Wages Tending Toward a
Minimum
Henry George: The Condition of
Labor — An Open Letter to Pope Leo XIII in response
to Rerum Novarum (1891)
Since man can live only on land and from land, since
land is the reservoir of matter and force from which
man’s body itself is taken, and on which he must
draw for all that he can produce, does it not
irresistibly follow that to give the land in ownership to
some men and to deny to others all right to it is to
divide mankind into the rich and the poor, the privileged
and the helpless? Does it not follow that those who have
no rights to the use of land can live only by selling
their power to labor to those who own the land?
Does it not follow that what the socialists call
“the iron law of wages,” what the political
economists term “the tendency of wages to a
minimum,” must take from the landless masses
— the mere laborers, who of themselves have no
power to use their labor — all the benefits of any
possible advance or improvement that does not alter this
unjust division of land? For having no power to
employ themselves, they must, either as labor-sellers or
as land-renters, compete with one another for permission
to labor. This competition with one another of men shut
out from God’s inexhaustible storehouse has no
limit but starvation, and must ultimately force wages to
their lowest point, the point at which life can just be
maintained and reproduction carried on.
This is not to say that all wages must fall to this
point, but that the wages of that necessarily largest
stratum of laborers who have only ordinary knowledge,
skill and aptitude must so fall. The wages of special
classes, who are fenced off from the pressure of
competition by peculiar knowledge, skill or other causes,
may remain above that ordinary level. Thus, where the
ability to read and write is rare its possession enables
a man to obtain higher wages than the ordinary laborer.
But as the diffusion of education makes the ability to
read and write general this advantage is lost. So when a
vocation requires special training or skill, or is made
difficult of access by artificial restrictions, the
checking of competition tends to keep wages in it at a
higher level. But as the progress of invention dispenses
with peculiar skill, or artificial restrictions are
broken down, these higher wages sink to the ordinary
level. And so, it is only so long as they are special
that such qualities as industry, prudence and thrift can
enable the ordinary laborer to maintain a condition above
that which gives a mere living. Where they become
general, the law of competition must reduce the earnings
or savings of such qualities to the general level —
which, land being monopolized and labor helpless, can be
only that at which the next lowest point is the cessation
of life. ... read the whole
letter
Louis Post: Outlines of Louis F. Post's
Lectures, with Illustrative Notes and Charts (1894)
b. Normal Effect of Social Progress upon
Wages and Rent
In the foregoing charts the effect of social growth is
ignored, it being assumed that the given expenditure of
labor force does not become more productive.93 Let us now
try to illustrate that effect, upon the supposition that
social growth increases the productive power of the given
expenditure of labor force as applied to the first closed
space, to 100; as applied to the second, to 50; as
applied to the third, to 10; as applied to the fourth, to
3, and as applied to the open space, to 1. 94 If there
were no increased demand for land the chart would then be
like this: [chart]
93. "The effect of increasing population
upon the distribution of wealth is to increase rent ..
. in two ways: First, By lowering the margin of
cultivation. Second, By bringing out in land special
capabilities otherwise latent, and by attaching special
capabilities to particular lands.
"I am disposed to think that the latter
mode, to which little attention has been given by
political economists, is really the more important."
— Progress and Poverty, book iv, ch. iii.
"When we have inquired what it is that
marks off land from those material things which we
regard as products of the land, we shall find that the
fundamental attribute of land is its extension. The
right to use a piece of land gives command over a
certain space — a certain part of the earth's
surface. The area of the earth is fixed; the geometric
relations in which any particular part of it stands to
other parts are fixed. Man has no control over them;
they are wholly unaffected by demand; they have no cost
of production; there is no supply price at which they
can be produced.
"The use of a certain area of the earth's
surface is a primary condition of anything that man can
do; it gives him room for his own actions, with the
enjoyment of the heat and the light, the air and the
rain which nature assigns to that area; and it
determines his distance from, and in great measure his
relations to, other things and other persons. We shall
find that it is this property of land, which, though as
yet insufficient prominence has been given to it, is
the ultimate cause of the distinction which all writers
are compelled to make between land and other things."
— Marshall's Prin., book iv, ch. ii, sec. i.
94. Of course social growth does not go
on in this regular way; the charts are merely
illustrative. They are intended to illustrate the
universal fact that as any land becomes a center of
trade or other social relationship its value rises.
Though Rent is now increased, so are Wages. Both
benefit by social growth. But if we consider the fact
that increase in the productive power of labor increases
demand for land we shall see that the tendency of Wages
(as a proportion of product if not as an absolute
quantity) is downward, while that of Rent is upward. 95
And this conclusion is confirmed by observation. 96
95. "Perhaps it may be well to remind the
reader, before closing this chapter, of what has been
before stated — that I am using the word wages
not in the sense of a quantity, but in the sense of a
proportion. When I say that wages fall as rent rises, I
do not mean that the quantity of wealth obtained by
laborers as wages is necessarily less, but that the
proportion which it bears to the whole produce is
necessarily less. The proportion may diminish while the
quantity remains the same or increases." —
Progress and Poverty, book iii, ch. vi.
96. The condition illustrated in the last
chart would be the result of social growth if all land
but that which was in full use were common land. The
discovery of mines, the development of cities and
towns, and the construction of railroads, the
irrigation of and places, improvements in government,
all the infinite conveniences and laborsaving devices
that civilization generates, would tend to abolish
poverty by increasing the compensation of labor, and
making it impossible for any man to be in involuntary
idleness, or underpaid, so long as mankind was in want.
If demand for land increased, Wages would tend to fall
as the demand brought lower grades of land into use;
but they would at the same time tend to rise as social
growth added new capabilities to the lower grades. And
it is altogether probable that, while progress would
lower Wages as a proportion of total product, it would
increase them as an absolute quantity.
c. Significance of the Upward Tendency of
Rent.
Now, what is the meaning of this tendency of Rent to
rise with social progress, while Wages tend to fall? Is
it not a plain promise that if Rent be treated as common
property, advances in productive power shall be steps in
the direction of realizing through orderly and natural
growth those grand conceptions of both the socialist and
the individualist, which in the present condition of
society are justly ranked as Utopian? Is it not likewise
a plain warning that if Rent be treated as private
property, advances in productive power will be steps in
the direction of making slaves of the many laborers, and
masters of a few land-owners? Does it not mean that
common ownership of Rent is in harmony with natural law,
and that its private appropriation is disorderly and
degrading? When the cause of Rent and the tendency
illustrated in the preceding chart are considered in
connection with the self-evident truth that God made the
earth for common use and not for private monopoly, how
can a contrary inference hold? Caused and increased by
social growth, 97 the benefits of which should be common,
and attaching to land, the just right to which is equal,
Rent must be the natural fund for public expenses. 98
97. Here, far away from civilization, is
a solitary settler. Getting no benefits from
government, he needs no public revenues, and none of
the land about him has any value. Another settler
comes, and another, until a village appears. Some
public revenue is then required. Not much, but some.
And the land has a little value, only a little; perhaps
just enough to equal the need for public revenue. The
village becomes a town. More revenues are needed, and
land values are higher. It becomes a city. The public
revenues required are enormous, and so are the land
values.
98. Society, and society alone, causes
Rent. Rising with the rise, advancing with the growth,
and receding with the decline of society, it measures
the earning power of society as a whole as
distinguished from that of the individuals. Wages, on
the other hand, measure the earning power of the
individuals as distinguished from that of society as a
whole. We have distinguished the parts into which
Wealth is distributed as Wages and Rent; but it would
be correct, indeed it is the same thing, to regard all
wealth as earnings, and to distinguish the two kinds as
Communal Earnings and Individual Earnings. How, then,
can there be any question as to the fund from which
society should be supported? How can it be justly
supported in any other way than out of its own
earnings?
If there be at all such a thing as design in the
universe — and who can doubt it? — then has
it been designed that Rent, the earnings of the
community, shall be retained for the support of the
community, and that Wages, the earnings of the
individual, shall be left to the individual in proportion
to the value of his service. This is the divine law,
whether we trace it through complex moral and economic
relations, or find it in the eighth commandment.
d. Effect of Confiscating Rent to Private
Use.
By giving Rent to individuals society ignores this
most just law, 99 thereby creating social disorder and
inviting social disease. Upon society alone, therefore,
and not upon divine Providence which has provided
bountifully, nor upon the disinherited poor, rests the
responsibility for poverty and fear of poverty.
99. "Whatever dispute arouses the
passions of men, the conflict is sure to rage, not so
much as to the question 'Is it wise?' as to the
question 'Is it right?'
"This tendency of popular discussions to
take an ethical form has a cause. It springs from a law
of the human mind; it rests upon a vague and
instinctive recognition of what is probably the deepest
truth we can grasp. That alone is wise which is just;
that alone is enduring which is right. In the narrow
scale of individual actions and individual life this
truth may be often obscured, but in the wider field of
national life it everywhere stands out.
"I bow to this arbitrament, and accept
this test." — Progress and Poverty, book vii, ch.
i.
The reader who has been deceived into
believing that Mr. George's proposition is in any
respect unjust, will find profit in a perusal of the
entire chapter from which the foregoing extract is
taken.
Let us try to trace the connection by means of a
chart, beginning with the white spaces on page 68. As
before, the first-comers take possession of the best
land. But instead of leaving for others what they do not
themselves need for use, as in the previous
illustrations, they appropriate the whole space, using
only part, but claiming ownership of the rest. We may
distinguish the used part with red color, and that which
is appropriated without use with blue. Thus: [chart]
But what motive is there for appropriating more of the
space than is used? Simply that the appropriators may
secure the pecuniary benefit of future social growth.
What will enable them to secure that? Our system of
confiscating Rent from the community that earns it, and
giving it to land-owners who, as such, earn
nothing.100
100. It is reported from Iowa that a few
years ago a workman in that State saw a meteorite fall,
and. securing possession of it after much digging, he
was offered $105 by a college for his "find." But the
owner of the land on which the meteorite fell claimed
the money, and the two went to law about it. After an
appeal to the highest court of the State, it was
finally decided that neither by right of discovery, nor
by right of labor, could the workman have the money,
because the title to the meteorite was in the man who
owned the land upon which it fell.
Observe the effect now upon Rent and Wages. When other
men come, instead of finding half of the best land still
common and free, as in the corresponding chart on page
68, they find all of it owned, and are obliged either to
go upon poorer land or to buy or rent from owners of the
best. How much will they pay for the best? Not more than
1, if they want it for use and not to hold for a higher
price in the future, for that represents the full
difference between its productiveness and the
productiveness of the next best. But if the first-comers,
reasoning that the next best land will soon be scarce and
theirs will then rise in value, refuse to sell or to rent
at that valuation, the newcomers must resort to land of
the second grade, though the best be as yet only partly
used. Consequently land of the first grade commands Rent
before it otherwise would.
As the sellers' price, under these circumstances, is
arbitrary it cannot be stated in the chart; but the
buyers' price is limited by the superiority of the best
land over that which can be had for nothing, and the
chart may be made to show it: [chart]
And now, owing to the success of the appropriators of
the best land in securing more than their fellows for the
same expenditure of labor force, a rush is made for
unappropriated land. It is not to use it that it is
wanted, but to enable its appropriators to put Rent into
their own pockets as soon as growing demand for land
makes it valuable.101 We may, for illustration, suppose
that all the remainder of the second space and the whole
of the third are thus appropriated, and note the effect:
[chart]
At this point Rent does not increase nor Wages fall,
because there is no increased demand for land for use.
The holding of inferior land for higher prices, when
demand for use is at a standstill, is like owning lots in
the moon — entertaining, perhaps, but not
profitable. But let more land be needed for use, and
matters promptly assume a different appearance. The new
labor must either go to the space that yields but 1, or
buy or rent from owners of better grades, or hire out.
The effect would be the same in any case. Nobody for the
given expenditure of labor force would get more than 1;
the surplus of products would go to landowners as Rent,
either directly in rent payments, or indirectly through
lower Wages. Thus: [chart]
101. The text speaks of Rent only as a
periodical or continuous payment — what would be
called "ground rent." But actual or potential Rent may
always be, and frequently is, capitalized for the
purpose of selling the right to enjoy it, and it is to
selling value that we usually refer when dealing in
land.
Land which has the power of yielding Rent
to its owner will have a selling value, whether it be
used or not, and whether Rent is actually derived from
it or not. This selling value will be the
capitalization of its present or prospective power of
producing Rent. In fact, much the larger proportion of
laud that has a selling value is wholly or partly
unused, producing no Rent at all, or less than it would
if fully used. This condition is expressed in the chart
by the blue color.
"The capitalized value of land is the
actuarial 'discounted' value of all the net incomes
which it is likely to afford, allowance being made on
the one hand for all incidental expenses, including
those of collecting the rents, and on the other for its
mineral wealth, its capabilities of development for any
kind of business, and its advantages, material, social,
and aesthetic, for the purposes of residence." —
Marshall's Prin., book vi, ch. ix, sec. 9.
"The value of land is commonly expressed
as a certain number of times the current money rental,
or in other words, a certain 'number of years'
purchase' of that rental; and other things being equal,
it will be the higher the more important these direct
gratifications are, as well as the greater the chance
that they and the money income afforded by the land
will rise." — Id., note.
"Value . . . means not utility, not any
quality inhering in the thing itself, but a quality
which gives to the possession of a thing the power of
obtaining other things, in return for it or for its
use. . . Value in this sense — the usual sense
— is purely relative. It exists from and is
measured by the power of obtaining things for things by
exchanging them. . . Utility is necessary to value, for
nothing can be valuable unless it has the quality of
gratifying some physical or mental desire of man,
though it be but a fancy or whim. But utility of itself
does not give value. . . If we ask ourselves the reason
of . . . variations in . . . value . . . we see that
things having some form of utility or desirability, are
valuable or not valuable, as they are hard or easy to
get. And if we ask further, we may see that with most
of the things that have value this difficulty or ease
of getting them, which determines value, depends on the
amount of labor which must be expended in producing
them ; i.e., bringing them into the place, form and
condition in which they are desired. . . Value is
simply an expression of the labor required for the
production of such a thing. But there are some things
as to which this is not so clear. Land is not produced
by labor, yet land, irrespective of any improvements
that labor has made on it, often has value. . . Yet a
little examination will show that such facts are but
exemplifications of the general principle, just as the
rise of a balloon and the fall of a stone both
exemplify the universal law of gravitation. . . The
value of everything produced by labor, from a pound of
chalk or a paper of pins to the elaborate structure and
appurtenances of a first-class ocean steamer, is
resolvable on analysis into an equivalent of the labor
required to produce such a thing in form and place;
while the value of things not produced by labor, but
nevertheless susceptible of ownership, is in the same
way resolvable into an equivalent of the labor which
the ownership of such a thing enables the owner to
obtain or save." —
Perplexed Philosopher, ch. v.
The figure 1 in parenthesis, as an item of Rent,
indicates potential Rent. Labor would give that much for
the privilege of using the space, but the owners hold out
for better terms; therefore neither Rent nor Wages is
actually produced, though but for this both might be.
In this chart, notwithstanding that but little space
is used, indicated with red, Wages are reduced to the
same low point by the mere appropriation of space,
indicated with blue, that they would reach if all the
space above the poorest were fully used. It thereby
appears that under a system which confiscates Rent to
private uses, the demand for land for speculative
purposes becomes so great that Wages fall to a minimum
long before they would if land were appropriated only for
use.
In illustrating the effect of confiscating Rent to
private use we have as yet ignored the element of social
growth. Let us now assume as before (page 73), that
social growth increases the productive power of the given
expenditure of labor force to 100 when applied to the
best land, 50 when applied to the next best, 10 to the
next, 3 to the next, and 1 to the poorest. Labor would
not be benefited now, as it appeared to be when on page
73 we illustrated the appropriation of land for use only,
although much less land is actually used. The prizes
which expectation of future social growth dangles before
men as the rewards of owning land, would raise demand so
as to make it more than ever difficult to get land. All
of the fourth grade would be taken up in expectation of
future demand; and "surplus labor" would be crowded out
to the open space that originally yielded nothing, but
which in consequence of increased labor power now yields
as much as the poorest closed space originally yielded,
namely, 1 to the given expenditure of labor force.102
Wages would then be reduced to the present productiveness
of the open space. Thus: [chart]
102. The paradise to which the youth of
our country have so long been directed in the advice,
"Go West, young man, go West," is truthfully described
in "Progress and Poverty," book iv, ch. iv, as follows
:
"The man who sets out from the eastern
seaboard in search of the margin of cultivation,
where he may obtain land without paying rent, must,
like the man who swam the river to get a drink, pass
for long distances through half-titled farms, and
traverse vast areas of virgin soil, before he reaches
the point where land can be had free of rent —
i.e., by homestead entry or preemption."
If we assume that 1 for the given expenditure of labor
force is the least that labor can take while exerting the
same force, the downward movement of Wages will be here
held in equilibrium. They cannot fall below 1; but
neither can they rise above it, no matter how much
productive power may increase, so long as it pays to hold
land for higher values. Some laborers would continually
be pushed back to land which increased productive power
would have brought up in productiveness from 0 to 1, and
by perpetual competition for work would so regulate the
labor market that the given expenditure of labor force,
however much it produced, could nowhere secure more than
1 in Wages.103 And this tendency would persist until some
labor was forced upon land which, despite increase in
productive power, would not yield the accustomed living
without increase of labor force. Competition for work
would then compel all laborers to increase their
expenditure of labor force, and to do it over and over
again as progress went on and lower and lower grades of
land were monopolized, until human endurance could go no
further.104 Either that, or they would be obliged to
adapt themselves to a lower scale of living.105
103. Henry Fawcett, in his work on
"Political Economy," book ii, ch. iii, observes with
reference to improvements in agricultural implements
which diminish the expense of cultivation, that they do
not increase the profits of the farmer or the wages of
his laborers, but that "the landlord will receive in
addition to the rent already paid to him, all that is
saved in the expense of cultivation." This is true not
alone of improvements in agriculture, but also of
improvements in all other branches of industry.
104. "The cause which limits speculation
in commodities, the tendency of increasing price to
draw forth additional supplies, cannot limit the
speculative advance in land values, as land is a fixed
quantity, which human agency can neither increase nor
diminish; but there is nevertheless a limit to the
price of land, in the minimum required by labor and
capital as the condition of engaging in production. If
it were possible to continuously reduce wages until
zero were reached, it would be possible to continuously
increase rent until it swallowed up the whole produce.
But as wages cannot be permanently reduced below the
point at which laborers will consent to work and
reproduce, nor interest below the point at which
capital will be devoted to production, there is a limit
which restrains the speculative advance of rent. Hence,
speculation cannot have the same scope to advance rent
in countries where wages and interest are already near
the minimum, as in countries where they are
considerably above it. Yet that there is in all
progressive countries a constant tendency in the
speculative advance of rent to overpass the limit where
production would cease, is, I think, shown by recurring
seasons of industrial paralysis." — Progress and
Poverty, book iv, ch. iv.
105. As Puck once put it, "the man who
makes two blades of grass to grow where but one grew
before, must not be surprised when ordered to 'keep off
the grass.' "
They in fact do both, and the incidental disturbances
of general readjustment are what we call "hard times."
106 These culminate in forcing unused land into the
market, thereby reducing Rent and reviving industry. Thus
increase of labor force, a lowering of the scale of
living, and depression of Rent, co-operate to bring on
what we call "good times." But no sooner do "good times"
return than renewed demands for land set in, Rent rises
again, Wages fall again, and "hard times" duly reappear.
The end of every period of "hard times" finds Rent higher
and Wages lower than at the end of the previous
period.107
106. "That a speculative advance in rent
or land values invariably precedes each of these
seasons of industrial depression is everywhere clear.
That they bear to each other the relation of cause and
effect, is obvious to whoever considers the necessary
relation between land and labor." — Progress and
Poverty, book v, ch. i.
107. What are called "good times" reach a
point at which an upward land market sets in. From that
point there is a downward tendency of wages (or a rise
in the cost of living, which is the same thing) in all
departments of labor and with all grades of laborers.
This tendency continues until the fictitious values of
land give way. So long as the tendency is felt only by
that class which is hired for wages, it is poverty
merely; when the same tendency is felt by the class of
labor that is distinguished as "the business interests
of the country," it is "hard times." And "hard times"
are periodical because land values, by falling, allow
"good times" to set it, and by rising with "good times"
bring "hard times" on again. The effect of "hard times"
may be overcome, without much, if any, fall in land
values, by sufficient increase in productive power to
overtake the fictitious value of land.
The dishonest and disorderly system under which
society confiscates Rent from common to individual uses,
produces this result. That maladjustment is the
fundamental cause of poverty. And progress, so long as
the maladjustment continues, instead of tending to remove
poverty as naturally it should, actually generates and
intensifies it. Poverty persists with increase of
productive power because land values, when Rent is
privately appropriated, tend to even greater increase.
There can be but one outcome if this continues: for
individuals suffering and degradation, and for society
destruction.
Q25. What good would the single tax do to the
poor? and how?
A. By constantly keeping the demand for labor above the
supply it would enable them to abolish their poverty.
... read the
book
Charles B. Fillebrown: A Catechism of
Natural Taxation, from Principles of Natural
Taxation (1917)
Q30. How would the single tax increase
wages?
A. By gradually transferring to wages that portion of the
current wealth that now flows to privilege. In other
words, it would widen and deepen the channel of wages by
enlarging opportunities for labor, and by increasing the
purchasing power of nominal wages through reduction of
prices. On the other hand it would narrow the channel of
privilege by making the man who has a privilege pay for
it.
Q31. How can this transfer be effected?
A. By the taxation of privilege.
Q32. How much ultimately may wages be thus
increased?
A. Fifty percent would be a low estimate.
Q33. What are fair prices and fair
wages?
A. Prices unenhanced by privilege, and wages undiminished
by taxation. ... read the whole
article
Rev. A. C. Auchmuty: Gems from George, a themed
collection of excerpts from the writings of Henry
George (with links to sources)
THE aggregate produce of the labor of a savage tribe
is small, but each member is capable of an independent
life. He can build his own habitation, hew out or stitch
together his own canoe, make his own clothing,
manufacture his own weapons, snares, tools and ornaments.
He has all the knowledge of nature possessed by his tribe
— knows what vegetable productions are fit for
food, and where they maybe found; knows the habits and
resorts of beasts, birds, fishes and insects; can pilot
himself by the sun or the stars, by the turning of
blossoms or the mosses on the trees; is, in short,
capable of supplying all his wants. He may be cut off
from his fellows and still live; and thus possesses an
independent power which makes him a free contracting
party in his relations to the community of which he is a
member.
Compare with this savage the laborer in the lowest
ranks of civilized society, whose life is spent in
producing but one thing, or oftener but the infinitesimal
part of one thing, out of the multiplicity of things that
constitute the wealth of society and go to supply even
the most primitive wants; who not only cannot make even
the tools required for his work, but often works with
tools that he does not own, and can never hope to own.
Compelled to even closer and more continuous labor than
the savage, and gaining tby it no more than the savage
gets — the mere necessaries of life — he
loses the independence of the savage. He is not only
unable to apply his own powers to the direct satisfaction
of his own wants, but, without the concurrence of many
others, he is unable to apply them indirectly to the
satisfaction of his wants. He is a mere link in an
enormous chain of producers and consumers, helpless to
separate himself, and helpless to move, except as they
move. The worse his position in society, the more
dependent is he on society; the more utterly unable does
he become to do anything for himself. The very power of
exerting his labor for the satisfaction of his wants
passes from his own control, and may be taken away or
restored by the actions of others, or by general causes
over which he has no more influence than he has over the
motions of the solar system. The primeval curse comes to
be looked upon as a boon, and men think, and talk, and
clamor, and legislate as though monotonous manual labor
in itself were a good and not an evil, an end and not a
means. Under such circumstances, the man loses the
essential quality of manhood — the godlike power of
modifying and controlling conditions. He becomes a slave,
a machine, a commodity — a thing, in some respects,
lower than the animal.
I am no sentimental admirer of the savage state. I do
not get my ideas of the untutored children of nature from
Rousseau, or Chateaubriand, or Cooper. I am conscious of
its material and mental poverty, and its low and narrow
range. I believe that civilization is not only the
natural destiny of man, but the enfranchisement,
elevation, and refinement of all his powers, and think
that it is only in such moods as may lead him to envy the
cud-chewing cattle, that a man who is free to the
advantages of civilization could look with regret upon
the savage state. But, nevertheless, I think no one who
will open his eyes to the facts, can resist the
conclusion that there are in the heart of our
civilization large classes with whom the veriest savage
could not afford to exchange. It is my deliberate opinion
that if, standing on the threshold of being, one were
given the choice of entering life as a Terra del Fuegan,
a black fellow of Australia, an Esquimaux in the Arctic
Circle, or among the lowest classes in such a highly
civilized country as Great Britain, he would make
infinitely the better choice in selecting the lot of the
savage. For those classes who in the midst of wealth are
condemned to want, suffer all the privations of the
savage, without his sense of personal freedom; they are
condemned to more than his narrowness and littleness,
without opportunity for the growth of his rude virtues;
if their horizon is wider, it is but to reveal blessings
that they cannot enjoy. — Progress & Poverty
— Book V, Chapter 2: The Problem Solved: The
Persistence of Poverty Amid Advancing Wealth
BUT it seems to us the vice of Socialism in all its
degrees is its want of radicalism, of going to the root.
. .. It assumes that the tendency of wages to a minimum
is the natural law, and seeks to abolish wages; it
assumes that the natural result of competition is to
grind down workers, and seeks to abolish competition by
restrictions, prohibitions, and extensions of governing
power. Thus mistaking effects for causes, and childishly
blaming the stone for hitting it, it wastes strength in
striving for remedies that when not worse are futile.
Associated though it is in many places with democratic
aspiration, yet its essence is the same delusion to which
the Children of Israel yielded when, against the protest
of their prophet, they insisted on a king; the delusion
that has everywhere corrupted democracies and enthroned
monarchs — that power over the people can be used
for the benefit of the people; that there may be devised
machinery that through human agencies will secure for the
management of individual affairs more wisdom and more
virtue than the people themselves possess. — The
Condition of Labor, an Open Letter to Pope Leo XIII
JUMPING to conclusions without effort to discover
causes, it fails to see that oppression does not come
from the nature of capital, but from the wrong that robs
labor of capital by divorcing it from land, and that
creates a fictitious capital that is really capitalized
monopoly. It fails to see that it would be impossible for
capital to oppress labor were labor free to the natural
material of production; that the wage system in itself
springs from mutual convenience, being a form of
co-operation in which one of the parties prefers a
certain to a contingent result; and that what it calls
the "iron law of wages," is not the natural law of wages,
but only the law of wages in that unnatural condition in
which men are made helpless by being deprived of the
materials for life and work. It fails to see that what it
mistakes for the evils of competition are really the
evils of restricted competition — are due to a
one-sided competition to which men are forced when
deprived of land. While its methods, the organization of
men into industrial armies, the direction and control of
all production and exchange by governmental or
semi-governmental bureaus, would, if carried to full
expression, mean Egyptian despotism. —The Condition
of Labor, an Open Letter to Pope Leo XIII
IN socialism as distinguished from individualism there
is an unquestionable truth — and that a truth to
which (especially by those most identified with
free-trade principles) too little attention has been
paid. Man is primarily an individual — a separate
entity, differing from his fellows in desires and powers,
and requiring for the exercise of those powers and the
gratification of those desires individual play and
freedom. But he is also a social being, having desires
that harmonize with those of his fellows, and powers that
can only be brought out in concerted action. There is
thus a domain of individual action and a domain of social
action — some things which can best be done when
each acts for himself, and some things which can best be
done when society acts for all its members. And the
natural tendency of advancing civilization is to make
social conditions relatively more important, and more and
more to enlarge the domain of social action. This has not
been sufficiently regarded, and at the present time, evil
unquestionably results from leaving to individual action
functions that by reason of the growth of society and the
developments of the arts have passed into the domain of
social action; just as, on the other hand, evil
unquestionably results from social interference with what
properly belongs to the individual. Society ought not to
leave the telegraph and the railway to the management and
control of individuals; nor yet ought society to step in
and collect individual debts or attempt to direct
individual industry. — Protection or Free Trade,
Chapter 28 econlib
NOW, why is it that men, have to work for such low
wages? Because, if they were to demand higher wages,
there are plenty of unemployed men ready to step into
their places. It is this mass of unemployed men who
compel that fierce competition that drives wages down to
the point of bare subsistence. Why is it that there are
men who cannot get employment? Did you ever think what a
strange thing it is that men cannot find employment? If
men cannot find an employer, why can they not employ
themselves? Simply because they are shut out from the
element on which human labor can alone be exerted; men
are compelled to compete with each other for the wages of
an employer, because they have been robbed of the natural
opportunities of employing themselves; because they
cannot find a piece of God's world on which to work
without paying some other human creature for the
privilege. — The Crime of Poverty
WE laud as public benefactors those who, as we say,
"furnish employment." We are constantly talking as though
this "furnishing of employment," this "giving of work"
were the greatest boon that could be conferred upon
society. To listen to much that is talked and much that
is written, one would think that the cause of poverty is
that there is not work enough for so many people, and
that if the Creator had made the rock harder, the soil
less fertile, iron as scarce as gold, and gold as
diamonds; or if ships would sink and cities burn down
oftener, there would be less poverty, because there would
be more work to do. — Social Problems, Chapter 8
— That We All Might Be Rich
YOU assert the right of laborers to employment and
their right to receive from their employers a certain
indefinite wage. No such rights exist. No one has a right
to demand employment of another, or to demand higher
wages than the other is willing to give, or in any way to
put pressure on another to make him raise such wages
against his will. There can be no better moral
justification for such demands on employers by
working-men than there would be for employers demanding
that working-men shall be compelled to work for them when
they do not want to, and to accept wages lower than they
are willing to take. — The Condition of Labor, an
Open Letter to Pope Leo XIII
THE natural right which each man has, is not that of
demanding employment or wages from another man, but that
of employing himself — that of applying by his own
labor to the inexhaustible storehouse which the Creator
has in the land provided for all men. Were that
storehouse open, as by the single tax we would open it,
the natural demand for labor would keep pace with the
supply, the man who sold labor and the man who bought it
would become free exchangers for mutual advantage, and
all cause for dispute between workman and employer would
be gone. For then, all being free to employ themselves,
the mere opportunity to labor would cease to seem a boon;
and since no one would work for another for less, all
things considered, than he could earn by working for
himself, wages would necessarily rise to their full
value, and the relations of workman and employer be
regulated by mutual interest and convenience. — The
Condition of Labor, an Open Letter to Pope Leo XIII ...
go to "Gems from
George"
|
To share this page with a friend:
right click, choose "send," and add your
comments.
|
|
Red links have not been
visited; .
Green links are pages you've seen
|
Essential Documents pertinent
to this theme:
essential_documents
|
|