Tax Justice
There is a group in Washington that calls itself Citizens
for Tax Justice. Their research is often good and
relevant, but their solutions fail to meet the criteria
for real justice. Here are some Georgist writings
which they might find illuminating, and which you might
find useful in evaluating what CTJ, and others, propose
in the way of tax reform.
Henry George: The Condition of Labor
— An Open Letter to Pope Leo XIII in response to
Rerum Novarum (1891)
Nor do we hesitate to say that this way of securing
the equal right to the bounty of the Creator and the
exclusive right to the products of labor is the way
intended by God for raising public revenues. For we are
not atheists, who deny God; nor semi-atheists, who deny
that he has any concern in politics and legislation.
It is true as you say — a salutary truth too
often forgotten — that “man is older than the
state, and he holds the right of providing for the life
of his body prior to the formation of any state.”
Yet, as you too perceive, it is also true that the state
is in the divinely appointed order. For He who foresaw
all things and provided for all things, foresaw and
provided that with the increase of population and the
development of industry the organization of human society
into states or governments would become both expedient
and necessary.
No sooner does the state arise than, as we all know,
it needs revenues. This need for revenues is small at
first, while population is sparse, industry rude and the
functions of the state few and simple. But with growth of
population and advance of civilization the functions of
the state increase and larger and larger revenues are
needed.
Now, He that made the world and placed man in it, He
that pre-ordained civilization as the means whereby man
might rise to higher powers and become more and more
conscious of the works of his Creator, must have foreseen
this increasing need for state revenues and have made
provision for it. That is to say: The increasing
need for public revenues with social advance, being a
natural, God-ordained need, there must be a right way of
raising them — some way that we can truly say is
the way intended by God. It is clear that this right way
of raising public revenues must accord with the moral
law.
Hence:
It must not take from individuals what
rightfully belongs to individuals.
It must not give some an advantage over
others, as by increasing the prices of what some have to
sell and others must buy.
It must not lead men into temptation, by
requiring trivial oaths, by making it profitable to lie,
to swear falsely, to bribe or to take
bribes.
It must not confuse the distinctions of right
and wrong, and weaken the sanctions of religion and the
state by creating crimes that are not sins, and punishing
men for doing what in itself they have an undoubted right
to do.
It must not repress industry. It must not
check commerce. It must not punish thrift. It must offer
no impediment to the largest production and the fairest
division of wealth.
Let me ask your Holiness to consider the taxes
on the processes and products of industry by which
through the civilized world public revenues are collected
— the octroi duties that surround Italian cities
with barriers; the monstrous customs duties that hamper
intercourse between so-called Christian states; the taxes
on occupations, on earnings, on investments, on the
building of houses, on the cultivation of fields, on
industry and thrift in all forms. Can these be the ways
God has intended that governments should raise the means
they need? Have any of them the characteristics
indispensable in any plan we can deem a right
one?
All these taxes violate the moral law. They
take by force what belongs to the individual alone; they
give to the unscrupulous an advantage over the
scrupulous; they have the effect, nay are largely
intended, to increase the price of what some have to sell
and others must buy; they corrupt government; they make
oaths a mockery; they shackle commerce; they fine
industry and thrift; they lessen the wealth that men
might enjoy, and enrich some by impoverishing
others.
Yet what most strikingly shows how opposed to
Christianity is this system of raising public revenues is
its influence on thought.
Christianity teaches us that all men are brethren;
that their true interests are harmonious, not
antagonistic. It gives us, as the golden rule of life,
that we should do to others as we would have others do to
us. But out of the system of taxing the products and
processes of labor, and out of its effects in increasing
the price of what some have to sell and others must buy,
has grown the theory of “protection,” which
denies this gospel, which holds Christ ignorant of
political economy and proclaims laws of national
well-being utterly at variance with his teaching. This
theory sanctifies national hatreds; it inculcates a
universal war of hostile tariffs; it teaches peoples that
their prosperity lies in imposing on the productions of
other peoples restrictions they do not wish imposed on
their own; and instead of the Christian doctrine of
man’s brotherhood it makes injury of foreigners a
civic virtue.
“By their fruits ye shall know them.” Can
anything more clearly show that to tax the products and
processes of industry is not the way God intended public
revenues to be raised?
But to consider what we propose — the raising of
public revenues by a single tax on the value of land
irrespective of improvements — is to see that in
all respects this does conform to the moral law.
Let me ask your Holiness to keep in mind that the
value we propose to tax, the value of land irrespective
of improvements, does not come from any exertion of labor
or investment of capital on or in it — the values
produced in this way being values of improvement which we
would exempt. The value of land irrespective of
improvement is the value that attaches to land by reason
of increasing population and social progress. This is a
value that always goes to the owner as owner, and never
does and never can go to the user; for if the user be a
different person from the owner he must always pay the
owner for it in rent or in purchase-money; while if the
user be also the owner, it is as owner, not as user, that
he receives it, and by selling or renting the land he
can, as owner, continue to receive it after he ceases to
be a user.
Thus, taxes on land irrespective of improvement cannot
lessen the rewards of industry, nor add to prices,* nor
in any way take from the individual what belongs to the
individual. They can take only the value that attaches to
land by the growth of the community, and which therefore
belongs to the community as a whole.
* As to this point it may be well to add
that all economists are agreed that taxes on land
values irrespective of improvement or use — or
what in the terminology of political economy is styled
rent, a term distinguished from the ordinary use of the
word rent by being applied solely to payments for the
use of land itself — must be paid by the owner
and cannot be shifted by him on the user. To explain in
another way the reason given in the text: Price is not
determined by the will of the seller or the will of the
buyer, but by the equation of demand and supply, and
therefore as to things constantly demanded and
constantly produced rests at a point determined by the
cost of production — whatever tends to increase
the cost of bringing fresh quantities of such articles
to the consumer increasing price by checking supply,
and whatever tends to reduce such cost decreasing price
by increasing supply. Thus taxes on wheat or tobacco or
cloth add to the price that the consumer must pay, and
thus the cheapening in the cost of producing steel
which improved processes have made in recent years has
greatly reduced the price of steel. But land has no
cost of production, since it is created by God, not
produced by man. Its price therefore is fixed
—
1 (monopoly rent), where land is held
in close monopoly, by what the owners can extract
from the users under penalty of deprivation and
consequently of starvation, and amounts to all that
common labor can earn on it beyond what is necessary
to life;
2 (economic rent proper), where there is no special
monopoly, by what the particular land will yield to
common labor over and above what may be had by like
expenditure and exertion on land having no special
advantage and for which no rent is paid; and,
3 (speculative rent, which is a species of monopoly
rent, telling particularly in selling price), by the
expectation of future increase of value from social
growth and improvement, which expectation causing
landowners to withhold land at present prices has the
same effect as combination.
Taxes on land values or economic rent
can therefore never be shifted by the landowner to the
land-user, since they in no wise increase the demand
for land or enable landowners to check supply by
withholding land from use. Where rent depends on mere
monopolization, a case I mention because rent may in
this way be demanded for the use of land even before
economic or natural rent arises, the taking by taxation
of what the landowners were able to extort from labor
could not enable them to extort any more, since
laborers, if not left enough to live on, will die. So,
in the case of economic rent proper, to take from the
landowners the premiums they receive, would in no way
increase the superiority of their land and the demand
for it. While, so far as price is affected by
speculative rent, to compel the landowners to pay taxes
on the value of land whether they were getting any
income from it or not, would make it more difficult for
them to withhold land from use; and to tax the full
value would not merely destroy the power but the desire
to do so.
To take land values for the state, abolishing all
taxes on the products of labor, would therefore leave to
the laborer the full produce of labor; to the individual
all that rightfully belongs to the individual. It would
impose no burden on industry, no check on commerce, no
punishment on thrift; it would secure the largest
production and the fairest distribution of wealth, by
leaving men free to produce and to exchange as they
please, without any artificial enhancement of prices; and
by taking for public purposes a value that cannot be
carried off, that cannot be hidden, that of all values is
most easily ascertained and most certainly and cheaply
collected, it would enormously lessen the number of
officials, dispense with oaths, do away with temptations
to bribery and evasion, and abolish man-made crimes in
themselves innocent.
But, further: That God has intended the state to
obtain the revenues it needs by the taxation of land
values is shown by the same order and degree of evidence
that shows that God has intended the milk of the mother
for the nourishment of the babe.
See how close is the analogy. In that primitive
condition ere the need for the state arises there are no
land values. The products of labor have value, but in the
sparsity of population no value as yet attaches to land
itself. But as increasing density of population and
increasing elaboration of industry necessitate the
organization of the state, with its need for revenues,
value begins to attach to land. As population still
increases and industry grows more elaborate, so the needs
for public revenues increase. And at the same time and
from the same causes land values increase. The connection
is invariable. The value of things produced by labor
tends to decline with social development, since the
larger scale of production and the improvement of
processes tend steadily to reduce their cost. But the
value of land on which population centers goes up and up.
Take Rome or Paris or London or New York or Melbourne.
Consider the enormous value of land in such cities as
compared with the value of land in sparsely settled parts
of the same countries. To what is this due? Is it not due
to the density and activity of the populations of those
cities — to the very causes that require great
public expenditure for streets, drains, public buildings,
and all the many things needed for the health,
convenience and safety of such great cities? See how with
the growth of such cities the one thing that steadily
increases in value is land; how the opening of roads, the
building of railways, the making of any public
improvement, adds to the value of land. Is it not clear
that here is a natural law — that is to say a
tendency willed by the Creator? Can it mean anything else
than that He who ordained the state with its needs has in
the values which attach to land provided the means to
meet those needs?
That it does mean this and nothing else is confirmed
if we look deeper still, and inquire not merely as to the
intent, but as to the purpose of the intent. If we do so
we may see in this natural law by which land values
increase with the growth of society not only such a
perfectly adapted provision for the needs of society as
gratifies our intellectual perceptions by showing us the
wisdom of the Creator, but a purpose with regard to the
individual that gratifies our moral perceptions by
opening to us a glimpse of his beneficence.
Consider: Here is a natural law by which as society
advances the one thing that increases in value is land
— a natural law by virtue of which all growth of
population, all advance of the arts, all general
improvements of whatever kind, add to a fund that both
the commands of justice and the dictates of expediency
prompt us to take for the common uses of society. Now,
since increase in the fund available for the common uses
of society is increase in the gain that goes equally to
each member of society, is it not clear that the law by
which land values increase with social advance while the
value of the products of labor does not increase, tends
with the advance of civilization to make the share that
goes equally to each member of society more and more
important as compared with what goes to him from his
individual earnings, and thus to make the advance of
civilization lessen relatively the differences that in a
ruder social state must exist between the strong and the
weak, the fortunate and the unfortunate? Does it not show
the purpose of the Creator to be that the advance of man
in civilization should be an advance not merely to larger
powers but to a greater and greater equality, instead of
what we, by our ignoring of his intent, are making it, an
advance toward a more and more monstrous inequality? ...
read the whole
letter
Henry George: The
Common Sense of Taxation (1881 article)
IT may seem like a truism to assert that the only fund
upon which taxation can draw is that made up by the
produce of the community, and that to multiply the places
at which it is tapped is not to increase its capacity to
yield. Yet the manner in which taxation, under our
system, is spread over a multitude of subjects, and new
subjects are still sought for, suggests the belief of
that chief of the eunuchs who thought the weight of an
obnoxious poll-tax might be lessened, and his masters
revenues at the same time increased, by substituting for
the tax on heads a tax upon fingers and toes.
But it is probable that the disposition to tax
everything susceptible of taxation does not spring so
much from the notion that more may thus be obtained, as
from the notion that as a matter of justice everything
should be taxed. That all species of property shall be
equally taxed, is enjoined by many of our State
constitutions, and that it should be so, at least so far
as direct taxation is concerned, is regarded by most of
our people as a self-evident truth — the idea being
that every one should contribute to public expenses in
proportion to his means, or, as it is sometimes phrased,
that all property, being equally protected by the State,
should equally contribute to the expenses of the
State.
But under no system that any of our legislatures have
yet been able to devise is all property equally taxed;
nor can it be equally taxed. And if it were possible to
even approximate to the equal taxation of all property,
this would not be to secure that equality which justice
demands. For, as is evident in the case of mortgages,
etc., to equally tax all property would infallibly be to
levy a higher rate of taxation upon some than upon
others; and even if the same proportion could be taken
from the means of every member of the community, that
would no more conform to the dictates of equality than
would the levy upon each of an equal sum; for, as the
demand for a sum which would not be felt by the rich man
would fall with crushing weight on the poor man, so to
take the same proportion of their means would be a very
different thing to him who has barely enough, and to him
who has a large surplus.
Quite as fallacious is the idea that all property
should be equally taxed, because equally protected. The
fact is that all property is not equally protected,
cannot be equally protected, and ought not to be equally
protected, if by protection anything more is meant than
the mere preservation of the peace. The protection of
property is not the end, it is only one of the incidents,
of government. As John Stuart Mill says: "The ends of
government are as comprehensive as those of the social
union. They consist of all the good and all the immunity
from evil which the existence of government can be made,
either directly or indirectly, to bestow." And to say
that government should impartially protect and equally
tax all property, is like saying that the farmer should
bestow the same care upon everything he may find growing
in his fields, whether weeds or grain. ...
Evidently this regard for the general good is the true
principle of taxation. The more it is examined the more
clearly it will be seen that there is no valid reason why
we should, in any case, attempt to tax all property. That
equality should be the rule and aim of taxation is true,
and this for the reason given in the Declaration of
Independence, that all men are created equal. But
equality does not require that all men should be taxed
alike, or that all things should be taxed alike. It
merely requires that whatever taxes are imposed shall be
equally imposed upon the persons or things in like
conditions or situations; it merely requires that no
citizen shall be given an advantage, or put at a
disadvantage, as compared with other citizens.
The true purposes of government are well stated in the
preamble to the Constitution of the United States, as
they are in the Declaration of Independence. To insure
the general peace, to promote the general welfare, to
secure to each individual the inalienable rights to life,
liberty, and the pursuit of happiness — these are
the proper ends of government, and are therefore the ends
which in every scheme of taxation should be kept in
mind.
As to amount of taxation, there is no principle which
imposes any arbitrary limit. Heavy taxation is better for
any community than light taxation, if the increased
revenue be used in doing by public agencies things which
could not be done, or could not be as well and
economically done, by private agencies. Taxes could be
lightened in the city of New York by dispensing with
street-lamps and disbanding the police force. But would a
reduction in taxation gained in this way be for the
benefit of the people of New York and make New York a
more desirable place to live in? Or if it should be found
that heat and light could be conducted through the
streets at public expense and supplied to each house at
but a small fraction of the cost of supplying them by
individual effort, or that the city railroads could be
run at public expense so as to give every one
transportation at very much less than it now costs the
average resident, the increased taxation necessary for
these purposes would not be increased burden, and in
spite of the larger taxation required, New York would
become a more desirable place to live in. It is a mistake
to condemn taxation as bad merely because it is high; it
is a mistake to impose by constitutional provision, as in
many of our States has been advocated, and in some of our
States has been done, any restriction upon the amount of
taxation. A restriction upon the incurring of public
indebtedness is another matter. In nothing is the
far-reaching statesmanship of Jefferson more clearly
shown than in his proposition that all public obligations
should be deemed void after a certain brief term —
a proposition which he grounds upon the self-evident
truth that the earth belongs in usufruct to the living,
and that the dead have no control over it, and can give
no title to any part of it. But restriction upon public
debts is a very different thing from restriction upon the
power of taxation, and reasons which urge the one do not
apply to the other. Nor is increased taxation necessarily
proof of governmental extravagance. Increase in taxation
is in the order of social development, for the reason
that social development tends to the doing of things
collectively that in a ruder state are done individually,
to the giving to government of new functions and the
imposing of new duties. Our public schools and libraries
and parks, our signal service and fish commissions and
agricultural bureaus and grasshopper investigations, are
evidences of this.
But while no limit can be properly fixed for the
amount of taxation, the method of taxation is of supreme
importance. A horse may be anchored by fastening to his
bridle a weight which he will not feel when carried in a
buggy behind him. The best ship may be made utterly
unseaworthy by the bad stowage of a cargo which properly
placed would make her the stiffer and more weatherly. So
enterprise may be palsied, industry crushed, accumulation
prevented, and a prosperous country turned into a desert,
by taxation which rightly levied would hardly be
felt.
Now discarding all idea that there rests upon us any
obligation to equally tax all kinds of property, and
assuming for our guidance the true rule, that taxation
should be levied with a view to the promotion of the
general prosperity, the securing of substantial equality,
and the recognition of inalienable rights, let us
consider upon what species of property it may be best
laid.
To consider what is included in the category of
property is to see the absurdity of saying that all
property should be equally taxed. ...
To consider the nature of property of this kind is
again to see a clear distinction. That distinction is
not, as the lawyers have it, between movables and
immovables, between personal property and real estate.
The true distinction is between property which is, and
property which is not, the result of human labor; or, to
use the terms of political economy, between land and
wealth. For, in any precise use of the term, land is not
wealth, any more than labor is wealth. Land and labor are
the factors of production. Wealth is such result of their
union as retains the capacity of ministering to human
desire. A lot and the house which stands upon it are
alike property, alike have a tangible value, and are
alike classed as real estate. But there are between them
the most essential differences. The one is the free gift
of Nature, the other the result of human exertion; the
one exists from generation to generation, while men come
and go; the other is constantly tending to decay, and can
only be preserved by continual exertion. To the one, the
right of exclusive possession, which makes it individual
property, can, like the right of property in slaves, be
traced to nothing but municipal law; to the other, the
right of exclusive property springs clearly from those
natural relations which are among the primary perceptions
of the human mind. Nor are these mere abstract
distinctions. They are distinctions of the first
importance in determining what should and what should not
be taxed.
For, keeping in mind the fact that all wealth is the
result of human exertion, it is clearly seen that, having
in view the promotion of the general prosperity, it is
the height of absurdity to tax wealth for purposes of
revenue while there remains, unexhausted by taxation, any
value attaching to land. We may tax land values as much
as we please, without in the slightest degree lessening
the amount of land, or the capabilities of land, or the
inducement to use land. But we cannot tax wealth without
lessening the inducement to the production of wealth, and
decreasing the amount of wealth. We might take the whole
value of land in taxation, so as to make the ownership of
land worth nothing, and the land would still remain, and
be as useful as before. The effect would be to throw land
open to users free of price, and thus to increase its
capabilities, which are brought out by increased
population. But impose anything like such taxation upon
wealth, and the inducement to the production of wealth
would be gone. Movable wealth would be hidden or carried
off, immovable wealth would be suffered to go to decay,
and where was prosperity would soon be the silence of
desolation.
And the reason of this difference is clear. The
possession of wealth is the inducement to the exertion
necessary to the production and maintenance of wealth.
Men do not work for the pleasure of working, but to get
the things their work will give them. And to tax the
things that are produced by exertion is to lessen the
inducement to exertion. But over and above the benefit to
the possessor, which is the stimulating motive to the
production of wealth, there is a benefit to the
community, for no matter how selfish he may be, it is
utterly impossible for any one to entirely keep to
himself the benefit of any desirable thing he may
possess. These diffused benefits when localized give
value to land, and this may be taxed without in any wise
diminishing the incentive to production.
To illustrate: A man builds a fine house or large
factory in a poorly improved neighborhood. To tax this
building and its adjuncts is to make him pay for his
enterprise and expenditure — to take from him part
of his natural reward. But the improvement thus made has
given new beauty or life to the neighborhood, making it a
more desirable place than before for the erection of
other houses or factories, and additional value is given
to land all about. Now to tax improvements is not only to
deprive of his proper reward the man who has made the
improvement, but it is to deter others from making
similar improvements. But, instead of taxing
improvements, to tax these land values is to leave the
natural inducement to further improvement in full force,
and at the same time to keep down an obstacle to further
improvement, which, under the present system, improvement
itself tends to raise. For the advance of land values
which follows improvement, and even the expectation of
improvement, makes further improvement more costly.
See how unjust and short-sighted is this system. Here
is a man who, gathering what little capital he can, and
taking his family, starts West to find a place where he
can make himself a home. He must travel long distances;
for, though he will pass plenty of land nobody is using,
it is held at prices too high for him. Finally he will go
no further, and selects a place where, since the creation
of the world, the soil, so far as we know, has never felt
a plowshare. But here, too, in nine cases out of ten, he
will find the speculator has been ahead of him, for the
speculator moves quicker, and has superior means of
information to the emigrant. Before he can put this land
to the use for which nature intended it, and to which it
is for the general good that it should be put, he must
make terms with some man who in all probability never saw
the land, and never dreamed of using it, and who, it may
be, resides in some city, thousands of miles away. In
order to get permission to use this land, he must give up
a large part of the little capital which is seed-wheat to
him, and perhaps in addition mortgage his future labor
for years. Still he goes to work: he works himself, and
his wife works, and his children work — work like
horses, and live in the hardest and dreariest manner.
Such a man deserves encouragement, not discouragement;
but on him taxation falls with peculiar severity. Almost
everything that he has to buy — groceries,
clothing, tools — is largely raised in price by a
system of tariff taxation which cannot add to the price
of the grain or hogs or cattle that he has to sell. And
when the assessor comes around he is taxed on the
improvements he has made, although these improvements
have added not only to the value of surrounding land, but
even to the value of land in distant commercial centers.
Not merely this, but, as a general rule, his land,
irrespective of the improvements, will be assessed at a
higher rate than unimproved land around it, on the ground
that "productive property" ought to pay more than
"unproductive property" — a principle just the
reverse of the correct one, for the man who makes land
productive adds to the general prosperity, while the man
who keeps land unproductive stands in the way of the
general prosperity, is but a dog-in-the-manger, who
prevents others from using what he will not use
himself.
Or, take the case of the railroads. That railroads are
a public benefit no one will dispute. We want more
railroads, and want them to reduce their fares and
freight. Why then should we tax them? for taxes upon
railroads deter from railroad building, and compel higher
charges. Instead of taxing the railroads, is it not clear
that we should rather tax the increased value which they
give to land? To tax railroads is to check railroad
building, to reduce profits, and compel higher rates; to
tax the value they give to land is to increase railroad
business and permit lower rates. The elevated railroads,
for instance, have opened to the overcrowded population
of New York the wide, vacant spaces of the upper part of
the island. But this great public benefit is neutralized
by the rise in land values. Because these vacant lots can
be reached more cheaply and quickly, their owners demand
more for them, and so the public gain in one way is
offset in another, while the roads lose the business they
would get were not building checked by the high prices
demanded for lots. The increase of land values, which the
elevated roads have caused, is not merely no advantage to
them — it is an injury; and it is clearly a public
injury. The elevated railroads ought not to be taxed. The
more profit they make, with the better conscience can
they be asked to still further reduce fares. It is the
increased land values which they have created that ought
to be taxed, for taxing them will give the public the
full benefit of cheap fares.
So with railroads everywhere. And so not alone with
railroads, but with all industrial enterprises. So long
as we consider that community most prosperous which
increases most rapidly in wealth, so long is it the
height of absurdity for us to tax wealth in any of its
beneficial forms. We should tax what we want to repress,
not what we want to encourage. We should tax that which
results from the general prosperity, not that which
conduces to it. It is the increase of population, the
extension of cultivation, the manufacture of goods, the
building of houses and ships and railroads, the
accumulation of capital, and the growth of commerce that
add to the value of land — not the increase in the
value of land that induces the increase of population and
increase of wealth. It is not that the land of Manhattan
Island is now worth hundreds of millions where, in the
time of the early Dutch settlers, it was only worth
dollars, that there are on it now so many more people,
and so much more wealth. It is because of the increase of
population and the increase of wealth that the value of
the land has so much increased. Increase of land values
tends of itself to repel population and prevent
improvement. And thus the taxation of land values, unlike
taxation of other property, does not tend to prevent the
increase of wealth, but rather to stimulate it. It is the
taking of the golden egg, not the choking of the goose
that lays it.
Every consideration of policy and ethics squares with
this conclusion. The tax upon land values is the most
economically perfect of all taxes. It does not raise
prices; it maybe collected at least cost, and with the
utmost ease and certainty; it leaves in full strength all
the springs of production; and, above all, it consorts
with the truest equality and the highest justice. For, to
take for the common purposes of the community that value
which results from the growth of the community, and to
free industry and enterprise and thrift from burden and
restraint, is to leave to each that which he fairly
earns, and to assert the first and most comprehensive of
equal rights — the equal right of all to the land
on which, and from which, all must live.
Thus it is that the scheme of taxation which conduces
to the greatest production is also that which conduces to
the fairest distribution, and that in the proper
adjustment of taxation lies not merely the possibility of
enormously increasing the general wealth, but the
solution of these pressing social and political problems
which spring from unnatural inequality in the
distribution of wealth.
"There is," says M. de Laveleye, in concluding that
work in which he shows that the first perceptions of
mankind have everywhere recognized a most vital
distinction between property in land and property which
results from labor, — "there is in human affairs
one system which is the best; it is not that system which
always exists, otherwise why should we desire to change
it; but it is that system which should exist for the
greatest good of humanity. God knows it, and wills it;
man's duty it is to discover and establish it." read the whole
article
H.G. Brown: Significant Paragraphs
from Henry George's Progress &
Poverty, Chapter 8: Why a Land-Value Tax is
Better than an Equal Tax on All Property (in the
unabridged P&P:
Book VIII: Application of the Remedy — Chapter 3: The
proposition tried by the canons of taxation)
The ground upon which the equal taxation of all
species of property is commonly insisted upon is that it
is equally protected by the state. The basis of this idea
is evidently that the enjoyment of property is made
possible by the state — that there is a value
created and maintained by the community, which is justly
called upon to meet community expenses. Now, of what
values is this true? Only of the value of land. This is a
value that does not arise until a community is formed,
and that, unlike other values, grows with the growth of
the community. It exists only as the community exists.
Scatter again the largest community, and land, now so
valuable, would have no value at all. With every increase
of population the value of land rises; with every
decrease it falls. This is true of nothing else save of
things which, like the ownership of land, are in their
nature monopolies.
The tax upon land values is, therefore, the most just
and equal of all taxes.
- It falls only upon those who receive from society a
peculiar and valuable benefit, and upon them in
proportion to the benefit they receive.
- It is the taking by the community, for the use of
the community, of that value which is the creation of
the community.
- It is the application of the common property to
common uses.
When all rent is taken by taxation for the needs of
the community, then will the equality ordained by Nature
be attained. No citizen will have an advantage over any
other citizen save as is given by his industry, skill,
and intelligence; and each will obtain what he fairly
earns. Then, but not till then, will labor get its full
reward, and capital its natural return. ... read the whole
chapter
Henry George: Justice
the Object -- Taxation the Means (1890)
Tax buildings, and you will have fewer or poorer
buildings; tax farms, and you will have fewer farms and
more wilderness; tax ships, there will be fewer and
poorer ships; and tax capital, and there will be less
capital; but you may tax land values all you please and
there will not he a square inch the less land. Tax land
values all you please up to the point of taking the full
annual value — up to the point of making mere
ownership in land utterly unprofitable, so that no one
will want merely to own land — what will be the
result? Simply that land will be the easier had by the
user. Simply that the land will become valueless to the
mere speculator — to the dog in the manger, who
wants merely to hold and not to use; to the forestaller,
who wants merely to reap where others have sown, to
gather to himself the products of labour, without doing
labour. Tax land values, and you leave to production its
full rewards, and you open to producers natural
opportunities.
Read the entire article
Henry George: The
Single Tax: What It Is and Why We Urge It (1890)
When we tax houses, crops, money, furniture,
capital or wealth in any of its forms, we take from
individuals what rightfully belongs to them. We
violate the right of property, and in the name of the
State commit robbery. But when we tax ground values,
we take from individuals what does not belong to them,
but belongs to the community, and which cannot be
left to individuals without robbery of other
individuals. ... read the whole
article
Louis Post: Outlines of
Louis F. Post's Lectures, with Illustrative Notes and
Charts (1894)
c. Significance of the Upward Tendency of
Rent
Now, what is the meaning of this tendency of Rent to
rise with social progress, while Wages tend to fall? Is
it not a plain promise that if Rent be treated as common
property, advances in productive power shall be steps in
the direction of realizing through orderly and natural
growth those grand conceptions of both the socialist and
the individualist, which in the present condition of
society are justly ranked as Utopian? Is it not likewise
a plain warning that if Rent be treated as private
property, advances in productive power will be steps in
the direction of making slaves of the many laborers, and
masters of a few land-owners? Does it not mean that
common ownership of Rent is in harmony with natural law,
and that its private appropriation is disorderly and
degrading? When the cause of Rent and the tendency
illustrated in the preceding chart are considered in
connection with the self-evident truth that God made the
earth for common use and not for private monopoly, how
can a contrary inference hold? Caused and
increased by social growth, 97 the benefits of which
should be common, and attaching to land, the just right
to which is equal, Rent must be the natural fund for
public expenses. 98
97. Here, far away from civilization, is
a solitary settler. Getting no benefits from
government, he needs no public revenues, and none of
the land about him has any value. Another settler
comes, and another, until a village appears. Some
public revenue is then required. Not much, but some.
And the land has a little value, only a little; perhaps
just enough to equal the need for public revenue. The
village becomes a town. More revenues are needed, and
land values are higher. It becomes a city. The public
revenues required are enormous, and so are the land
values.
98. Society, and society alone,
causes Rent. Rising with the rise, advancing
with the growth, and receding with the decline of
society, it measures the earning power of society as a
whole as distinguished from that of the individuals.
Wages, on the other hand, measure the earning power of
the individuals as distinguished from that of society
as a whole. We have distinguished the parts into which
Wealth is distributed as Wages and Rent; but it would
be correct, indeed it is the same thing, to regard all
wealth as earnings, and to distinguish the two kinds as
Communal Earnings and Individual Earnings. How,
then, can there be any question as to the fund from
which society should be supported? How can it be justly
supported in any other way than out of its own
earnings?
If there be at all such a thing as design in the
universe — and who can doubt it? — then has
it been designed that Rent, the earnings of the
community, shall be retained for the support of the
community, and that Wages, the earnings of the
individual, shall be left to the individual in proportion
to the value of his service. This is the divine law,
whether we trace it through complex moral and economic
relations, or find it in the eighth commandment. ...
read the book
Charles B. Fillebrown: A Catechism of Natural
Taxation, from Principles of Natural Taxation
(1917)
Q46. Would it not be confiscation so to increase
the tax on land?
A. What would be confiscated? No land would be taken, no
right of occupancy, or use, or improvement, or sale, or
devise; nothing would be taken that is conveyed or
guaranteed by the title deed.
Q47. What is the distinction between taxation and
confiscation?
A. The sovereign state may appropriate private property
of its citizens in two ways: (1) by confiscation; (2) by
taxation. When one particular man by treason or otherwise
has forfeited his rights as a citizen, the land and
houses and personalty of this one man may all be "forfeit
to the crown," while the validity and sanctity of 9,999
other men's rights are in no way infringed. This is
confiscation. On the other hand, when the state, in order
to obtain the revenue to meet the expenses of government,
levies tribute upon its 10,000 citizens impartially, this
is taxation.
Q48. But would it not be an injustice to the
landowner?
A. If it be an injustice to tax hard-earned incomes
(wages) to maintain an unearned income (net economic
rent) that bears no tax burden, how can it be an
injustice to stop doing so? There can be no injustice in
taking for the benefit of the community the value that is
created by the community.
Q61. Do you think there would be any injustice in
taking by taxation the future increment in the value of
land?
A. Fifteen professors of political economy have answered
"Yes." Ninety-four have answered "No." ... read the whole
article
Ted Gwartney: Estimating Land
Values
The economic market rental value of land should be
sufficient to finance public services and to obviate the
need for raising revenue from taxes, such as income or
wage taxes; sales, commodity or value-added taxes; and
taxes on buildings, machinery and industry. Public
revenue should not be supplied by taxes on people and
enterprise until after all of the available revenue has
been first collected from the natural and community
created value of land. Only if land rent were
insufficient would it be necessary to collect any
taxes.
The collection of land rent, by the
public for supplying public needs, returns the advantage an
individual receives from the exclusive use of a land site
to the balance of the community, who along with nature,
contributed to its value and allow its exclusive
use. ...
EFFICIENCY OF PUBLIC
REVENUE
Adam Smith, in The Wealth of Nations, suggested
that any "tax" should be a charge for services which
benefit all people and are more efficiently performed by
a single cooperative effort. He postulated four
principles of taxation which any source of revenue should
meet:
1. Light on the production of wealth, and does not
impede or reduce production;
2. Cheap to collect, requiring few collectors,
and easy to understand;
3. Certain; can't be avoided, little
opportunity for corruption, and provides adequate
revenue;
4. Equitable and fair, payment for benefits
received, impartial, and just.
Collecting public revenue from land rent is the
only revenue source, or "tax", that meets these
criteria.
While the major argument for raising
public revenue from land rent and natural resources is
because it is equitable and fair, it is also the most
efficient method of raising the revenue which is needed for
public facilities and services. Land is visible, can't be
hidden and its valuation is less intrusive than valuations
of income and sales. Taxes on labor and capital cause
people to consider alternative options, including working
with less effort, which produces less real goods. For
example, a tax on wages will reduce after-tax net wages and
weaken the incentive to work. A person might be willing to
work hard for a wage of $20 per hour, but decide to drop
out if the taxes take $8 and the net wage is only $12 per
hour. Economists claim that present taxes account for a 25%
loss in production in the United States. Production and
consumption would be greatly improved if public revenue
came primarily from land rather than a wage tax. The same
would occur when buildings and machinery are taxed. The tax
on building reduces the quantity and quality of buildings
produced. A tax on sales, commerce or value added reduces
consumption, production and net wealth. Sales tax evasion
in the United States has exceeded 30% in recent
years.
As new inventions and more efficient ways
of producing goods are discovered, people's economic
well-being is not improved, because they have lost access
to land and must pay both rent and taxes. (5) Instead of rent being used to
provide community services, capital and wages must be
depleted, which obstructs private enterprise. When the
rent of land is taken for public purposes production and
distribution are not held back. This is because the same
amount of rent would otherwise have been taken by some
private individual. The rent would be the same, the
difference is how it is utilized. There is evidence that
communities who raise their revenue from land, rather
than from labor and capital, are more prosperous, many
increasing productivity by more than 25%.
HOW MUCH LAND RENT SHOULD THE
COMMUNITY COLLECT?
In order to preserve the environment,
it is necessary and possible to better utilize our
communities. If the producers of the land market value
(nature, government and people) don't utilize land rent,
someone else will. This is why efficient land use fails
under contemporary land systems in most countries. All
countries collect some of the land rent, perhaps 10%, 20%
or 30%, but none yet, collect all of the market rent of
land.
Studies have been produced that
demonstrate that communities prosper and succeed in
proportion to the percentage of the land rent that they
collect. The first communities that decide to collect all
of the ground rent will have an enormous competitive
advantage over all other communities. They will be able to
reduce or eliminate regressive taxes on labor and capital.
They will attract new business and industry and become
prosperous.
To determine how much
land rent the community should collect, let's consider the
alternatives. Whatever is not collected will be capitalized
into market value by land owners. Buying land at inflated
market prices is a block to new industry. Land owners sell
the capitalized land rent (known as land value) which is
uncollected by the community even though it is unearned
income. This causes a disparity between landowners and
non-landowners. In the United States 5% of the population,
which does not include many homeowners or farmers, own 70%
of the total national land and natural resource
values.
People will come to a well run
community because they will be better off than living by
themselves or in an impoverished locale. A city must secure
revenue in order to provide good quality
services.
This revenue can best be procured
when the community recaptures the value of the benefits and
services that it provides. This is done by collecting the
rental revenue from land that reflects the value of the
services and facilities provided in that community. The
land rent belongs equally to all people that live in the
locale who helped to produce that value. In a well run
community, there is sufficient land rent to provide
adequate funding for the social purposes requested of, and
provided by, the local city government.
Cities which choose to collect land
rent as their primary source of revenue have the advantage
of not requiring burdensome taxes to be paid by workers,
businesspeople, entrepreneurs or citizens. Individuals who
work to create wealth should be allowed to keep what they
produce. When labor is not taxed, greater production and
consumption occurs. Investment capital is formed which is
used to produce more wealth. New jobs are created and
economic diversity results.
Each person has a right to keep what
he or she produces, but no one has the right to waste what
belongs to all people, the land which includes the natural
environment. Each person should have an opportunity to use
the best land for his business or personal needs, as long
as they are willing to pay the land rent that other land
users are willing to pay.
If the value of land rent exceeds the
community's needs for public services a method of
dispensing of the revenue can easily be found. To
maintain an equitable society, where nobody has special
benefits that they do not pay for, it is important to
collect all of the land rent. The community should
use what is needed for public services and improvements
such as schools, hospitals, parks, police, roadways,
utilities and defense -- and reserve a fund for
emergencies.
An ethical proposal might be to then
divide the excess revenue that is not needed for public
facilities and services at the end of each year and send
each citizen in that community an equal portion of the
remaining revenue. This is similar to the method used in
Alaska and Alberta. Equality of opportunity to be
productive can only be accomplished by recapturing all of
the market rent of land and ensuring that all people
benefit from its value.
Not only is land rent potentially an
important source of public revenue, collecting all of it
would ensure that the equal opportunity to be productive
would be available to all citizens. People could fund
useful buildings, equipment and wages, rather than having
to buy land at inflated prices. Many countries, including
the United States, were started on the premise of using
land rent to fund public services. Many countries suffer
economic loss because they no longer collect the market
rent of land.
The value of land can be estimated
with an acceptable accuracy, at a cost which is very small
compared to the revenue to be obtained. A proper system of
assessment and taxation of land can provide for the proper
economic use of the land. A land site should be available
to the user who can make the highest and best use of the
site and maximize the site benefits for all people. A land
tax can provide a major source of public revenue which the
local governing body could use for the benefit of all
people. A land tax can prevent the dispossession of our
children, the future producers in the society. Justice
requires that land values, which are created by society and
nature, be made available for public improvements. This is
the responsibility of good government. ... Read the whole
article
Weld Carter: An
Introduction to Henry George
However, what is the effect on
production of taxes levied on products and of taxes levied
on the value of land?
Of taxes levied on products, George
said: "The present method of taxation operates upon
exchange like artificial deserts and mountains; it costs
more to get goods through a custom house than it does to
carry them around the world. It operates upon energy, and
industry, and skill, and thrift, like a fine upon those
qualities. If I have worked harder and built myself a good
house while you have been contented to live in a hovel, the
taxgatherer now comes annually to make me pay a penalty for
my energy and industry, by taxing me more than you. If I
have saved while you wasted, I am mulct, while you are
exempt. If a man build a ship we make him pay for his
temerity, as though he had done an injury to the state; if
a railroad be opened, down comes the taxcollector upon it,
as though it were a public nuisance; if a manufactory be
erected we levy upon it an annual sum which would go far
toward making a handsome profit. We say we want capital,
but if anyone accumulate it, or bring it among us, we
charge him for it as though we were giving him a privilege.
We punish with a tax the man who covers barren fields with
ripening grain, we fine him who puts up machinery, and him
who drains a swamp. How heavily these taxes burden
production only those realize who have attempted to follow
our system of taxation through its ramifications, for, as I
have before said, the heaviest part of taxation is that
which falls in increased prices" (1879, rpt. 1958, p.
434).
Turning to taxation levied on the
value of land, George went on to say:
For this simple device of placing
all taxes on the value of land would be in effect putting
up the land at auction to whosoever would pay the highest
rent to the state. The demand for land fixes its value,
and hence, if taxes were placed so as very nearly to
consume that value, the man who wished to hold land
without using it would have to pay very nearly what it
would be worth to anyone who wanted to use
it.
And it must be remembered that this
would apply, not merely to agricultural land, but to all
land. Mineral land would be thrown open to use, just as
agricultural land; and in the heart of a city no one
could afford to keep land from its most profitable use,
or on the outskirts to demand more for it than the use to
which it could at the time be put would warrant.
Everywhere that land had attained a value, taxation,
instead of operating, as now, as a fine upon improvement,
would operate to force improvement (1879, rpt. 1958, p.
437).
A few pages before this he had told
us that, "It is sufficiently evident that with regard to
production, the tax upon the value of land is the best tax
that can be imposed. Tax manufactures, and the effect is to
check manufacturing; tax improvements, and the effect is to
lessen improvement; tax commerce, and the effect is to
prevent exchange; tax capital, and the effect is to drive
it away. But the whole value of land may be taken in
taxation, and the only effect will be to stimulate
industry, to open new opportunities to capital, and to
increase the production of wealth" (1879, rpt. 1958, p.
414).
In other words, according to George,
taxation of products checks production, whereas taxation of
land values stimulates production.
...
The Ethics of Taxation
It was but a short step from the ethics of
property to the ethics of taxation. George's position
here was that as labor and capital rightfully and
unconditionally own what they produce, no one can
rightfully appropriate any of their earnings; nor can the
State. On the other hand, land value is always a socially
created value, never the result of action by the owner of
the land. Therefore this is a value that must be taken by
society; otherwise, those who comprise the social whole
are deprived of what is rightfully theirs. Furthermore,
to charge the owner for this value, in the form of
taxation, is only to collect from him the precise value
of the benefit he receives from society.
As to the justice of taxes on
products, George spoke of "...all taxes now levied on the
products and processes of industry -- which taxes, since
they take from the earnings of labor, we hold to be
infringements of the right of property."
Of the justice of
taxes on land values, he said, "Adam Smith speaks of
incomes as 'enjoyed under the protection of the state'; and
this is the ground upon which the equal taxation of all
species of property is commonly insisted upon -- that it is
equally protected by the state. The basis of this idea is
evidently that the enjoyment of property is made possible
by the state -- that there is a value created and
maintained by the community, which is justly called upon to
meet community expenses. Now of what values is this true?
Only of the value of land. This is a value that does not
arise until a community is formed, and that, unlike other
values, grows with the growth of the community. It exists
only as the community exists. Scatter again the largest
community, and land, now so valuable, would have no value
at all. With every increase of population the value of land
rises; with every decrease it falls. ...
"The tax upon land values is,
therefore, the most just and equal of all taxes. It falls
only upon those who receive from society a peculiar and
valuable benefit, and upon them in proportion to the
benefit they receive. It is the taking by the community,
for the use of the community, that value which is the
creation of the community. It is the application the common
property to common uses." ... read the
whole article
Nic Tideman: The Ethics of Coercion
in Public Finance
Taxation began as extortion by
conquerors. Over the centuries, regimes that started as
tyrannies have evolved into democracies. The public sector
has evolved from an apparatus for implementing the will of
despots into a mechanism for carrying out democratic
decisions. But public finance continues to rely on the
power of tax collectors, developed under early tyrants, to
coerce citizen to pay taxes. The wrath that citizens feel
toward tax collectors is probably the strongest
antagonistic feeling that citizens have toward a
governmental institution. Nevertheless, few economists
question the need for continued reliance on coercion to
collect public revenues in democracies.
How do we justify coercion?
Legislators and bureaucrats who devise coercive tax
collection rarely bother to address the question. Nor do
interest groups that promote expansions of the public
sector, with their inevitable accompaniment of higher
coercively collected taxes. Thus coercive tax collection
has every appearance of a power play against the weak by
those who have the strength to get away with
it.
We need to reexamine our acceptance
of coercion in public finance. If we are going to continue
to rely on coercion, we need to develop a consensus about
the framework that justifies it.
This paper begins with a definition of
justice and a taxonomy of theories that might be used to
justify coercion in public finance. I argue that theories
based on Conservatism, Contractarianism, Utilitarianism, or
Libertarianismall have value in some circumstances, but not
for justifying the use of power to extract resources from
people. None of these theories are
consistent with what we ought to understand justice to be,
because they do not accept the equal standing of all
persons in defining what is good. A theory of
justice that does accept the equal standing of all persons
in defining what is good is Liberalism as elucidated by
Bruce Ackerman (1980).
To oblige people to pay taxes while
satisfying the limitations that Liberalism sets on the use
of power, three conditions must be met:
1. People must be free to emigrate to any
jurisdiction that will accept them.
2. If the fraction of natural opportunities claimed by a
jurisdiction exceeds the fraction of population in the
jurisdiction, the jurisdiction must compensate those who
would otherwise be accorded smaller-than-average shares
of natural opportunities.
3. Sub-units of jurisdictions must be allowed to secede,
provided that they are willing to pay appropriate
costs.
What is Justice?
Begin with what justice is not. Justice is the
antithesis of might-makes-right. A powerful person might
say, "This is just because I say it is just, and if you
voice any disagreement I will silence you," and he might
have the power to make his threat stick. However, he
would be misusing language.
Justice entails the recognition by
those who have power that the use of power ought to be
constrained by principles whose relevance does not depend
on the views of those with power.
Justice is well represented by the
classical figure of the blindfolded goddess, with scales
lifted up in one hand and a sword in the other. The scales
convey the idea of equal division. The blindfold represents
complete impartiality in determinations of what constitutes
equal division. The sword says that there will be power to
ensure that the determinations of justice are carried out.
In other words,
Justice is the evenhanded adjudication of
conflicting claims, backed by the threat of
force.
To achieve the impartiality that
justice requires, we generally insist that the person
making a judicial determination have no personal interest
in the matter being decided. The maxim that no person
should be the judge of his own case is offered repeatedly
in classical discussions of justice. But in the most
fundamental questions of justice, we have no choice but to
abandon this valuable rule. When it comes to determining
the foundations of justice, there are no disinterested
parties. When a person determines what we must all accord
to one another, he determines for himself as well as for
others. ...
One way to sidestep the lack of
disinterested parties to define justice is to identify
justice with tradition.
...
As valid as these claims for
tradition are, they are not sufficient to make tradition an
adequate source for justice. In some times and places,
tradition has given us slavery, serfdom, denial of voting
rights to women, and any number of other inequalities that
we have come to realize we cannot accept. While the
Conservative perspective is valuable for the insights it
provides into rationales for the status quo, its automatic
acceptance of tradition cannot guarantee the evenhandedness
that is essential in a theory of justice.
In rejecting tradition as a
fundamental source for justice, we must also reject the
ultimate authority of laws and constitutions as sources for
justice. Justice is the standard to which we hold laws and
constitutions; it is not defined by them.
...
A second common way of coping with
the lack of disinterested parties is through
Contractarianism. This is the axiom that it is just to
coerce people to abide by rules to which they would have
agreed before they knew how they would be personally
affected by the rules. ...
The most famous modern application of
Contractarianism is John Rawls' 1971 book, A Theory of Justice. Rawls argues that behind a
"veil of ignorance" regarding one's personal
characteristics, a person would want the rules that
maximized the well-being of the representative member of
the least advantaged class. To most economists, Rawls'
specification of what would concern people behind a veil
of ignorance sounds completely arbitrary and unfounded.
If people are going to be overwhelmingly concerned about
losing in the lottery of life, why would they focus on
the representative member of the least advantaged class
and not on the worst possible individual outcome? Why
would people be unwilling to trade a minute loss by the
least advantaged class for a substantial gain by the
second-least advantaged class?
John Harsanyi (1975) argues that
behind Rawls' veil of ignorance, people would not be
concerned exclusively with the well-being of the
representative member of the least advantaged class.
Rather, they would recognize that they had equal chances of
being all persons, and therefore, to maximize their
expected utility, they would choose the rules that
maximized the sum of individual utilities. The Buchanan and
Tullock framework is consistent with Harsanyi's
claim.
Another theory that applies the
Contractarian axiom is Ronald Dworkin's (1981) theory of
justice as equality of resources. Dworkin justifies an
income tax as the expression of an insurance policy that
people would desire before they knew their
talents.
The fact that people using the basic idea of
Contractarianism could come to conclusions as different
as those of Rawls and Harsanyi is a reflection of a
limitation of the axiom.
...
Utilitarian and Contractarian
theories of justice share the feature that they do not
acknowledge self-ownership. Under Utilitarianism, persons
are inputs into the generation of aggregate utility. Under
Contractarianism, persons might have owned themselves in
the contractual setting, but there they sold themselves.
The rights of real people are gone. Theories in these
classes can be contrasted with a class of theories that
justify power with direct responses to those who question
power, treating them as individuals who own themselves.
There are two theories in this class: Liberalism and
Libertarianism. The two theories share the idea of
self-ownership, the idea that each person is free to decide
the purpose of his or her life, provided that the rights
of others to do the same are
respected.
The fundamental difference between
Libertarianism and Liberalism concerns the basis for
claims to own things. ...
The Libertarian and Liberal theories both have
limitations in terms of efficiency. Acceptance of the
Libertarian theory promotes a land rush, in which people
waste resources doing the minimal work necessary to
establish claims to land, so that they can later sell it
to others. (Whoever burns down the most rain forest gets
the most land.) This first inefficiency is compounded by
a continuing inefficient use of land, arising from the
inability of people to manage all that they have claimed.
If the Liberal theory is accepted, an opposite
inefficiency occurs. There is no incentive for people to
seek to discover opportunities hidden in nature, because
whatever is discovered belongs equally to all.
...
The basic problem with the justice of
Libertarian theory is that it allows the first arrivers to
deprive those who come later of any natural opportunities
that it suits the first arrivers to claim and transform. To
permit this is inconsistent with the evenhandedness that
justice requires. ...
A Just Framework for Taxation
Consider how Ackerman's principle of Neutrality
constrains a person who wishes to levy taxes. How can
person say to others, "You must pay these taxes," without
violating Neutrality? One possibility is by permitting
emigration. If there were unclaimed land with natural
opportunities as good as those of existing nations, where
those who did not like existing nations could form their
own nations, then a right of emigration would make
taxation consistent with Neutrality. The person who
levied taxes would not be claiming more for himself than
he left for others. In fact, the best natural
opportunities are fully claimed. Still, a right of
emigration goes some of the way toward making taxation
just. It prevents at least the worst exploitation of
taxpayers.
When the most valuable natural
opportunities are fully appropriated, Neutrality requires
that any effort to induce people to accept an obligation to
pay taxes provide an alternative of leaving the tax-levying
jurisdiction while retaining a level of access to natural
opportunities that is no less than the per capita level
within the tax-levying jurisdiction. "Leaving" could mean
emigrating, or it could mean seceding.
The most straightforward way of
achieving equal access to natural opportunities for
emigrants is to recognize the requirements that Neutrality
places on relations among nations or their subunits with
respect to claims on natural opportunities. To guarantee
equal access to natural opportunities, governments must
acknowledge that their claims to natural opportunities,
that is, their claims to land and natural resources, are
just only if they are not disproportionate to the number of
persons making the claim.
If land were uniform in its economic
potential and there were no depletable natural resources,
the application of such a rule would be straightforward.
But land is not economically uniform and there are
depletable natural resources, so the problem of equal
access is conceptually more difficult.
To consider a simple case first,
suppose that there is no disagreement about the relative
value of land in different places and that there are no
depletable natural resources. Equal access to natural
opportunities is satisfied if the ratio of aggregate land
rent to population is the same in all jurisdictions. Equal
access is also satisfied if there is a set of transfer
payments among jurisdictions, such that the ratio of the
sum of aggregate land rent and net transfers received to
population is the same in all jurisdictions.
The rent of land in these formulas is
not calculated on a site-by-site basis, but rather on an
aggregate basis, under the assumption that there are no
man-made improvements in the territory being evaluated.
Thus, in asking whether the United States was claiming more
than its share of natural opportunities, one would ask what
the rental value of the territory occupied by the U.S.
would be if it were completely devoid of human improvements
and human habitation, and the only bidders were other
nations or their citizens. A similar calculation would be
made for every other nation. Of course there can be no
guarantee of agreement about such valuations, but agreement
on the need to make such estimates and to try to reach
consensus on their magnitudes would constitute enormous
progress in global justice.
Next, suppose that there are depletable natural
resources. This raises two new issues: appropriate
depletion and intergenerational equity. Appropriate
depletion is depletion on a path that maximizes the
present value of net returns from using a resource.
... Read
the whole article
Bill Batt: Stemming
Sprawl: The Fiscal Approach
In addition, a tax on site value (that is, the
collection of economic rent) restores moral principle to
tax theory. By collecting rent on that value that is
generated by the collective activity of the community, it
offers the opportunity to relieve tax burdens on value
that is generated by individual effort. Put another way,
any value that individuals create by their own bodies and
minds is left for them to keep; that which is socially
created value is recovered by the community to pay for
its collective purposes. "Tax what you take, not what you
make," is one way to say it. "Tax bads, not goods," or
"Tax waste, not work," is another way. At the heart of
this approach is a very profound message: The earth is
the common heritage of humanity; it belongs to everyone.
That which grows out of our own personal efforts and
ingenuity is ours to keep, and no part of it should be
subject to taxation.[37] Taxes on
income, sales, savings, structures, and things that come
from the sweat of our brow can be replaced by taxes on
land rent — which, when all forms of it are
included, is revenue source that can fully pay for the
full services of government and is nonetheless
essentially burden-less to taxpayers.[38] What
economists call the "excess burden" or "deadweight loss"
of the current tax structure — by many calculations
at least 25 percent[39] — is
reduced to zero, thereby increasing our collective
productivity by that amount That effectively makes us all
20 percent wealthier. ... read the whole article
Bill Batt: The
Compatibility of Georgist Economics and Ecological
Economics
As with all nineteenth century moral
philosophers, Henry George subscribed to a belief in
natural law. The natural order of things as he saw it
required that land be held in usufruct and that rent from
such should be returned to society. The theory was
inspired by his deeply religious roots and grounded in
his reading of the prominent thinkers that predated him.
The natural order was also a moral order, and the failure
to comply with the order of nature and society as he saw
it was a perversion of justice. The fruits of the land
belonged to everyone, just as the fruits of one’s
own labor were uniquely one’s own. Since one owned
one’s body, one was entitled to keep the product of
one’s physical efforts. Society had no more right
to confiscate the earnings of one’s sweat and brow
than it ought to leave in the hands of rich landowners
the rent that was everyone’s inherent birthright to
be shared. There were just and unjust taxes, and the only
just tax was that which grew out of rent, of the unearned
increment that visited certain land sites as windfall
gains because of the efforts and investments by the
community. Income and excise taxes were unjust and
confiscatory— even theft, as especially were
tariffs. Taxing or collecting land rent alone was the
means of ending poverty and restoring progress. Indeed
many Georgists reject use of the word tax entirely,
preferring instead to talk instead about rent collection.
There is even a lapel button Georgists use that says
“Abolish all taxes; collect ground rent
instead.” ...
There was another dimension to George’s
economic views as well. As Locke and later classical
economists argued, one owned the items with which one
“mixed his labor.” By extension one also
owned items which one purchased in trade from others who
had similarly created their wealth. Hence it was unjust and immoral for society to claim
any parts of the fruits of one’s own efforts in the
form of tariffs, sales taxes, and especially the income
tax. Of course, except for a short period during
the American Civil War, the American government had never
implemented an income tax. But Britain had, and there was
much discussion of a need for an income tax in the United
States; it was again instituted in this country in 1913.
... read
the whole article
Alanna Hartzok:
Who Would Jesus Tax? The Saga of Susan Pace Hamill's
Alabama Tax Crusade
A University of Alabama School of Law Professor has
asked God's forgiveness for the years she lived in the
sin of ignorance about tax injustice. Susan Pace Hamill,
a tax expert, business consultant, and dedicated United
Methodist church goer, thought there was a misprint when
she first read that personal incomes as low as $4,600 for
a family of four were being taxed by the state, while
timber owners holding 71% of the land of Alabama were
paying less than $1 per acre in property taxes. Two hours
later she found out there had been no mistake and that
Alabama has the most regressive tax code in the country.
Her righteous rage spawned a tax crusade that has
reverberated onto the national scene.
"As somebody who knows a lot about taxes, I could not
have imagined a design of a tax structure this bad," she
said in a Tuscaloosa Newsstory last February.
"The state's tax code is really horribly unjust and has
no moral, ethical leg to stand on. Period."
Alabamians with incomes under $13,000 pay 10.9 percent of
their incomes in state and local taxes while those who
make over $229,000 pay just 4.1 percent. Commercial
property owners pay more than 50 percent of property
taxes, with homes approaching one-third. Alabama's sales
taxes are among the highest in the nation, up to 10
percent in some areas, and do not exempt even the most
basic necessities such as food. The state's 1901
constitution was written primarily by large landholders
to secure their economic interests, consequently property
taxes are extremely light on their holdings. ...
While resoundingly condemning the current system (she
uses words like "horrific" and "monstrous injustice")
Hamill clearly articulates a tax reform approach which
shifts taxes off of low wage earners and onto large land
owners. Through a combination of her own reasoning,
caring heart, and inherent sense of justice and a
thorough investigation of Judeo-Christian ethics, Hamill
arrived at a tax policy approach which bears remarkable
similarities to the economic justice crusades of 19th
century reformer, Henry George. ...
read the whole article
Charles T. Root — Not a Single Tax! (1925)
... let us lay down and briefly defend the proposition
that —
Taxation as a means of meeting the proper
expenses of government is oppressive, unjust,
inexpedient and unnecessary.
This proposition will strike a good many readers as
absurd, but all must at least recognize the timeliness of
the topic and the importance of any contribution to the
discussion of a subject which is agitating the whole
civilized world, for the methods, subjects and amounts of
taxation are among the pressing problems of every
country.
The most obvious question which arises in the mind of
anyone who reads for the first time the proposition above
laid down is this:
"If taxation is unnecessary, what is to take its
place? Government and its functions are increasingly
expensive. They require a lot of money. Where is it to
come from?" The answer may be placed in the form of a
second proposition:
Every community, whatever its political name and
extent — village, city, state or province or nation
— has its own normal, unfailing income, growing
with the growth of the community and always adequate to
meet necessary governmental expenditure.
To explain: Every community has an indefeasible
original right to the land on which it exists, and to all
the natural, unmodified properties and advantages of that
particular area of the earth's surface. To this land in
its natural state, undrained, unfenced, unfertilized,
unplanted and unoccupied, including its waters, its
contents and its location, every individual in the
community (which may consist of any political unit
selected) has an equal right, while all the individuals
together have a joint right to the value for use which
society has conferred upon these natural advantages.
This value for use is known as "Land Value," or by the
not particularly descriptive but generally adopted name
of "Economic Rent."
Briefly defined the land value or economic rent of any
piece of ground is the largest annual amount voluntarily
offered for the exclusive use of that ground, or of an
equivalent parcel, independent of improvements thereon.
Every holder or user of land pays economic rent, but he
now pays most of it to the wrong party. The aggregate
economic rent of the territory occupied by any political
unit is, as has been stated above, always sufficient,
usually more than sufficient, for the legitimate expenses
of the government of that unit. As also stated above, the
economic rent belongs to the community, and not to
individual landowners.
On the other hand, the result of every utilization or
enhancement of the natural advantages of land (such as
farm profits, the rent and selling value of buildings and
other improvements), when accomplished by an individual,
belongs wholly to that individual, and should never, and
need never, be taken from him by taxation. ...
Under the normal system which this article advocates,
the user of land would pay substantially the same
economic rent as now, for the reason that economic rent
is fixed by the payer and not by the payee; but it would
be paid to the credit of the community instead of for the
benefit of the individual landowner. And the economic
rent is all the land user would have to pay; no taxes on
industry or personal product and no other forced
contribution for governmental purposes.
It follows that, under the normal system, the holder
of unimproved land would usually contribute more than at
present toward the expenses of government, while the
holder of well improved property would contribute, in
most instances, less than the total of his present
taxes.
To illustrate simply, let us suppose a state which has
never parted with its natural income but is supported by
its own economic rent. ...
This principle of economic rent applies to all the
users of land, including mining, use of waterpower, and
rights of way over or under its surface. Had this
principle always been recognized, and the economic rent
always been retained by the community, taxation would
never have been heard of. When the economic rent is
reclaimed by the community, the need of taxation will
disappear.
Let us roughly restate the proposition: All members of
the community having a joint right to the income which
the social advantages of the land will command, they are
all partners in this income.
Therefore, when one of their number wishes to take for
his private use a parcel of this land, he should buy out
his partners, i.e., the rest of the community, by paying
regularly into the common treasury the economic rent of
that parcel, instead of paying, as at present, the
purchase price, i.e., the right to collect the economic
rent, in a lump, to some other individual who has no more
original right to it than himself.
But before this time the reader, unless he has given
previous attention to the subject, is full of objections
to the above doctrine: "How about the law?" he is asking.
"Hasn't a man the right to buy a piece of land as cheaply
as he can, to do what he pleases with it, and hold on to
it till he gets ready to sell?" The answer is that at
present he certainly has this statutory right, which has
been so long and so universally recognized that most
people suppose it to be not only a legal, but a real or
equitable right. A shrewd man, foreseeing the direction
of growth of population in a city, for example, can buy a
well-located block at a moderate figure from some less
far-seeing owner, can let it grow up to weeds, fence it
off against all comers and give it no further attention
except to pay the very small tax usually imposed upon
vacant land.
Meantime the increasing community builds up all around
it with homes, banks, stores, churches, schools, paving
and lighting the streets, giving police and fire
protection, etc., and at last comes to need this block so
urgently that the owner is fairly begged to sell it, at
three or ten or fifty times what it cost him. Quite often
the purchaser at this enormous advance is the very
community which has through its presence and the
expenditure of its taxes created practically the whole
value of the land in question!
It was said above that an individual has a statutory
right to pursue this very common course. That was an
error. The statement should have been that he has a
statutory wrong; for no disinterested person can follow
the course of land speculation as almost universally
practiced, without feeling its rank injustice.
How did so evident a wrong become so firmly established?
...
he landlords, being also the lawmakers, have seen to
it that their tenure of this easy money should not be
disturbed, but on the contrary have so buttressed it with
centuries of legislation, precedents, and judicial
decisions, that any proposition to hark back to the terms
of the original bargain, whereby the owners of the land
agreed to pay the expenses of the government, is now
denounced as anarchy and sacrilege.
Lapse of time, however, never can transform wrong into
right, nor can a buyer acquire any better title than the
seller possessed. The economic rent belongs to the
community, which can and will begin to reclaim it as soon
as the voters thoroughly awake to the facts and the right
and wrong of the matter, which are not hard to grasp when
the subject is presented in its simplest form.
An illustration has already been given of the case of
a piece of farm land. Let us take an example in a large
city. Let us take a corner lot centrally located in New
York City, the title to which lot is held by, say, Mr.
John William Rhinelastor. This lot was a part of an old
Dutch farm, and is an heirloom. It did not cost the
present owner anything, nor his father nor his
grandfather. There is a little old building on it, which
has always been rented at a figure ten times as large as
the taxes imposed, so that the owner has been handsomely
subsidized each year for storing his title-deeds during a
period of the city's growth in which the increase in
population and the expenditure of public money in that
neighborhood have raised the value of this corner
location to, say, two hundred times its early value.
...
Now suppose this $20,000 and all the rest of this same
community product — i.e., the site or location rent
of its ground — were paid every year to its
rightful owner, the treasurer of New York City, what
would become of taxation, with its inseparable retinue,
Fraud, Evasion, Perjury, Inequality, and an all-pervading
public sense of injustice?
An authority on municipal taxation estimates the
present economic rent of the land embraced in the City of
New York at from $350,000,000 to $400,000,000. Assuming
the lesser of these figures and adding the receipts from
licenses, fees and fines, New York City should receive,
of her own income, enough to pay all her own legitimate
bills, to make her proper contributions to county and
state and build a new subway or its equivalent every
year.
And this with nobody paying a dollar of taxes, or, if
we except the fines, a dollar that he was not ready and
glad to pay for his own advantage.
We repeat, this is not taxation; but for the sake of
those who cannot grasp the idea of public revenue without
taxation, let us state the matter in their own
language.
Think of a tax which both assesses itself and collects
itself, which burdens no one, which is paid voluntarily,
and only by those who do so for their own profit or other
advantage. Compare this with our present system of taxes,
which everyone despises, which can be collected in full
only from the very scrupulous and from the helpless, from
trust funds of widows and orphans, or from estates which
lie naked before the tax gatherer on the records of
court; a system which drives men of property from state
to state and town to town in flight from the assessor,
and well-nigh forces many worthy citizens to practices of
evasion which must make it hard for them to look into
their own mirrors during the season for "Correction of
Assessments;" there can be but one verdict upon such
comparison.
But again the voice of the objector is heard, possibly
to this effect: "This plan may be all right for the
community, but how about poor Mr. Rhinelastor?"
...
Reclaim for the community its natural income, making
it expensive either to keep needed land vacant or to
withhold it from the ready and willing to improve it to
the full extent of its possibilities.
Does it require severe intellectual effort to foresee
the results? Better and better houses, apartments,
tenements, offices and stores, more employment for labor
in all enterprises now held back by the shadow of the
tax-gatherer, an end of all tax-lying, tax-evasion and
tax-injustice, and withal, a public revenue adequate to
all real public needs.
What a contrast to the existing plan of pouring public
money into the laps of individual landowners ...
Henry George gave the first impulse, and his followers
of the Single Tax have continued the good work. There is
one objection, however, to the statement of their case by
the Single Taxers: the nature of this objection is
indicated by their name. Most persons will infer that,
under their proposal, whatever portion of the economic
rent is taken by the community is taken as a tax on the
land.
This seems to the present writer to show a
misconception of the nature of the transaction, and one
which tends to retard the cause which is being advocated.
The amount of economic rent which is taken by the
community for public purposes is not a tax paid by the
land-holder, but whatever amount of such rent is left in
his hands is a gift to him by the community, or else is
the compensation which the community allows him for
acting as its agent and collector in the matter of
economic rent.
This is an important distinction which is necessary to
make the facts and the relations clear. It is also highly
expedient. Taxation and the idea behind it are abhorrent
to men. As a result of long experience the very word
Taxation connotes to them injustice, oppression, and
antagonism between the individual and the community. To
the mass "The Single Tax" means simply rolling into one
the manifold injustices and oppressions of the present
complex system. Only slow headway can be made by a
proposition which at first sight seems to promise merely
to shift the burden from one shoulder to the other.
But make it plain to the wayfaring man that taxation
can be abolished and will be abolished whenever the
voters of any political unit so decree, and a force of
hope and purpose will be liberated which must bring
nearer the time when the things that are the community's
will be rendered to it, and the things which are the
individual's will be left in his unmolested possession.
The watchword of our friends the Georgeites is "A Single
Tax." The true slogan is "Not a Single Tax!"; and the
triumph of the cause behind that slogan would cut more of
the taproots of poverty, vice and social unrest than any
other progressive step which is a legislative
possibility. read the
whole article
|
To share this page with a friend:
right click, choose "send," and add your
comments.
|
|
Red links have not been
visited; .
Green links are pages you've seen
|
Essential Documents pertinent
to this theme:
|
|