so many negative effects. Recovering
economic rent in all its manifestations by taxing its
various bases actually can foster economic performance
and yield other benefits that make it the natural source
of revenue for governments. Such a tax is essentially
painless. ...
Tax Principles
The starting points should be the lessons that have
been learned over the course of the past three hundred
and more years about what is a good tax. Most basic
textbooks in public finance enumerate them in very clear
form, and they constitute benchmarks against which to
measure the soundness of any particular tax. They are
listed as few as three or as many as eight such
principles but little disagreement exists as to their
substance, regardless of ideology or government. Most
commonly enumerated are neutrality, efficiency, equity,
administrability, simplicity, stability,
sufficiency.[3] Tax theorists
typically measure revenue structures according to any or
all of these criteria: ...
The principle of equity is central to
any discussion of tax design. Tax design requires concern
with both what is fair and the extent to which it must
sometimes be compromised to satisfy the other principal
criteria. Fairness can be evaluated according to what is
termed "horizontal equity" -- the extent to which those
in similar circumstances will pay similar tax burdens,
and "vertical equity" -- how well those in different
classes bear different burdens in the tax structure. It
is this latter perspective that leads to the use of terms
like "proportional," "progressive," and "regressive" in
referring to tax structures. A tax is progressive with
respect to income if the ratio of tax revenue to income
rises when moving up the income scale, proportional if
the ratio is constant, and regressive if the ratio
declines. There is an ancillary question of whether
taxing to reach greater equity should employ measures of
income or of wealth, difficult as this is to measure.
Such questions of equity are a matter particularly
central when discussing the property tax. ... read the whole
article
Bill Batt: Comment on Parts of the
NYS Legislative Tax Study Commission's 1985 study
“Who Pays New York Taxes?”
... This last caveat suggests what is likely the most
critical failing of the Report. The use of an income
snapshot as the basis for measuring the effective tax
burden on owners of real property reflects a
misunderstanding of how tax equity should be construed.
The value of property titles is a measure of wealth, and
is likely to have little if any bearing on any momentary
snapshot of income in a household. This confusion lies at
the very core of difficulties in assessing the fairness
of the property tax. Several studies of tax equity
involving the real property tax fail to recognize that
they are using income as a benchmark for analysis, even
while the tax is upon wealth. ... read the whole
commentary
Bill Batt: How Our Towns
Got That Way (1996 speech)
There were many arguments to be made
for the classical tradition, the result of which would be
to rely upon payment of rent of land according to its value
to society. George recognized that land value is largely a
function of how society has elected to invest in any
general neighborhood; there is no argument for any one
titleholder to reap the reward of what others have
invested. Gaffney points out that, from the standpoint of
economic theory, the framework had the following
virtues:
- It reconciled common land rights with private
tenure, free markets and modern capitalism, a growing and
persistent problem as the industrial society took
hold.
- It enabled the lowering of taxes on labor
without raising taxes on capital.
- It reconciled equity and
efficiency. It constituted a progressive tax because land
is concentrated so much among the wealthy and because the
tax cannot be shifted. It was efficient because it
is neutral among different land-use options.
- It constituted no disincentive to business
location or population settlement. In this way it
encouraged the most efficient land use and discouraged
sprawl.
- It created jobs without inflation, and raised
government revenue without any penalty upon its
base.
- It strengthened public revenues and at the
same time promotes economy in government.
Those economists who today still
persistently hold to the view that there is something
special about land that make it unwise to treat as a form
of capital are known as Georgists. They represent a small
minority of the economics profession, but, little known as
they are, they are among its most esteemed members.
...
The principle of equity is
central to any discussion of tax design. Tax design
requires concern with both what is fair and the extent to
which it must sometimes be compromised to satisfy the other
principal criteria. Fairness can be evaluated according to
what is termed "horizontal equity" the extent to which
those in similar circumstances will pay similar tax
burdens, and "vertical equity" how well those in different
classes bear different burdens in the tax structure. It is
this latter perspective that leads to the use of terms like
"proportional," "progressive," and "regressive" in
referring to tax structures. A tax is progressive with
respect to income if the ratio of tax revenue to income
rises when moving up the income scale, proportional if the
ratio is constant, and regressive if the ratio declines.
There is an ancillary question of whether taxing to reach
greater equity should employ measures of income or of
wealth, difficult as this is to measure. Such questions of
equity are a matter particularly central when discussing
the property tax. This is because people capitalize their
income in the course of a lifetime frequently in property.
Although claims are often made to the contrary and really
comprehensive studies have yet to be done, available
studies suggest that the property tax is really highly
progressive, especially for the land component.... read the whole
article
Bill Batt: Who Says Cities
are Poor? They Just Don't Know How to Tax Their
Wealth!
The Perfect Tax
In the final analysis, a tax should be evaluated
according to the tenets of sound tax theory that have
evolved over the course of recent centuries, and much of
what has been said above is recaptured by a review of
those principles. These measures of what is a "good" tax
or a "bad" tax are often listed differently in textbooks,
but they are largely agreed upon. Failure to conform to
these venerable benchmarks is by itself sufficient cause
to explain an economy's faltering — a particularly
noteworthy example today is the city of Philadelphia
which appears to have done everything backward! It taxes
income, sales, building capital and even business
privilege, the result being that its fisc is
destitute.[20] The
principles by which to measure tax design are enumerated
here so as to make quite clear how recapturing economic
rent in the form of taxes — in all the several
forms where 'land' can be identified — constitutes
the best method of financing government services and the
most advantageous to cities.[21]
The first measure of a good tax is its neutrality. A
neutral tax in no way alters the behavior of its partners
from what would transpire were there no tax at all. A
simple example illustrates the case: today many consumers
will travel to alternate jurisdictions to avoid paying a
sales tax on particular items, be they food, medication,
clothing, or whatever. Taxes fully absorbed
("capitalized") in a market price such as land taxes in
no way distort behavior, the volume of transactions, or
gross prices. They are neutral.
A tax should also be efficient. To be sure, efficiency
has many meanings even in economics. But here, rather
than speaking of the administrative efficiency of its
collection as will be addressed below, the measure is
whether and how much it constitutes an excess burden on
the economy, thereby slowing down performance and market
vitality. Many taxes, as was mentioned earlier, exert so
much drag on market transactions that they are
destructive, however much revenue is brought to
government coffers. Because land has a fixed supply there
is no excess burden at all.
People are frequently most concerned about the
fairness of a tax, which is typically measured according
to both horizontal and vertical equity. Horizontal equity
means that those in similar circumstances will bear
similar burdens. Vertical equity prescribes that those
with greater resources will pay more. Although studies
have yet to show this, land taxes are likely the most
"progressive" of any levy, as tenants bear no
passed-through burden at all.[22] Not only does
no household or office tenant bear any tax burden,
locational sites distant from the urban core, mostly
homeowners and farmers, typically find their burden
reduced. Vacant or underused lots in high value areas
pick up the difference, employing a design that employs
an alternate criterion of equity: taxing according to
use. "Paying for what you take and not for what you make"
encourages efficient consumption of space and resources
in an automatic and non-coercive manner. The one-third of
households that own no land are relieved of all taxes,
and residential and non-residential property owners split
the rest. Farmers, whose land is typically of
inconsequential value relative to sites in urban areas,
are likely to pay little if anything even if they are not
already protected by other save-harmless provisions. By
eliminating taxes on building improvements they typically
enjoy savings just as do other businesses.
All this makes for a far simpler and more
comprehensible system of taxation. Land taxes are totally
transparent, impossible to evade, and therefore much more
administrable. This further engenders the legitimacy of
taxation and of government itself. What it also does is
assure stability to the tax system, for the reason that
land values are not subject to the variations and
vacillations that other tax bases frequently have.
Indeed, the removal of economic rent from locational
sites discourages speculative bubbles and the related
economic cycles that are associated with them. This
greater stability and reliability is to the advantage of
every sector of the economy — private, public, and
non-profit.
A tax that collects economic rent offers a win-win
proposition to every sector of the community —
except to those who speculate in land. But who wants to
favor land speculators? They are not held in high regard
anywhere; their destructive behavior is the bane of
cities, recognized everywhere for what it is: parasitic
and passive. Speculators provide no added value to a
community's well-being, and taxing rent is a foolproof
means by which to eliminate it. Land speculation is
highest where the most rent can be privately captured,
but it forces those who choose to develop to look to
sub-optimal locations when the primary locations they
hoped for are held off the market for opportunistic gain.
By collecting rent, primary choice locations become
available for use and to facilitate the development of
land use configurations ideal for the economic health and
efficient allocation. Urban ambience is improved, public
sector service costs are reduced, and sprawl development
is stemmed. ... read the
whole article
Frank Stilwell and Kirrily Jordan: The Political Economy of Land:
Putting Henry George in His Place
One might expect such arguments to have led to the
advocacy of land nationalisation. But George thought this
unnecessary because a tax on land could be effective in
capturing the economic surplus arising from land
ownership. This tax would generate all the revenue
necessary to fund public expenditures. George thought
that such a land tax would permit the removal of other
taxes on labour and capital, which he regarded as
inherently inefficient. He argued that taxes on incomes,
sales, and payrolls, for example, acted as disincentives
to production and active endeavour, thereby stifling
economic growth and creating a barrier to full
employment. A land tax, by contrast, would be both
economically efficient and more equitable in its
distributional effects. ... read the whole
article
|
To share this page with a friend:
right click, choose "send," and add your
comments.
|
|
Red links have not been
visited; .
Green links are pages you've seen
|
Essential Documents pertinent
to this theme:
|
|