Margin of Production
also known as the margin of cultivation
Thomas Flavin, writing in The
Iconoclast, 1897
Now, it is quite true that all taxes of whatever
nature are paid out of the products of labor. But must
they be for that reason a tax on labor products. Let us
see.
I suppose you won't deny that a unit of labor applies
to different kinds of land will give very different
results. Suppose that a unit of labor produces on A's
land 4, on B's 3, on C's 2 and on D's 1. A's land is the
most, and D's is the least, productive land in use in the
community to which they belong. B's and C's represent
intermediate grades. Suppose each occupies the best land
that was open to him when he entered into possession.
Now, B, and C, and D have just as good a right to the use
of the best land as A had.
Manifestly then, if this be the whole story, there
cannot be equality of opportunity where a unit of labor
produces such different results, all other things being
equal except the land.
How is this equality to be secured? There is but one
possible way. Each must surrender for the common use of
all, himself included, whatever advantages accrues to him
from the possession of land superior to that which falls
to the lot of him who occupies the poorest.
In the case stated, what the unit of labor produces
for D, is what it should produce for A, B and C, if these
are not to have an advantage of natural opportunity over
D.
Hence equity is secured when A pays 3, B, 2 and C, 1
into a common fund for the common use of all — to
be expended, say in digging a well, making a road or
bridge, building a school, or other public utility.
Is it not manifest that here the tax which A, B and C
pay into a common fund, and from which D is exempt, is
not a tax on their labor products (though paid out of
them) but a tax on the superior advantage which they
enjoy over D, and to which D has just as good a right as
any of them.
The result of this arrangement is that each takes up
as much of the best land open to him as he can put to
gainful use, and what he cannot so use he leaves open for
the next. Moreover, he is at no disadvantage with the
rest who have come in ahead of him, for they provide for
him, in proportion to their respective advantages, those
public utilities which invariably arise wherever men live
in communities. Of course he will in turn hold to those
who come later the same relation that those who came
earlier held to him.
Suppose now that taxes had been levied on labor
products instead of land; all that any land-holder would
have to do to avoid the tax is to produce little or
nothing. He could just squat on his land, neither using
it himself nor letting others use it, but he would not
stop at this, for he would grab to the last acre all that
he could possibly get hold of. Each of the others would
do the same in turn, with the sure result that by and by,
E, F and G would find no land left for them on which they
might make a living.
So they would have to hire their labor to those who
had already monopolized the land, or else buy or rent a
piece of land from them. Behold now the devil of
landlordism getting his hoof on God's handiwork! Exit
justice, freedom, social peace and plenty. Enter robbery,
slavery, social discontent, consuming grief, riotous but
unearned wealth, degrading pauperism, crime breeding,
want, the beggar's whine, and the tyrant's iron heel.
And how did it all come about? By the simple
expedient of taxing labor products in order that precious
landlordism might laugh and grow fat on the bovine
stupidity of the community that contributes its own land
values toward its own enslavement!
And yet men vacuously ask, "What difference does it
make?"
O tempora! O mores! To be as plain as is necessary, it
makes this four-fold difference.
- First, it robs the community of its land
values;
- second, it robs labor of its wages in the name of
taxation;
- third, it sustains and fosters landlordism, a most
conspicuously damnable difference;
- fourth, it exhibits willing workers in enforced
idleness; beholding their families in want on the one
hand, and unused land that would yield them abundance
on the other.
This last is a difference that cries to heaven for
vengeance, and if it does not always cry in vain, will W.
C. Brann be able to draw his robe close around him and
with a good conscience exclaim, "It's none of my fault; I
am not my brother's keeper."
Mason Gaffney: Full Employment,
Growth And Progress On A Small Planet: Relieving Poverty
While Healing The Earth
Effect of artificial scarcity on marginal
returns to labor and capital. Underuse of better
lands forces labor and capital (which is mobile, like
labor) to resort to worse or “marginal”
lands, thus scattering and spreading out settlement,
raising aggregate demands on land, and wasting capital
(George, 1879). This lowering of the “margin of
production” lowers the marginal productivity of
labor and capital, and hence their economic rewards,
tilting the distribution of income in favor of
landowners, creating an illusion of overpopulation
(Malthus), and lack of investment outlets (Marx, Keynes,
Hobson et al.). Read the whole
article
Karl Williams: Social
Justice In Australia: INTERMEDIATE KIT
We've just seen how returns from land are, by
nature, monopolistic and, by rights, should be returned
to the community. But how do we calculate this
amount?
WHO GETS THE
COCONUTS?
It's perhaps best illustrated by the Robinson
Crusoe scenario, where he finds himself alone on a desert
island. Rob naturally settles on the best available land
which, for argument's sake, can produce 20 coconuts per
acre per month. Along comes Man Friday, who gets the
second-best land producing 18 coconuts per acre. This
best, freely-available land of Friday is called the
marginal land and, as we'll see, determines both the
level of wages and that of rent.
For how much could Rob rent out his land - 2
coconuts or 20 coconuts per acre? Friday would only be
prepared to pay 2, because he can already get 18 from
his. So here's our first definition, that of the Law of
Rent: The application of labour and capital equipment
being equal, the rent of land is determined by the
difference between the value of its produce and that of
the least productive land in use. So if Man Saturday
comes along (the next day?!) and finds that the best
available land can only produce 15 coconuts per acre, Rob
could rent his land out to Saturday for 5 coconuts per
acre, and Friday for 2.
What then determines the level of
wages? When Friday came along and could work land
yielding 18 coconuts per acre in a month, then he
wouldn't accept wages offered by Rob for less than 18
coconuts. But when Saturday arrived, suddenly Friday
could only command 15 per month, because Rob knows that
the going rate (that applicable to Saturday at the
margin) is only 15. So here we have the Law of Wages,
which is the corollary of the law of rent: Wages are the
reward that labour can obtain on marginal land, i.e. the
most productive land available to it without paying
rent.
Of course it all gets more complicated by
technology, trade unions, immigration, the existence of a
pool of unemployed, personal preferences, levels of
education etc., but these strong underlying laws always
hold. But let's now tie up the factors of production.
Rent is the return to land, wages are the return to
labour, and interest is the return to capital. The law of
interest can be stated thus: Interest is the return that
the use of capital equipment can obtain on marginal land,
i.e. the most productive land available to it without
paying rent.
PROGRESS AND POVERTY, SIDE BY
SIDE
So here's the alarming paradox of progress
marching side by side with poverty. Those who have
grabbed the best land get richer and richer (from
increasing rent) while the tenants and wage-earners get
poorer and poorer for having to accept lower and lower
wages as the margin is pushed out to less productive
land). Henry George, in his classic Progress
and Poverty drove home this point, but took about 600
pages to deal with all the complications and fine details
not examined here. It's no wonder that the unmasking of
this great paradox - the title of his book - hit the 19th
century world like a great revelation. And it's no wonder
that vested interests, through the neoclassical economics
that they fostered, knew they had to shut him up. And, by
successfully silencing him, it's no wonder that, despite
all efforts, increasing and ever more alarming
disparities of wealth are the norm
world-wide.
But, anyway, how many coconut-basketsful of LVT
should we collect? Chuck away all those calculators,
guys, for the answer is simple: Collect
the rent, the whole rent, and nothing but the
rent. Assuming that everyone has to do the same
amount of work to produce their differing yields of
coconuts, when Friday came along then we'd collect 2
coconuts per acre from Rob. This would leave 18 coconuts
in each of their hands, and 2 coconuts of rent or LVT
collected. When Saturday arrived we'd collect 5 from Rob
and 3 from Friday, which would leave 15 coconuts in
everyone's hands and 8 coconuts of rent collected.
Result: everybody effectively shares equally in the
bounty of Our One Earth, and we have a natural,
non-punitive form of revenue raising with which to fund
infrastructure.
We've already seen how speculators can presently
hold on to idle parcels of land, waiting for unearned
increases in their value to accrue to them. But here's another curse of land speculation: by
locking up productive land, it forces newcomers out to
less productive land. By "pushing back the margin", the
evil of speculation simultaneously raises rents and
lowers wages. LVT makes it impossible for speculators to
enjoy unearned income. ...
Read the entire article
Louis Post: Outlines
of Louis F. Post's Lectures, with Illustrative Notes and
Charts (1894)
b. Normal Effect of Social Progress upon
Wages and Rent
In the foregoing charts the effect of social growth is
ignored, it being assumed that the given expenditure of
labor force does not become more productive.93 Let us now
try to illustrate that effect, upon the supposition that
social growth increases the productive power of the given
expenditure of labor force as applied to the first closed
space, to 100; as applied to the second, to 50; as
applied to the third, to 10; as applied to the fourth, to
3, and as applied to the open space, to 1. 94 If there
were no increased demand for land the chart would then be
like this:
93. "The effect of increasing population
upon the distribution of wealth is to increase rent ..
. in two ways: First, By lowering the margin of
cultivation. Second, By bringing out in land special
capabilities otherwise latent, and by attaching special
capabilities to particular lands.
"I am disposed to think that the latter
mode, to which little attention has been given by
political economists, is really the more important."
— Progress and Poverty, book iv, ch. iii.
"When we have inquired what it is that
marks off land from those material things which we
regard as products of the land, we shall find that the
fundamental attribute of land is its extension. The
right to use a piece of land gives command over a
certain space — a certain part of the earth's
surface. The area of the earth is fixed; the geometric
relations in which any particular part of it stands to
other parts are fixed. Man has no control over them;
they are wholly unaffected by demand; they have no cost
of production; there is no supply price at which they
can be produced.
"The use of a certain area of the
earth's surface is a primary condition of anything that
man can do; it gives him room for his own actions, with
the enjoyment of the heat and the light, the air and
the rain which nature assigns to that area; and it
determines his distance from, and in great measure his
relations to, other things and other persons. We shall
find that it is this property of land, which, though as
yet insufficient prominence has been given to it, is
the ultimate cause of the distinction which all writers
are compelled to make between land and other things."
— Marshall's Prin., book iv, ch. ii, sec. i.
94. Of course social growth does not go
on in this regular way; the charts are merely
illustrative. They are intended to illustrate the
universal fact that as any land becomes a center of
trade or other social relationship its value rises.
...
d. Effect of Confiscating Rent to Private
Use.
By giving Rent to individuals society ignores this
most just law, 99 thereby creating social disorder and
inviting social disease. Upon society alone, therefore,
and not upon divine Providence which has provided
bountifully, nor upon the disinherited poor, rests the
responsibility for poverty and fear of poverty.
99. "Whatever dispute arouses the
passions of men, the conflict is sure to rage, not so
much as to the question 'Is it wise?' as to the
question 'Is it right?'
"This tendency of popular discussions to
take an ethical form has a cause. It springs from a law
of the human mind; it rests upon a vague and
instinctive recognition of what is probably the deepest
truth we can grasp. That alone is wise which is just;
that alone is enduring which is right. In the narrow
scale of individual actions and individual life this
truth may be often obscured, but in the wider field of
national life it everywhere stands out.
"I bow to this arbitrament, and accept
this test." — Progress and Poverty, book vii, ch.
i.
The reader who has been deceived into
believing that Mr. George's proposition is in any
respect unjust, will find profit in a perusal of the
entire chapter from which the foregoing extract is
taken.
Let us try to trace the connection by means of a
chart, beginning with the white spaces on page 68. As
before, the first-comers take possession of the best
land. But instead of leaving for others what they do not
themselves need for use, as in the previous
illustrations, they appropriate the whole space, using
only part, but claiming ownership of the rest. We may
distinguish the used part with red color, and that which
is appropriated without use with blue. Thus: [chart]
But what motive is there for appropriating more of the
space than is used? Simply that the appropriators may
secure the pecuniary benefit of future social growth.
What will enable them to secure that? Our system of
confiscating Rent from the community that earns it, and
giving it to land-owners who, as such, earn
nothing.100
100. It is reported from Iowa that a few
years ago a workman in that State saw a meteorite fall,
and. securing possession of it after much digging, he
was offered $105 by a college for his "find." But the
owner of the land on which the meteorite fell claimed
the money, and the two went to law about it. After an
appeal to the highest court of the State, it was
finally decided that neither by right of discovery, nor
by right of labor, could the workman have the money,
because the title to the meteorite was in the man who
owned the land upon which it fell.
Observe the effect now upon Rent and Wages. When other
men come, instead of finding half of the best land still
common and free, as in the corresponding chart on page
68, they find all of it owned, and are obliged either to
go upon poorer land or to buy or rent from owners of the
best. How much will they pay for the best? Not more than
1, if they want it for use and not to hold for a higher
price in the future, for that represents the full
difference between its productiveness and the
productiveness of the next best. But if the first-comers,
reasoning that the next best land will soon be scarce and
theirs will then rise in value, refuse to sell or to rent
at that valuation, the newcomers must resort to land of
the second grade, though the best be as yet only partly
used. Consequently land of the first grade commands Rent
before it otherwise would.
As the sellers' price, under these circumstances, is
arbitrary it cannot be stated in the chart; but the
buyers' price is limited by the superiority of the best
land over that which can be had for nothing, and the
chart may be made to show it: [chart]
And now, owing to the success of the appropriators of
the best land in securing more than their fellows for the
same expenditure of labor force, a rush is made for
unappropriated land. It is not to use it that it is
wanted, but to enable its appropriators to put Rent into
their own pockets as soon as growing demand for land
makes it valuable.101 We may, for illustration, suppose
that all the remainder of the second space and the whole
of the third are thus appropriated, and note the effect:
[chart]
At this point Rent does not increase nor Wages fall,
because there is no increased demand for land for use.
The holding of inferior land for higher prices, when
demand for use is at a standstill, is like owning lots in
the moon — entertaining, perhaps, but not
profitable. But let more land be needed for use, and
matters promptly assume a different appearance. The new
labor must either go to the space that yields but 1, or
buy or rent from owners of better grades, or hire out.
The effect would be the same in any case. Nobody for the
given expenditure of labor force would get more than 1;
the surplus of products would go to landowners as Rent,
either directly in rent payments, or indirectly through
lower Wages. Thus: [chart]
101. The text speaks of Rent only as a
periodical or continuous payment — what would be
called "ground rent." But actual or potential Rent may
always be, and frequently is, capitalized for the
purpose of selling the right to enjoy it, and it is to
selling value that we usually refer when dealing in
land.
Land which has the power of yielding
Rent to its owner will have a selling value, whether it
be used or not, and whether Rent is actually derived
from it or not. This selling value will be the
capitalization of its present or prospective power of
producing Rent. In fact, much the larger proportion of
laud that has a selling value is wholly or partly
unused, producing no Rent at all, or less than it would
if fully used. This condition is expressed in the chart
by the blue color.
"The capitalized value of land is the
actuarial 'discounted' value of all the net incomes
which it is likely to afford, allowance being made on
the one hand for all incidental expenses, including
those of collecting the rents, and on the other for its
mineral wealth, its capabilities of development for any
kind of business, and its advantages, material, social,
and aesthetic, for the purposes of residence." —
Marshall's Prin., book vi, ch. ix, sec. 9.
"The value of land is commonly expressed
as a certain number of times the current money rental,
or in other words, a certain 'number of years'
purchase' of that rental; and other things being equal,
it will be the higher the more important these direct
gratifications are, as well as the greater the chance
that they and the money income afforded by the land
will rise." — Id., note.
"Value . . . means not utility, not any
quality inhering in the thing itself, but a quality
which gives to the possession of a thing the power of
obtaining other things, in return for it or for its
use. . . Value in this sense — the usual sense
— is purely relative. It exists from and is
measured by the power of obtaining things for things by
exchanging them. . . Utility is necessary to value, for
nothing can be valuable unless it has the quality of
gratifying some physical or mental desire of man,
though it be but a fancy or whim. But utility of itself
does not give value. . . If we ask ourselves the reason
of . . . variations in . . . value . . . we see that
things having some form of utility or desirability, are
valuable or not valuable, as they are hard or easy to
get. And if we ask further, we may see that with most
of the things that have value this difficulty or ease
of getting them, which determines value, depends on the
amount of labor which must be expended in producing
them ; i.e., bringing them into the place, form and
condition in which they are desired. . . Value is
simply an expression of the labor required for the
production of such a thing. But there are some things
as to which this is not so clear. Land is not produced
by labor, yet land, irrespective of any improvements
that labor has made on it, often has value. . . Yet a
little examination will show that such facts are but
exemplifications of the general principle, just as the
rise of a balloon and the fall of a stone both
exemplify the universal law of gravitation. . . The
value of everything produced by labor, from a pound of
chalk or a paper of pins to the elaborate structure and
appurtenances of a first-class ocean steamer, is
resolvable on analysis into an equivalent of the labor
required to produce such a thing in form and place;
while the value of things not produced by labor, but
nevertheless susceptible of ownership, is in the same
way resolvable into an equivalent of the labor which
the ownership of such a thing enables the owner to
obtain or save." —
Perplexed Philosopher, ch. v.
The figure 1 in parenthesis, as an item of Rent,
indicates potential Rent. Labor would give that much for
the privilege of using the space, but the owners hold out
for better terms; therefore neither Rent nor Wages is
actually produced, though but for this both might be.
In this chart, notwithstanding that but little space
is used, indicated with red, Wages are reduced to the
same low point by the mere appropriation of space,
indicated with blue, that they would reach if all the
space above the poorest were fully used. It thereby
appears that under a system which confiscates Rent to
private uses, the demand for land for speculative
purposes becomes so great that Wages fall to a minimum
long before they would if land were appropriated only for
use.
In illustrating the effect of confiscating Rent to
private use we have as yet ignored the element of social
growth. Let us now assume as before (page 73), that
social growth increases the productive power of the given
expenditure of labor force to 100 when applied to the
best land, 50 when applied to the next best, 10 to the
next, 3 to the next, and 1 to the poorest. Labor would
not be benefited now, as it appeared to be when on page
73 we illustrated the appropriation of land for use only,
although much less land is actually used. The prizes
which expectation of future social growth dangles before
men as the rewards of owning land, would raise demand so
as to make it more than ever difficult to get land. All
of the fourth grade would be taken up in expectation of
future demand; and "surplus labor" would be crowded out
to the open space that originally yielded nothing, but
which in consequence of increased labor power now yields
as much as the poorest closed space originally yielded,
namely, 1 to the given expenditure of labor force.102
Wages would then be reduced to the present productiveness
of the open space. Thus: [chart]
102. The paradise to which the youth of
our country have so long been directed in the advice,
"Go West, young man, go West," is truthfully described
in "Progress and Poverty," book iv, ch. iv, as follows
:
"The man who sets out from the eastern
seaboard in search of the margin of cultivation,
where he may obtain land without paying rent, must,
like the man who swam the river to get a drink, pass
for long distances through half-titled farms, and
traverse vast areas of virgin soil, before he reaches
the point where land can be had free of rent —
i.e., by homestead entry or preemption."
If we assume that 1 for the given expenditure of labor
force is the least that labor can take while exerting the
same force, the downward movement of Wages will be here
held in equilibrium. They cannot fall below 1; but
neither can they rise above it, no matter how much
productive power may increase, so long as it pays to hold
land for higher values. Some laborers would continually
be pushed back to land which increased productive power
would have brought up in productiveness from 0 to 1, and
by perpetual competition for work would so regulate the
labor market that the given expenditure of labor force,
however much it produced, could nowhere secure more than
1 in Wages.103 And this tendency would persist until some
labor was forced upon land which, despite increase in
productive power, would not yield the accustomed living
without increase of labor force. Competition for work
would then compel all laborers to increase their
expenditure of labor force, and to do it over and over
again as progress went on and lower and lower grades of
land were monopolized, until human endurance could go no
further.104 Either that, or they would be obliged to
adapt themselves to a lower scale of living.105
103. Henry Fawcett, in his work on
"Political Economy," book ii, ch. iii, observes with
reference to improvements in agricultural implements
which diminish the expense of cultivation, that they do
not increase the profits of the farmer or the wages of
his laborers, but that "the landlord will receive in
addition to the rent already paid to him, all that is
saved in the expense of cultivation." This is true not
alone of improvements in agriculture, but also of
improvements in all other branches of industry.
104. "The cause which limits speculation
in commodities, the tendency of increasing price to
draw forth additional supplies, cannot limit the
speculative advance in land values, as land is a fixed
quantity, which human agency can neither increase nor
diminish; but there is nevertheless a limit to the
price of land, in the minimum required by labor and
capital as the condition of engaging in production. If
it were possible to continuously reduce wages until
zero were reached, it would be possible to continuously
increase rent until it swallowed up the whole produce.
But as wages cannot be permanently reduced below the
point at which laborers will consent to work and
reproduce, nor interest below the point at which
capital will be devoted to production, there is a limit
which restrains the speculative advance of rent. Hence,
speculation cannot have the same scope to advance rent
in countries where wages and interest are already near
the minimum, as in countries where they are
considerably above it. Yet that there is in all
progressive countries a constant tendency in the
speculative advance of rent to overpass the limit where
production would cease, is, I think, shown by recurring
seasons of industrial paralysis." — Progress and
Poverty, book iv, ch. iv.
105. As Puck once put it, "the man who
makes two blades of grass to grow where but one grew
before, must not be surprised when ordered to 'keep off
the grass.' "
They in fact do both, and the incidental disturbances
of general readjustment are what we call "hard times."
106 These culminate in forcing unused land into the
market, thereby reducing Rent and reviving industry. Thus
increase of labor force, a lowering of the scale of
living, and depression of Rent, co-operate to bring on
what we call "good times." But no sooner do "good times"
return than renewed demands for land set in, Rent rises
again, Wages fall again, and "hard times" duly reappear.
The end of every period of "hard times" finds Rent higher
and Wages lower than at the end of the previous
period.107
106. "That a speculative advance in rent
or land values invariably precedes each of these
seasons of industrial depression is everywhere clear.
That they bear to each other the relation of cause and
effect, is obvious to whoever considers the necessary
relation between land and labor." — Progress and
Poverty, book v, ch. i.
107. What are called "good times" reach
a point at which an upward land market sets in. From
that point there is a downward tendency of wages (or a
rise in the cost of living, which is the same thing) in
all departments of labor and with all grades of
laborers. This tendency continues until the fictitious
values of land give way. So long as the tendency is
felt only by that class which is hired for wages, it is
poverty merely; when the same tendency is felt by the
class of labor that is distinguished as "the business
interests of the country," it is "hard times." And
"hard times" are periodical because land values, by
falling, allow "good times" to set it, and by rising
with "good times" bring "hard times" on again. The
effect of "hard times" may be overcome, without much,
if any, fall in land values, by sufficient increase in
productive power to overtake the fictitious value of
land.
The dishonest and disorderly system under which
society confiscates Rent from common to individual uses,
produces this result. That maladjustment is the
fundamental cause of poverty. And progress, so long as
the maladjustment continues, instead of tending to remove
poverty as naturally it should, actually generates and
intensifies it. Poverty persists with increase of
productive power because land values, when Rent is
privately appropriated, tend to even greater increase.
There can be but one outcome if this continues: for
individuals suffering and degradation, and for society
destruction. ... read
the book
Fred Foldvary: A Geoist Robinson
Crusoe Story
Once upon a time, Robinson G. Crusoe was the only
survivor of a ship that sunk. He floated on a piece of
wood to an unpopulated island. Robinson was an absolute
geoist. He believed with his mind, heart, and soul that
everyone should have an equal share of land
rent.
Since he was the only person on this island, it
was all his. He surveyed the island and found that the
only crop available for cultivation was alfalfa sprouts.
The land was divided into 5 grades that could grow 8, 6,
4, 2, and zero bushels of alfalfa sprouts per month.
There was one acre each for 8, 6, and 4, and 100 acres of
2-bushel land. For 8 hours per day of labor, he could
work 4 acres. So he could grow, per month, 8+6+4+2 = 20
bushels of alfalfa sprouts, much more than enough to feed
on.
One day another survivor of a sunken ship floated
to the island. His name was Friday George. Friday was a
boring talker and kept chattering about trivialities,
which greatly irritated Robinson. "I possess the whole
island. You may only have this rocky area," said
Robinson. ... Read the whole piece
H.G. Brown: Significant Paragraphs
from Henry George's Progress & Poverty, Chapter 4: Land
Speculation Causes Reduced Wages
There is a cause, not yet adverted to,
which must be taken into consideration fully to explain
the influence of material progress upon the distribution
of wealth.
That cause is the confident expectation of
the future enhancement of land values, which arises in
all progressive countries from the steady increase of
rent, and which leads to speculation, or the holding of
land for a higher price than it would then otherwise
bring.
We have hitherto assumed, as is generally
assumed in elucidations of the theory of rent, that the
actual margin of cultivation always coincides with what
may be termed the necessary margin of cultivation —
that is to say, we have assumed that cultivation extends
to less productive points only as it becomes necessary
from the fact that natural opportunities are at the more
productive points fully utilized.
This, probably, is the case in stationary
or very slowly progressing communities, but in rapidly
progressing communities, where the swift and steady
increase of rent gives confidence to calculations of
further increase, it is not the case. In such
communities, the confident expectation of increased
prices produces, to a greater or less extent, the effects
of a combination among landholders, and tends to the
withholding of land from use, in expectation of higher
prices, thus forcing the margin of cultivation farther
than required by the necessities of production. ...
read the
whole chapter
|
To share this page with a friend:
right click, choose "send," and add your
comments.
|
|
Red links have not been
visited; .
Green links are pages you've seen
|
Essential Documents pertinent
to this theme:
essential_documents
|
|