Unearned Increment
One person's unearned increment is another's — and
likely many others' — lost birthright. Who
is entitled to it? All of us! How do we implement this?
Land value taxation.
Mason Gaffney, correspondence (used with
permission)
We, like you no doubt, are basking in the unearned
increment of the land under our house, turbo-charged by
tax-exemption. Two of our older children in Marin
County are basking, too, and we take comfort in their
well-being. We deserve this, right? Are we
not of The Greatest Generation (how we love that toadying
title)? But how will your
grandchildren afford a home at today's prices? We
get the increment, but they get the
excrement. Oh, well, the plunging dollar,
crumbling infrastructure, far-called navies and troops
melting away, soaring interest rates, higher taxes,
incredible public debts coming due ... it'll all be
different soon. We may all grow poor
together.
Henry George: The Wages of
Labor
The worst evil of poverty is not in the want of
material things, but in the stunting and distortion of
the higher qualities. So, in another way, the
possession of unearned wealth stunts and distorts what
is noblest in man.
The evil is not in wealth itself
– in its command over material things: it is in the
possession of wealth while others are steeped in poverty;
in being raised above touch with the life of humanity;
from its work and its struggles, its hopes and its fears,
and the kind sympathies and generous acts that strengthen
faith in man and trust in God!
God’s commands cannot be
evaded with impunity. If it be His command that men shall
earn their bread by labor, the idle rich must suffer. And
they do!
See the utter vacancy of the lives
of those who live for pleasure; see the vices bred in a
class who, surrounded by poverty, are sated with wealth;
see the pessimism that grows among them; see that
terrible punishment of ennui, of which the poor know so
little that they cannot understand it!... read the whole
article Henry George: The Single Tax: What It Is
and Why We Urge It (1890)
Our plan involves the imposition of no new tax,
since we already tax land values in taxing real estate.
To carry it out we have only to abolish all taxes save
the tax on real estate, and abolish all of that which
now falls on buildings or improvements, leaving only
that part of it which now falls on the value of the
bare land, increasing that so as to take as nearly as
may be the whole of economic rent, or what is sometimes
styled the "unearned increment of land values."
... read the whole
article
Henry George: The Condition of Labor
— An Open Letter to Pope Leo XIII in response to
Rerum Novarum (1891)
The sympathy of your Holiness seems exclusively
directed to the poor, the workers. Ought this to be so?
Are not the rich, the idlers, to be pitied also? By the
word of the gospel it is the rich rather than the poor
who call for pity, for the presumption is that they will
share the fate of Dives. And to any one who believes in a
future life the condition of him who wakes to find his
cherished millions left behind must seem pitiful. But
even in this life, how really pitiable are the rich. The
evil is not in wealth in itself — in its command
over material things; it is in the possession of wealth
while others are steeped in poverty; in being raised
above touch with the life of humanity, from its work and
its struggles, its hopes and its fears, and above all,
from the love that sweetens life, and the kindly
sympathies and generous acts that strengthen faith in man
and trust in God.
Consider how the rich see the meaner side of human
nature; how they are surrounded by flatterers and
sycophants; how they find ready instruments not only to
gratify vicious impulses, but to prompt and stimulate
them; how they must constantly be on guard lest they be
swindled; how often they must suspect an ulterior motive
behind kindly deed or friendly word; how if they try to
be generous they are beset by shameless beggars and
scheming impostors; how often the family affections are
chilled for them, and their deaths anticipated with the
ill-concealed joy of expectant possession. The
worst evil of poverty is not in the want of material
things, but in the stunting and distortion of the higher
qualities. So, though in another way, the possession of
unearned wealth likewise stunts and distorts what is
noblest in man.
God’s commands cannot be evaded with impunity.
If it be God’s command that men shall earn
their bread by labor, the idle rich must suffer. And they
do. See the utter vacancy of the lives of those who live
for pleasure; see the loathsome vices bred in a class who
surrounded by poverty are sated with wealth. See
that terrible punishment of ennui, of which the poor know
so little that they cannot understand it; see the
pessimism that grows among the wealthy classes —
that shuts out God, that despises men, that deems
existence in itself an evil, and fearing death yet longs
for annihilation.
When Christ told the rich young man who sought him to
sell all he had and to give it to the poor, he was not
thinking of the poor, but of the young man. And I doubt
not that among the rich, and especially among the
self-made rich, there are many who at times at least feel
keenly the folly of their riches and fear for the dangers
and temptations to which these expose their children. But
the strength of long habit, the prompting of pride, the
excitement of making and holding what have become for
them the counters in a game of cards, the family
expectations that have assumed the character of rights,
and the real difficulty they find in making any good use
of their wealth, bind them to their burden, like a weary
donkey to his pack, till they stumble on the precipice
that bounds this life. ... read the whole
letter
Charles B. Fillebrown: A Catechism of Natural
Taxation, from Principles of Natural Taxation
(1917)
Q46. Would it not be confiscation so to increase
the tax on land?
A. What would be confiscated? No land would be taken, no
right of occupancy, or use, or improvement, or sale, or
devise; nothing would be taken that is conveyed or
guaranteed by the title deed.
Q47. What is the distinction between taxation and
confiscation?
A. The sovereign state may appropriate private property
of its citizens in two ways: (1) by confiscation; (2) by
taxation. When one particular man by treason or otherwise
has forfeited his rights as a citizen, the land and
houses and personalty of this one man may all be "forfeit
to the crown," while the validity and sanctity of 9,999
other men's rights are in no way infringed. This is
confiscation. On the other hand, when the state, in order
to obtain the revenue to meet the expenses of government,
levies tribute upon its 10,000 citizens impartially, this
is taxation.
Q48. But would it not be an injustice to the
landowner?
A. If it be an injustice to tax hard-earned incomes
(wages) to maintain an unearned income (net economic
rent) that bears no tax burden, how can it be an
injustice to stop doing so? There can be no injustice in
taking for the benefit of the community the value that is
created by the community.
Q61. Do you think there would be any injustice in
taking by taxation the future increment in the value of
land?
A. Fifteen professors of political economy have answered
"Yes." Ninety-four have answered "No." ... read the whole
article
Winston Churchill: Land Price as a Cause of
Poverty (1909 speech in Parliament)
When the Leader of the Opposition seeks by
comparisons to show that the same reasoning which has
been applied to land ought also in logic and by every
argument of symmetry to be applied to the unearned
increment derived from other processes which are at work
in our modern civilisation, he only shows by each example
he takes how different are the conditions which attach to
the possession of land and speculation in the value of
land from those which attach to other forms of business
speculation.
"If," he inquires, "you tax the
unearned increment on land, why don't you tax the unearned
increment from a large block of stock? I buy a piece of
land; the value rises. I buy stocks; their value rises."
But the operations are entirely dissimilar. In the first
speculation the unearned increment derived from land arises
from a wholly sterile process, from the mere withholding of
a commodity which is needed by the community. In the second
case, the investor in a block of shares does not withhold
from the community what the community needs. The one
operation is in restraint of trade and in conflict with the
general interest, and the other is part of a natural and
healthy process, by which the economic plant of the world
is nourished and from year to year successfully and notably
increased.
Then the right hon. gentleman instanced the case
of a new railway and a country district enriched by that
railway. The railway, he explained, is built to open up a
new district; and the farmers and landowners in that
district are endowed with unearned increment in
consequence of the building of the railway. But if after
a while their business aptitude and industry create a
large carrying trade, then the railway, he contends, gets
its unearned increment in its turn.
But the right hon. gentleman cannot
call the increment unearned which the railway acquires
through the regular service of carrying goods, rendering a
service on each occasion in proportion to the tonnage of
goods it carries, making a profit by an active extension of
the scale of its useful business - he cannot surely compare
that process with the process of getting rich merely by
sitting still? It is clear that the analogy is not true.
... Read the whole piece
Clarence Darrow: How to Abolish Unfair
Taxation (1913)
... Beyond a living all surplus goes to the
monopolist, and it does go to him. You talk about a city
of a million in 1915 — who would be benefited? Not
the workingman; he would be far worse off than at
present, for the greater the city the greater the
poverty.
Taxes on goods are added to the price of goods and
passed on to the consumer. There is only one kind of tax
that is not a curse, and that is the land tax. If you tax
a pair of shoes a dollar, the manufacturer will add that
to the price of the shoes, and thus diminish the number
of shoes the people can buy. The higher you tax the land
the more land is thrown on the market and the easier it
is to secure, and it is the only thing that increases by
taxation.
The higher the tax on land the more it comes into use,
and so "single tax" is a positive blessing. It is the
only tax that does not come out of labor, it comes out of
the monopolist; it stays right there, and that fact
compels them to put the land to some use, and that
employs labor. ... read the whole
speech
Arthur J. Ogilvy: A Colonist's Plea for
Land Nationalization (about 1890)
The Unearned Increment: Its
Nature.
LET us begin by taking the unearned increment in its
simplest and clearest form.
Suppose I buy Government land at £1 per acre, and
quietly holding on while roads are being pushed forward,
settlement extending and land values rising, refuse offer
after offer till the price reaches £2, when I sell
out. Of these £2, one I have acquired by direct
purchase; £1 worth of money for £1 worth of
land; but the other I have done nothing to acquire.
It is not interest on the purchase-money, for interest
is payment for the use of capital, and comes out of the
use. Who would expect interest on money tied up in an old
rag? There has been no use here.
It is not compensation for risk, for the land could
not disappear or deteriorate, and was sure to be
wanted.
It may be quite right for all that, that I should have
it. That is not the point at present. The point at
present is simply to explain the term, and to show not
only what it directly means, but what it indirectly
implies, for it implies a great deal much more than most
people have any idea of.
I have neither done anything to create this increase
of value nor rendered any service in return for it. If a
sovereign were suddenly to drop into my pocket from the
sky, it would not be more completely unearned.
But it has not only been unearned. If that were all,
it would be no great matter. If, like the sovereign, it
had dropped from the sky, then, though I might be
undeservedly the richer nobody else would be the poorer.
My gain would be a clear addition to the sum total of
human wealth, out of which others besides myself would in
one way or another derive benefit; and, whether or no
whatever benefits one without injuring another is fair
subject for congratulation.
But it has not only been unearned; it has been drawn
from the earnings of others. My gain is others' loss.
If I sell goods or perform work for another, then no
matter how high I may charge for the goods or the work, I
am rendering goods for goods, service for service,
earnings for earnings. What I offer is my labour, or the
fruits of it, and as the public are free to get the same
goods or services elsewhere if my terms don't suit, or to
go without them, the fact of their accepting my terms
shows that the thing I offer is, under the circumstances,
worth the money.
But in the case of this unearned increment on land
there is no pretence of any exchange. I offer for it
neither labour nor the produce of labour. All I do is to
place my hand on a certain portion of the earth's
surface, and say, "No one shall use this without paying
me for the mere permission to use it." I am rendering no
more service in return for this extra pound, either to
the purchaser or to society, than if I had acquired
exclusive title to the air, and charged people for
permission to breathe. And if, instead of selling my land
for an additional pound, I let it at a proportionately
additional rent the principle would be the same.
The increase of value in my land has arisen from the
execution of public works and increase of population,
causing an increased demand for the land; in other words,
it has arisen from the national progress; and I, so far
from aiding in this progress have actually hindered it,
by keeping my property locked up and so forcing on
intending producers to inferior or less accessible lands;
and by holding so much land back have helped to make land
so much scarcer, and, therefore, so much dearer, and so
have helped to increase the tribute which industry has to
pay to monopoly for the mere privilege of exerting
itself.
I have employed my land not as an instrument of
production, but as a means of extortion. I have bought
it, not to use but to prevent other people from using it
without my purchased leave; not to earn anything by it
but to obtain the power of demanding the earnings of
others.
Suppose certain parties, knowing that a road would
shortly be made into a particular region, bought from
Government the privilege of placing bars across the road
(when made) and forbidding anybody to pass until he had
paid toll; toll not (as under the old State tolls) to pay
for the maintenance of the road, but toll for the mere
permission to pass along the road. Every one would
recognise that this toll was pure blackmail and not
earnings, and the obstructors mere parasites licensed to
prey upon the public. But where is the difference between
blocking the road and blocking the land that the roads
lead to? Where is the difference between levying
blackmail on the transport of goods and levying it on
their production?
But it will be said, "It was with real earnings that I
bought the right to demand this payment."
True. But the point is that whether I bought it or
stole it, the thing I have bought or stolen is the
privilege of levying blackmail upon industry; of
demanding something and giving nothing in return; of
laying my hand on the earth's surface and saying to all
and sundry, "Give me of the produce of your labour, or be
off with you; so much a year if I choose to let it; so
much in a lump sum if I prefer to sell it." Whichever of
the two forms the demand assumes it is called by
political economists "rent," and by that name I shall
henceforth call it, because that is the accepted name,
and because there is no other compact and handy term by
which to express it; but it is not to be confounded with
rent in the legal and commercial sense, which includes
interest on the cost of improvements. The rent I shall
mean is economic rent only; the price charged for the
mere use of the land as such, either without any
improvements or apart from them: I shall mean "ground
rent" in short.
The fact that it was with real earnings that I bought
the land for which I charge rent does not make rent
earnings. I may invest earnings in buying a share in a
pirate vessel (as a great writer puts it), but the
proceeds of piracy are not therefore earnings.
It is the nature of the business whereby I make money,
and not the manner in which I got into it that makes the
difference between earnings and appropriation.
Earnings mean taking payment for goods or service
rendered; appropriation means taking something and giving
nothing in return; no matter whether the taking be legal
or illegal, or how I acquired the privilege of taking.
Anyone can recognise that it is one thing to charge for
the fish I caught in the sea, and quite another thing to
charge for permission to fish in the sea; one thing to
charge for produce I have raised from the land, and quite
another thing to charge for permission to raise produce
from land.
"Still I have the right to make this charge?"
I am not disputing that.
If Government, with the full consent of the governed,
issued licenses authorising to rob on the highway, the
robbers, I suppose, would be justified in acting on their
privilege; but their gains, all the same, would be
appropriation and not earnings, no matter how high they
paid for their license or how honestly they came by the
money to pay for it. And if the public, disgusted with
the system, demanded its immediate abolition, the robbers
would have a claim to compensation but their compensation
would have to be assessed, not by the amount of plunder
they had expected to make, but by the fee they had paid
for their license and the actual loss to which, in one
way or another, they had been put by the sudden abolition
of a privilege they had honestly paid for.
But it will be said, "Rent is the result of a free
contract."
Is it? The Italian peasant who agrees to pay to the
brigand on the mountain so much a year in consideration
of not being robbed makes a contract, but is it a free
contract? If he refuses to pay it the brigand will take
his earnings; if the applicant for land refuses to pay
rent the landlord will refuse to let him make any
earnings. Where is the great difference between the two
cases? There is a contract in each case, and the one is
about as free as the other.
In neither case is anything given in return for the
payment received, except permission to work unmolested in
a particular place.
"But," it will be said "in practice the rent of an
estate represents real earnings in the shape of
improvements made, as well as mere permission to use the
land, and how can you separate the two values."
Not only is it quite possible to separate them, but
the thing is often done. In London, for instance, the
ground rent and the rent for the house often belong to
quite different persons. In Ulster, again, the retiring
tenant receives the value of his improvements while the
landlord keeps the value of the land. And in America, I
am told, the land and the improvements are assessed
separately and taxed separately.
But all this has really nothing to do with the subject
in hand. My concern at present is simply to explain the
nature of the unearned increment.
Whether the value of land and the value of the
improvements can be separated or not, they are quite
distinct elements, just as in a glass of grog, the brandy
is brandy and the water water, each with its own
distinctive properties and effects, notwithstanding their
indistinguishable com-mixture; and he therefore who lets
land levies blackmail upon industry by charging for
something which represents no service at all, none the
less that at the same time he charges for something else
that does represent service.
No doubt there are many other things besides land in
which a monopoly of the article will enable the possessor
to levy something resembling blackmail; but there are
points of difference that distinguish them all from the
pure and simple appropriation of land monopoly.
The first is that none of them excludes other people
from making a living or from making earnings to any
extent by other means than the article monopolised.
If by a day's labour or by pure accident I find a
diamond, I may ask a price entirely disproportionate to
the value of my labour; but then the public need not buy
my diamond unless they like. My finding a diamond does
not prevent other people from looking for diamonds with
as much chance of finding them as I had, and, if they
don't think they are likely to find any by looking for
them they can go without, and be none the worse.
But every piece of land appropriated shuts out so many
other people from that land, and as all the land
(practically speaking) is appropriated, or in one way or
another out of reach of the masses, they are at the mercy
of the landholders, and have no choice but either to rent
it from them as tenants or work for them as labourers on
the hardest terms to which competition can drive them;
which means that the landowner has the power of
appropriating the greater part of their earnings in
return for the mere permission to them to earn
anything.
Or suppose that, instead of finding a diamond, I buy
tin, and that next week the price goes up to double here
there is an additional distinction between my gains and
the land speculator's; for not only are the public under
no compulsion to buy tin (while they are to rent land),
and not only does tin represent the results of labour,
and so represent earnings (which land does not), but the
magnitude of my gain in most cases represents
compensation for great risk.
The earnings of farmers and of miners may average the
same, but the farmers' average is made up of pretty equal
profits all round, while the miners' average is made up
of a few big prizes and many blanks. And what applies to
the miner applies also to the speculator in mining
products. His occasional large profits represent
compensation for great risks, and is thus as much of the
nature of insurance as of profit.
No one would think of either mining or speculating in
mining products, unless the many blanks were compensated
by occasional large prizes. They are the necessary
inducements to engage in those callings, and therefore
fair earnings when they come. Land, however, is not a
speculation in this sense (though even if it were, its
profits would still be appropriation and not earnings for
reasons already given); it is a sure investment in the
sense that it is subject to no extraordinary risks: to no
more risks, that is, than such as are inseparable from
all human enterprise, even the safest.
The value of land, as of everything else, will
oscillate within certain limits, and even in some
exceptional cases, as in the sudden diversion of traffic,
fall for an indefinitely prolonged period; but these
occasional or exceptional perturbations are but as the
advance and recession of the waves in a flowing tide. The
tide still comes in.
In every country which has any enterprise and
progress, land values must rise. The movement may be fast
or slow, continuous or interrupted, but it is up not
down.
There is not a single factor in a nation's progress
that does not add to the value of land. Every road
improved and railway laid down; every machine invented
and process perfected; every opening of new markets;
every improvement in fiscal policy, in order and good
Government, in the knowledge and skill, in the morals,
manners, and even numbers of the people, every
conceivable element, in short that adds to the
productiveness of industry, adds to the value of land,
and increases the tribute which monopoly can wring from
industry; which the man who merely owns the land can
exact from him who uses it for the mere permission to use
it.
This is why the gradual rise of land value or rent
(ground rent only, remember), is called the unearned
increment.
So far for its nature. Our next consideration will be
its magnitude.
The Unearned Increment: Its
Magnitude.
Under the system prevailing all over the civilised
world every country is appropriated by a (comparatively)
few owners.
What these owners do with the land is a matter the
State concerns itself very little about. Whether they
occupy and use it themselves, or let it to a tenant and
live in idleness on the fruits of his labour; whether
they cultivate it like a garden, making it yield abundant
wealth and maintain hundreds of families, or leave it in
a state of nature to carry sheep, excluding the whole
rising tide of population from the opportunity of
developing its boundless resources because the sheep pay
them rather better; whether they open out the mineral
treasures hidden in its depths or lock them up by
demanding such exorbitant royalties that enterprise
either will not attempt the work, or attempts and fails;
whether they construct factories and build cities upon
it, or turn out the whole population and burn down their
dwellings (as in the Scottish Highlands) because a
foreign millionaire offers them a higher price for the
privilege of turning it into a wilderness to shoot deer
in than the children of the soil can give for the mere
privilege of earning a living; all these things the State
regards as matters of quite secondary consideration with
which it is not called upon to interpose, because that
would be interfering with the "sacred rights" of
property.
The one thing it does concern itself energetically
about is to establish "the sacred rights" as fast as
possible and in all directions, and ensure that every
acre shall have its blackmailer privileged to exclude
everybody else from the land he has acquired possession
of, and to forbid access to all industry except on
payment of the heaviest toll which the keenest
competition can compel.
The whole country (that is the whole country worth
occupying at any given moment) being thus apportioned
amongst these privileged few, they are masters of the
situation. The first thing a man requires is room to
stand in; and there is no unappropriated room available
for the purpose. If he stands on private land he is
liable to an action for trespass. If he goes out into the
street, the policeman may order him to move on. When
night comes on, matters are worse. If he sleeps on
somebody's premises he can be apprehended for being on
the premises for an unlawful purpose. If he sleeps in the
bush he may be locked up as a vagrant without any visible
means of support. The State insists that he shall pay
blackmail to somebody; not payment for service of any
sort rendered, but payment for the mere permission to be
somewhere.
Land is the basis of all industry.
All industry consists either 1. In extracting the raw
materials of wealth from the land; or 2. In working up,
shifting about, or distributing these materials, or in
aiding in one way or another some of these processes.
We shall call the one class primary and the other
secondary industries.
Farming and mining are the chief examples of the
primaries. As to the secondaries, they are legion; and
not only are all the materials these last have to operate
upon drawn from the land, but so are the tools they work
with as well as the food the workmen consume.
It is clear that the extent of the secondary
industries will be strictly limited by the primaries;
that is, there can be no more persons engaged in working
up, shifting about and distributing materials than there
are materials (extracted from the land) for them to work
up, shift about and distribute and not only is the extent
of the secondaries determined by the extent of the
primaries, but so also are the profits in the secondaries
determined by the profits in the primaries.
Materials must be extracted (or produced) from the
land before they can be put to any further use, and men
will not leave this necessary preliminary work to take to
the secondary work unless they can make as much by the
new industry as they could by the old; and they cannot
hope to make more, because if they did, the opening in
the secondary industries being strictly limited,
competitors would at once flock in and bring their
profits down.
If profits in the primary industries are high, that
is, if the land yields abundantly, and no one steps in to
appropriate the fruits, profits in the secondaries will
be high too, for otherwise people would leave the
secondaries and betake themselves to the land.
If, on the other hand, profits in the primaries are
low that is, if either nature is niggardly or someone
(the landlord for instance) appropriates the fruits,
profits in the secondaries will be low too; for otherwise
people would leave the land and crowd into the
secondaries till they brought profits down. Now, if all
the land is held by a comparatively few people (as is the
case), then since the land is the basis of all industry,
there will be keen competition for it a competition
becoming keener year by year as the competitors multiply
and wealth increases, the result of which competition
will be that the man of average means and capacity will
have to give the very highest price for the land that he
will consent to give, rather than go without it, and this
highest price will be determined, not by the amount that
it takes out of his pocket, but by the amount it leaves
behind.
Here, for instance, are three farms of differing
fertility estimated to yield to the customary system of
farming, £200, £300, and £400 net profit
respectively. Then, if the first of these fetches, after
a pretty close competition, £100 a year, this shows
that no bidder will give more than will leave him
£100 to himself, but that the competition of the
others will not allow him to retain more; in other words,
that £100 is the lowest he will consent to keep, and
the highest he will be allowed to keep, so that £100
a year is the average profit of farming amongst farmers
of that class and means. But since he cannot hope to keep
more than £100, it does not matter to him what the
surplus may be which he is compelled to give up to his
landlord; consequently the other two farms will fetch
respectively £200 and £300. Of course it is the
rate of profit, and not the actual profit of which we are
speaking of. The £100 is only quoted as an example.
Amongst one class of farmers the reserve will be higher,
among another lower, according to their means and the
magnitude of their operations.
This is the theory, and it corresponds exactly with
the facts; for whether a farmer settles here or there,
near a market or far-off, whether he pays £100 a
year for an indifferent farm, £150 for a better, or
£200 for a better still, he finds that except by
some lucky accident his profits as a farmer remain much
the same; which shows that his rent is determined, not by
what be has to pay away, but by what he is determined to
keep; and this amount, this rate of profit, will, for
reasons already given, determine the rate of profit in
all the secondary industries, though they have no visible
connection with the land at all.
To put it compactly, the profits of industry all
around are determined by the rent of land. That amount of
profit which the worker on the land can save from his
landlord will be all that the worker at any industry can
hope to get, and it will represent that minimum margin to
which he will consent to be beaten down rather than go
without the land.
What is the minimum margin?
The applicant for the land has a certain amount of
capital (otherwise he could not be an applicant), and for
this he knows he could get interest, and he also has the
capacity to work. Consequently, the least he will
determine to keep will be what he could earn as a
labourer, plus the interest he could get on his capital.
Actually (except in the case of the poorest competitors
for the smallest and worst farms) it will be something
rather more than this, for his capital, such as it is,
gives him a certain advantage in the position. He and his
competitors being none of them in danger of immediate
want, and therefore not pressed by necessity, will have a
tendency to hold back in the bidding when it begins to
run high, and to cling to something more than the
closeness of the competition might seem to demand; and
the larger his capital the greater will be his advantage,
not only because of his greater power and stronger
inclination to hold out for better terms, but also
because the men of sufficient means to require a large
farm, such as he wants, are fewer in number, and the
competition in every way less keen and forced. Hence the
smallest and worst farms are always the highest rented,
which is only another way of saying that the profits on
them are smallest.
Still, be the farms large or small, competition will
always force rents up, and therefore profits down to the
smallest return the average applicant of his class will
consent to accept rather than go without the land.
Land, as we have said, is the basis of all industry,
and agriculture is the fundamental industry.
Everyone recognises this; and in view of the hard
struggle and hand-to-mouth existence of the farmer, all
sorts of projects are proposed to ameliorate his lot.
One party advocates protection, another the lightening
and equalising of taxation, another cheapness of labour
by assisted immigration (making the labourer the
scapegoat), another pins its faith on railways, and so
on.
Of these proposals some are good, some bad; but their
effects, whichever way they tend, will not, except for
the moment, affect the farmers' profit one way or the
other.
Let us suppose protection to be the true policy, and
raising the price of some particular article by a duty,
say meat, see what the result would be.
The rise of price in meat will produce two opposite
effects. It will immediately injure one class of farmers
and benefit another. Those who by reason of distance from
market, unsuitability of their land for grazing, or its
still greater suitability for something else, do not
fatten stock, notwithstanding the rise in price (and
these will be a very large number), will suffer a
distinct appreciable loss in increased household expenses
and increased cost of feeding their men, without any
advantage to set off; while those on the other hand, with
land specially adapted for grazing, who already made a
profit by it will make a larger profit still; and those
on land passably suited for it, who formerly made their
profit by something else, may, perhaps, change their
system, and make their profit by grazing instead of by
those other things.
But the point is, that after the first start neither
those who gain nor those who lose will be any the better
or the worse off, for their gain or loss, because at the
first renewal of their lease they will transfer the gain
or loss to their landlords.
For so long as all the land of the country is in the
hands of a comparatively few, so that there are more
farmers wanting farms than there are farms for them to
have, so long will competition force land values up to
their maximum, and rent will mean to the farmer the
utmost that he can see his way to giving for the land
rather than go without it and let another take his
place.
But for the very reason that competition is thus
already at its full stretch, it cannot be stretched any
farther, and those farmers whose narrow margin of profit
is trenched on by their increased expenses consequent on
the rise in meat will insist on having that margin
restored, and they will be able to carry their point; for
they were already giving full value for their farms, and
their farms (since they produce no more and yet cost more
to work) are now worth less, less not only to the present
occupants, but to any one else who might want to take
their place; therefore, the landlords cannot play off one
against another, and so must accept reduction.
Conversely, where the profits on land, already
profitable for grazing, have been increased by the duty,
those lands will have become just so much more valuable
and will fetch so much more rent.
So, if you made a railway to every farmer's door you
would simply make the land more valuable. Compare those
districts that have railways with those that have none.
In the former you will see a greater population:
probably, more cultivation, certainly higher rents, but
no higher farm profits; for where the carcase is there
will the eagles be gathered together; where returns are
high, thither will competitors flock. There may be no
actual bidding against each other among the applicants,
but this is only because the landlord will kindly take
that trouble off their hands. He will put up the rent as
high as he thinks he can too high at first perhaps if so
his vacant farm will soon cause him to correct his error;
but whatever the process, the result will be the
same.
So, if by assisted immigration, you reduce the cost of
labour by half, or if by mechanical inventions you enable
the farmer to do with half the number of men (which would
come to much the same thing to him) you would be simply
reducing the cost of working the land, and so increasing
the return to be got out of the land, and so increasing
the value of land, and so raising rents.
One after another labour-saving appliances have been
introduced within the last 20 years; double-furrow
ploughs, reapers and binders, horse rakes, steam
threshers, without improving the condition of the farmer
in the least. Never have there been so many aids and
appliances to industry as there are now, and never has
the struggle of the farmer been more severe.
So if you lightened taxation, or even abolished it
altogether, it would make no difference to the farmer,
beyond the moment. At present some leases stipulate that
the landlord shall pay all rates; others that the tenant
shall pay them; others again that each shall pay half,
but it is all a mere adjustment of rent. The more taxes
the less rent, and vice versa.
If the farmer pays more rent it is because he has to
pay less taxes, and whether this is owing to the landlord
paying them, or to there being none to pay, makes not the
least difference to the farmer.
So if nature herself instead of the mere instruments
of production were improved; if the soil were suddenly
doubled in fertility; if the sun could be got to shine
and the rain to fall exactly when and where it was
wanted; if all weeds and plagues were abolished, it would
come to the same thing, and for the same reasons.
The Press is continually preaching that the fault of
things all lies with the farmer. He should be more
industrious or more provident, he should know something
about chemistry, he should buy the best appliances, and
use the most advanced methods. It is very good advice in
its way perhaps, but it does not touch the question in
the least.
If you passed every farmer through a technical
college, if by a network of meteorological stations and
commercial agencies you supplied him every day with a
forecast of the weather, and the state of the markets, if
you supplied him gratis with all the best machinery, if
you trained him in habits of industry and economy,
foresight and skill, till you made him as much superior
to what he now is as a steam thresher is superior to a
flail, you would enormously increase his efficiency no
doubt, but you would not add one farthing to his profits.
The whole benefit would go as before to the landlord, and
for the same reasons. You would not have eased the
pressure of competition, but only have put it into the
power of every competitor to offer more. Still, as
before, rent would mean the utmost the farmer could be
forced to bid for the land rather than go without it.
Granting that there are many things that swallow up
much of the surplus that would otherwise come to the
farmer; heavy taxes, injudicious laws, bad roads, scarce
labour; all these matter nothing (as a great writer says)
so long as behind them stands something which swallows
all that is left. So long as that something stands
waiting with open mouth, abolishing any of these only
leaves so much more for it to swallow.
Some people shrink from these conclusions saying, "it
is a hard doctrine" (as if truths could be dodged by
shrinking from them.)
Others say that the remedy is the fixing of a fair
rent.
But what is meant by a fair rent?
If Brown objects to his present rent of £100,
saying it is too high, and should be reduced to £80,
and yet Jones is standing by prepared to give £100,
why should the rent be reduced? Why should Jones be
forbidden to have what he is ready to give £100 for,
in order that Brown should have it for £80? It is
fair neither to Jones nor to the landlord whatever it may
be to Brown.
What would Brown think if Jones objected to pay the
5s. for his wheat that he had agreed to pay, saying it
ought to be reduced to 4s., when Smith is standing by
ready to give 5s.?
In the open market a "fair price" has no meaning.
Hudibras' saying still holds good that "The value of a
thing is just as much as it will bring."
There is a remedy for this evil, and a very simple
one, but it is not the fixing of a fair rent.
"But," it will be said, "all farmers are not tenants.
Many own the land they occupy." True; but all that this
proves is, not that the preceding remarks are incorrect,
but that there is a certain class to whom they do not
apply. For the present we will let the exception go for
what it is worth. What I shall undertake to show
by-and-bye is that it is worth nothing.
But we shall have to present one or two other
considerations at some length before we are prepared to
deal fully with this. For the present we will let it
stand over, only remarking that in farming, tenants are
the rule, occupying owners the exception, and that the
exceptions grow steadily fewer year by year. Not only in
Tasmania, but in all the other colonies, in the United
States, and wherever, in short, land is recognised as
absolute private property, the divorce between occupation
and ownership is proceeding apace, and the very
institution which was designed to secure to the producer
the full fruits of his labour is becoming the means by
which he is compelled to surrender them to another. ...
read the
whole paper.
Louis Post: Outlines
of Louis F. Post's Lectures, with Illustrative Notes and
Charts (1894)
c. Significance of the Upward Tendency of
Rent
Now, what is the meaning of this tendency of Rent to
rise with social progress, while Wages tend to fall? Is
it not a plain promise that if Rent be treated as common
property, advances in productive power shall be steps in
the direction of realizing through orderly and natural
growth those grand conceptions of both the socialist and
the individualist, which in the present condition of
society are justly ranked as Utopian? Is it not likewise
a plain warning that if Rent be treated as private
property, advances in productive power will be steps in
the direction of making slaves of the many laborers, and
masters of a few land-owners? Does it not mean that
common ownership of Rent is in harmony with natural law,
and that its private appropriation is disorderly and
degrading? When the cause of Rent and the tendency
illustrated in the preceding chart are considered in
connection with the self-evident truth that God made the
earth for common use and not for private monopoly, how
can a contrary inference hold? Caused and increased by
social growth, 97 the benefits of which should be common,
and attaching to land, the just right to which is equal,
Rent must be the natural fund for public expenses. 98
97. Here, far away from civilization, is
a solitary settler. Getting no benefits from
government, he needs no public revenues, and none of
the land about him has any value. Another settler
comes, and another, until a village appears. Some
public revenue is then required. Not much, but some.
And the land has a little value, only a little; perhaps
just enough to equal the need for public revenue. The
village becomes a town. More revenues are needed, and
land values are higher. It becomes a city. The public
revenues required are enormous, and so are the land
values.
98. Society, and society alone, causes
Rent. Rising with the rise, advancing with the growth,
and receding with the decline of society, it measures
the earning power of society as a whole as
distinguished from that of the individuals. Wages, on
the other hand, measure the earning power of the
individuals as distinguished from that of society as a
whole. We have distinguished the parts into which
Wealth is distributed as Wages and Rent; but it would
be correct, indeed it is the same thing, to regard all
wealth as earnings, and to distinguish the two kinds as
Communal Earnings and Individual Earnings. How, then,
can there be any question as to the fund from which
society should be supported? How can it be justly
supported in any other way than out of its own
earnings?
If there be at all such a thing as design in the
universe — and who can doubt it? — then has
it been designed that Rent, the earnings of the
community, shall be retained for the support of the
community, and that Wages, the earnings of the
individual, shall be left to the individual in proportion
to the value of his service. This is the divine law,
whether we trace it through complex moral and economic
relations, or find it in the eighth commandment.
...
Q18. How would you reach the bondholder, or the
man with money alone?
A. Why should we wish to reach him if his bonds or his
money represent labor products to which he has honestly
acquired a just title? This question is a legitimate
offspring of the plundering theory that men should be
taxed according to their ability to pay, the merits of
which are considered on pages 7-9. It is a question which
may also have been suggested by the fact that
"bondholders" and "men of money" are so often men who
have special privileges which coin money for them. There
is a feeling that it would be unfair to allow such
special privileges to escape taxation. It would be. But
inquiry will show that the most important of these
privileges rest in the ownership of land, and that the
"bondholders" and "men of money" whom the questioner
probably has in mind, are in fact great landlords; that
is to say, that their fortunes are really based upon
land. When land values were taxed, the great
source of unearned incomes — land monopoly —
would be practically abolished, and bondholders
and men of money would be only those who earn what they
have. Such property no man of honest instincts should
wish to expropriate. ...
Q21. Do not the benefits of good government
increase the value of houses as well as of
land?
A. No. Houses are never worth any more than it
costs to reproduce them. Good government tends to
diminish the cost of house building; how, then, can good
government increase the value of houses? You are
confused by the fact that houses, being attached to land,
seem to increase in value, when it is the land and not
the house that really increases. It is the same mistake
that a somewhat noted economic teacher, who advocates
protection as his specialty, made when he tried to show
that there is an "unearned increment" to houses as well
as to lands. He did so by instancing a lot of vacant land
which had risen in value from $5000 to $10,000, and
comparing it with a house on a neighboring lot which, as
he said, had also increased in value from $5000 to
$10,000. At the moment when he wrote, the house to which
he referred could have been reproduced for $5000; and had
he been capable of thinking out a proposition he must
have discovered that it was the lot on which the house
stood, and not the house itself, which had increased in
value.
... read the
book
Upton Sinclair: The
Consequences of Land Speculation are Tenantry and Debt on
the Farms, and Slums and Luxury in the Cities
I know of a woman — I have never had the
pleasure of making her acquaintance, because she lives in
a lunatic asylum, which does not happen to be on my
visiting list. This woman has been mentally incompetent
from birth. She is well taken care of, because her father
left her when he died the income of a large farm on the
outskirts of a city. The city has since grown and the
land is now worth, at conservative estimate, about twenty
million dollars. It is covered with office buildings, and
the greater part of the income, which cannot be spent by
the woman, is piling up at compound interest. The woman
enjoys good health, so she may be worth a hundred million
dollars before she dies.
I choose this case because it is one about which there
can be no disputing; this woman has never been able to do
anything to earn that twenty million dollars. And if a
visitor from Mars should come down to study the
situation, which would he think was most insane, the
unfortunate woman, or the society which compels thousands
of people to wear themselves to death in order to pay her
the income of twenty million dollars?
The fact that this woman is insane makes it easy to
see that she is not entitled to the "unearned increment"
of the land she owns. But how about all the other people
who have bought up and are holding for speculation the
most desirable land? The value of this land increases,
not because of anything these owners do — not
because of any useful service they render to the
community — but purely because the community as a
whole is crowding into that neighborhood and must have
use of the land.
The speculator who bought this land thinks that he
deserves the increase, because he guessed the fact that
the city was going to grow that way. But it seems clear
enough that his skill in guessing which way the community
was going to grow, however useful that skill may be to
himself, is not in any way useful to the community. The
man may have planted trees, or built roads, and put in
sidewalks and sewers; all that is useful work, and for
that he should be paid. But should he be paid for
guessing what the rest of us were going to need?
Before you answer, consider the consequences of this
guessing game. The consequences of land speculation are
tenantry and debt on the farms, and slums and luxury in
the cities. A great part of the necessary land is held
out of use, and so the value of all land continually
increases, until the poor man can no longer own a home.
The value of farm land also increases; so year by year
more independent farmers are dispossessed, because they
cannot pay interest on their mortgages. So the land
becomes a place of serfdom, that land described by the
poet, "where wealth accumulates and men decay." The great
cities fill up with festering slums, and a small class of
idle parasites are provided with enormous fortunes, which
they do not have to earn, and which they cannot
intelligently spend. ...
In Philadelphia, as in all our great cities, are
enormously wealthy families, living on hereditary incomes
derived from crowded slums. Here and there among these
rich men is one who realizes that he has not earned what
he is consuming, and that it has not brought him
happiness, and is bringing still less to his children.
Such men are casting about for ways to invest their money
without breeding idleness and parasitism. Some of them
might be grateful to learn about this enclave plan, and
to visit the lovely village of Arden, and see what its
people are doing to make possible a peaceful and joyous
life, even in this land of bootleggers and jazz
orchestras. ... read
the whole article
Mason Gaffney: Nonpoint Pollution:
Tractable Solutions to Intractable Problems
The Special Challenge to Economic
Thinking
The Search for Surrogates
Sources of Nonpoint Pollution
What Problems are Created?
What Problems are Unsolved by Excise Taxes on
Surrogates?
The Case of Forestry
The Case of Urban Settlement
The Case of Agriculture
The Common Theme from Forest, City and
Farm
Solutions
THE SEARCH FOR
SURROGATES
The frustrated economist, unable to tax runoff,
still has a bag of tricks. He looks for surrogates
to tax, something in a sack or bottle that moves through
a market: Aha! pesticides, fertilizers, salt, they'll do
nicely to tax. Thus we will "internalize the
externalities" and have "proper pricing of inputs" to
create incentives for correct "trade‑offs" in the
"production functions," and we're nearly home.
Well, halfway home.
Well, we've made a start. A few problems
remain. One is that a plurality of economists don't
like the effluent charge approach anyway, even for point
sources. They follow Coase and prefer to grant
pollution entitlements to be traded in a free
market. Incredibly (to me) this view has
prevailed.
In principle they profess not to care what worthy
few get the original entitlements, but in practise a
select company of ancient and honorable polluters get
them. We now call these "offset rights," a new form
of property. In the L.A. Basin (South Coast Air
Quality Management District), a few have grown rich by
establishing their respective histories of pollution
which they can now sell to others who wish to continue
this wholesome tradition. The demonstration effect
on those contemplating new and as yet unregulated forms
of pollution may be imagined.
Those needing air to breathe? Well,
according to the modern philosophers they can enter the
market, buy up offset rights and retire them. Thus
is fulfilled Robert Ingersoll's forecast a century ago
that if some corporation could bottle the air they would
charge us to breathe. It seems to confirm this dour
warning from a former Secretary of
Labor:
"We soon discovered ... the danger of
allowing economic policy to be dominated by business or
financial interests or, which usually comes to the same
thing, orthodox economic analysis." (Marshall,
p.ix) (emphasis added)
The public has learned what is being done to it,
finally, and is rebelling at the Coase logic, which only
a Chicago economist could love. Offset rights are
on the ropes. To simplify, therefore, I am not
going to speculate how Coase might be applied to
nonpoint, but just ignore it. I will treat effluent
charges, and taxes on surrogates, as the conventional
economic solution to pollution.
But before leaving this there is
a lesson in it. The holders of offset rights,
whether "ancient and honorable" or "innocent purchasers,"
are demanding compensation. Never mind about asking
them to pay the victims; they demand payment to
stop! (Polakovic,
1987)
They will probably get it, for if
the system be changed, there will be a taking of
something, which they claim is property. Such is
the force of the Great Secular Superstition, that
unearned gains are sacred, even those originating with
something as unworthy as dumping crud on other human
beings. This superstition is why effective control
seems so expensive. My remarks will not be
instructed by it.
...
This perversion does not occur by accident.
Spread and sprawl in forestry, cities and agriculture are
common results of the dominant force driving American
politics, the quest for unearned increments to land
value. ... Read the entire
article
Walter Rybeck: The Uncertain Future of
the Metropolis
The single element that makes me apprehensive
about the future of our cities is our land system.
Tentacles of our misguided land policies are choking
almost every vital aspect of metropolitan life. This is
doubly worrisome, because the full dimensions of the land
problem have barely surfaced in the public consciousness.
To put it in the vernacular, most of us
don't know what's eating us.
We have scarcely begun to identify the causes of
today's city land problems. This is not to denigrate the
legions of good folk -- officials and citizens alike --
who are trying desperately to cope with the daily
disasters. But without a better notion of what is
producing these disasters, we are unlikely to stem the
flood.
A major problem, certainly, is
our distorted land system that operates around the clock
and around the calendar, and under the full sanction of
the law. It rips off the poor, saps small business, and
deprives municipalities of their rightful
revenue.
The people as a whole create land
values, not only by their presence, but also through
participation in government, as taxpayers.
Schools, firehouses, streets, police, water lines -- the
whole gamut of public works and services that enhance a
neighborhood are converted into higher land values. The
taxpayers of the entire country, through federal aid for
our multi-billion-dollar Metrorail project, have been
boosting Washington, D.C. land values
mightily.
Not all land values are manmade.
Inherent qualities also give land special
advantages: fertile soils in farming districts,
scenic views in residential areas, subsurface riches of
coal, oil, and minerals. None of us, as landlords,
tenants, or governments, can lay claim to having created
these values. The people who have been drawing up an
international law of the Seas have characterized these natural endowments as "the
common heritage of mankind", where no people,
individually or collectively, produce these land values,
it is difficult to argue with the
conclusion that they belong to all people
equally.
If the institution of private property has a sound
foundation, and I believe it does, then it rests on the
principle that people have a right to reap what they sow,
to retain for themselves what they themselves produce or
earn. Land values, produced by all of society, and by
nature, do not conform to this prescription.
...
Decade after decade, billions of dollars in urban
land values are being siphoned off by a narrowing class
that has no ethical or economic claim to them. To be
outraged when a few ghetto dwellers, in an occasional
frenzy of despair, engage in looting on a relatively
miniscule scale, but to remain indifferent to this
massive, wholesale looting, is worse than hypocritical.
It is to ignore a catastrophic social maladjustment, more
severe, I believe, than anything the U.S. has experienced
since slavery. ...
But I sense that we are drifting rapidly towards a
landlord-dominated society. ...
Before that happens, the opportunity awaits to see
whether a reasonably free economy can still be made to
work. Unless we tackle the land question, and the looting
of America, that game may be forfeited.
The future of the metropolis is uncertain. The
choice is ours. We can intervene in the way society is
now headed, to preserve the American dream. Or, we can
continue along the present path and await the American
nightmare. Read the whole
article
Mason Gaffney: Sounding the Revenue
Potential of Land: Fifteen Lost Elements
Taxing unearned increments as
current income. There is a swelling of land
gains as a component of income. Gains on land value are a
form of land rent, eminently taxable. Great is the need
for objective economists to establish the taxability of
capital gains, to show how to tax unrealized gains as
they accrue. It’s surprisingly easy: levy a
property tax based on the market value of appreciating
land. That is just what the property tax was, before the
current movement to limit assessed valuations to
capitalized income from current use only. Read the whole
article
Mason Gaffney: The
Taxable Capacity of Land
Those getting the cold shower, meantime, may
resist it. In California, the land of extremes, we got
Howard Jarvis and Prop. 13. This Constitutional
Amendment capped the property tax rate at 1%, and
virtually froze assessed values until land sold.
Then the boom really went wild. I myself, after
campaigning hard against Jarvis, unexpectedly made
$200,000 in a few months after it passed. Buyers were
chasing me around the block, just to buy a scrap of
land I happened to have in the right place at the right
time. It was blind luck, but the money was as good as
though I had earned it honestly: better, in fact,
because 60% of the gain was not even reportable as
taxable income. It was a once-in-a-lifetime experience,
but buyers and sellers came to regard it as normal, and
only fair. They saw regular annual increments as a
divine right of property. For a few mad years, they
were. ...
Read
the whole
article
California homeowners are wallowing in
unearned increments beyond the dreams of avarice, while its
governments are courting bankruptcy.
Warren Buffett dared point this out, and overnight
changed from the Oracle of Omaha into the Numbskull of
Nebraska because he does not understand the "reality of
California politics," the oxymoron du jour.
Most candidates for Governor fled like
startled deer. Buffett's sponsor, well-tailored Mr.
Muscles, recalled meeting a tearful widow who said she
would have been taxed out of her home were it not for Prop
13. Poor thing, her home had risen in value. No one asked
her name, or whether she knew what she was talking about,
or had her claims audited - being a tearful widow "on a
fixed income" insulates one from reality checks. The press
chimed in with pix of poster oldsters, gazing from their
multi-million dollar perches over the blue Pacific,
fretting about Buffett's solecism and its possible effect
on them, never mind anyone else.
Fact is, unearned increments ARE
income, at the time they accrue. Illiquid? They are
better than cash income because you can turn them into
cash by borrowing on them, and pay no income tax on the
cash. If you have trouble with that, the tax man
himself will arrange it for you by placing a tax lien on
your appreciated home, rather than foreclose and evict
you. This helps explain why we never actually see one of
these evicted widows suffering from unearned increments
-- they are maudlin figments for mythmakers. The evictees
we do see are renters who couldn't pay, and had no equity
to mortgage. Who cries for them? ...
Governor Gray Davis, supposedly fighting to close
a deficit, chimed in endorsing Prop 13, citing the
mythical widow again to explain why non-residential
property, about 2/3 of the tax base, should enjoy low
rates. Faced with a negative poll, he backed right down
from his "land tax on wheels," the higher vehicle
registration fee.
- No one has said a word about a severance tax
on oil and gas, although California is the only major
producing state without one.
- No one has crusaded for a severance tax on
water withdrawals, although it would solve both our
revenue and water crises in one stroke.
- No one has said word one about taxing the
taboo lands used for golfing, timber, or farming. ...
Read the whole
article
Michael Hudson: The
Lies of the Land: How and why land gets undervalued
Turning land-value gains into
capital gains
Hiding the free lunch
Two appraisal methods
How land gets a negative value!
Where did all the land value go?
A curious asymmetry
Site values as the economy's "credit sink"
Immortally aging buildings
Real estate industry's priorities
THE FREE LUNCH Its cost to citizens
Its cost to the economy
Hiding the free lunch
BAUDELAIRE OBSERVED that the devil wins at the
point where he convinces humanity that he does not exist.
The Financial, Insurance and Real Estate (FIRE)
sectors seem to have adopted a kindred philosophy that
what is not quantified and reported will be invisible to
the tax collector, leaving more to be pledged for
mortgage credit and paid out as interest. It appears to
have worked. To academic theorists as
well., breathlessly focused on their own particular
hypothetical world, the magnitude of land rent and
land-price gains has become invisible.
But not to investors. They are
out to pick a property whose location value increases
faster rate than the interest charges, and they want to
stay away from earnings on man-made capital -- like
improvements. That's earned income, not the "free lunch"
they get from land value increases.
Chicago School economists insist that no free
lunch exists. But when one begins to look beneath the
surface of national income statistics and the national
balance sheet of assets and liabilities, one can see that
modern economies are all about obtaining a free lunch.
However, to make this free ride go all the faster,
it helps if the rest of the world does
not see that anyone is getting the proverbial something
for nothing - what classical economists called
unearned income, most
characteristically in the form of land rent. You start by using a method of appraising that
undervalues the real income producer, land. Here's how
it's done.
Read the whole
article
Herbert J. G. Bab: Property Tax -- Cause of
Unemployment (circa 1964)
Ricardo believed that ground rents and the value
of land have a tendency to rise continuously and that
this benefits solely the landowners. The progress of industrialization and urbanization
in the second half of the 19th century resulted in a
rapid increase in the value of urban land and the owners
of such land reaped tremendous profits. This led John
Stuart Mill to observe, that "Only the landowners grow
richer, as it were in their sleep without working,
risking and economizing". He called for the taxation of
land in order to recapture the unearned increment
accruing to the land owners.
The apostle of land taxation is Henry George. In
his famous book
Progress and Poverty he develops his single
tax theory. He tries to show that poverty and
unemployment and other evils are caused by the land
monopolists. Henry George's theory is similar to that
developed by John Stuart Mill. Land values are based on
ground rents which are created by the community and not
by the land owners. Therefore the community is justified
in recapturing these rents by a single tax on land.
For these reasons increases in land values can be
prevented by taxing land at an appropriate rate. Yet
urban land values have increased tremendously during
recent years. For instance in Los
Angeles county the assessed value of land increased from
$1,972 millions in 1952 to $4,002 millions in 1962, an
increase of a little over 100%. The assessed
values, are supposed to represent 25% of the market
value. Thus the unearned increment in
land values during this period amounted to not less than
$8 billions. Even this figure is an understatement
because it is based on assessed values and land is
greatly underassessed. While land values have risen by
about 10% yearly, property taxes assessed on land
averaged about 1.5%. Thus a person owning vacant or
underimproved land would have earned about 8 1/2% per
year just by withholding land from its proper
use. Read the
whole
article
Henry George: Justice
the Object -- Taxation the Means (1890)
We used to be confronted constantly by the
question: "Well, after you have divided the land up, how
do you propose to keep it divided?" We don't meet that
question now. The Single Tax has, at least, this great
merit: it suggests our method; it shows the way we would
travel — the simple way of abolishing all taxes,
save one tax upon land values. Now, mark: One tax upon
land values.
We do not propose a tax upon land, as
people who misapprehend us constantly say. We do not
propose a tax upon land; we propose a tax upon land values,
or what in the terminology of political economy is termed
rent; that is to say, the value which attaches to land
irrespective of any improvements — in or on it; that
value which attaches to land, not by reason of anything
that the user or improver of land does — not by
reason of any individual exertion of labour, but by reason
of the growth and improvement of the community. A tax that
will take up what John Stuart Mill called the unearned
increment; that is to say, that increment of wealth which
comes to the owner of land, not as a user; that comes
whether he be a resident or an absentee; whether he be
engaged in the active business of life; whether he be an
idiot and whether he be a child; that growth of value that
we have seen in our own times so astonishingly great in
this city; that has made sand lots, lying in the same
condition that they were thousands of years ago, worth
enormous sums, without anyone putting any exertion of
labour or any expenditure of capital upon them.
Now, the distinction between a tax on
land and a tax on land values may at first seem an idle
one, but it is a most important one. A tax on land that is
to say, a tax upon all land — would ultimately become
a condition to the use of land; would therefore fall upon
labour, would increase prices, and be borne by the general
community. But a tax on land values cannot fall on all
land, because all land is not of value; it can only fall on
valuable land, and on valuable land in proportion to its
value; therefore, it can no more become a tax on labour
than can a tax upon the value of special privileges of any
kind. It can merely take from the individual, not the
earnings of the individual, but that
premium which, as society grows and improves, attaches to
the use of land of superior quality.
Read the entire article Winston
Churchill: The
People's Land
...If the railway makes greater profits, it is
usually because it carries more goods and more
passengers. If a doctor or a lawyer enjoys a better
practice, it is because the doctor attends more patients
and more exacting patients, and because the lawyer pleads
more suits in the courts and more important suits. At
every stage the doctor or the lawyer is giving service in
return for his fees, and if the service is too poor or
the fees are too high, other doctors and other lawyers
can come freely into competition. There is constant
service, there is constant competition; there is no
monopoly, there is no injury to the public interest,
there is no impediment to the general progress.
Unearned increment
Fancy comparing these healthy processes
with the enrichment which comes to the landlord who
happens to own a plot of land on the outskirts or at the
centre of one of our great cities, who watches the busy
population around him making the city larger, richer,
more convenient, more famous every day, and all the while
sits still and does nothing. Roads are made, streets are
made, railway services are improved, electric light turns
night into day, electric trams glide swiftly to and fro,
water is brought from reservoirs a hundred miles off in
the mountains -- and all the while the landlord sits
still.To not one of those
improvements does the land monopolist as a land
monopolist contribute, and yet by every one of them the
value of his land is sensibly enhanced. He renders
no service to the community, he contributes nothing to
the general welfare; he contributes nothing even to the
process from which his own enrichment is derived. If the
land were occupied by shops or by dwellings, the
municipality at least would secure the rates upon them in
aid of the general fund, but the land may be unoccupied,
undeveloped, it may be what is called 'ripening' --
ripening at the expense of the whole city, of the whole
country, for the unearned increment of its owner. Roads
perhaps may have to be diverted to avoid this forbidden
area. The merchant going to his office, the artisan going
to his work, have to make a detour or pay a tram fare to
avoid it. The citizens are losing their chance of
developing the land, the city is losing its rates, the
State is losing its taxes which would have accrued if the
natural development had taken place; and that share has
to be replaced at the expense of the other ratepayers and
taxpayers, and the nation as a whole is losing in the
competition of the world -- the hard and growing
competition of the world -- both in time and money. And
all the while the land monopolist has only to sit still
and watch complacently his property multiplying in value,
sometimes manifold, without either effort or contribution
on his part; and that is justice!
Every one of those improvements is effected by
the labour and at the cost of other people. Many of the
most important are effected at the cost of the
municipality and of the ratepayers.
Unearned increment reaped in
exact proportion to the disservice done. But let
us follow the process a little further. The population of
the city grows and grows still larger year by year, the
congestion in the poorer quarters becomes acute, rents
and rates rise hand in hand, and thousands of families
are crowded into one-roomed tenements. There are 120,000
persons living in one-roomed tenements in Glasgow alone
at the present time. At last the land becomes ripe for
sale -- that means that the price is too tempting to be
resisted any longer -- and then, and not till then, it is
sold by the yard or by the inch at ten times, or twenty
times, or even fifty times, its agricultural value, on
which alone hitherto it has been rated for the public
service. The greater the population around the land, the
greater the injury which they have sustained by its
protracted denial, the more inconvenience which has been
caused to everybody, the more serious the loss in
economic strength and activity, the larger will be the
profit of the landlord when the sale is finally
accomplished. In fact, you may say that the unearned
increment on the land is on all fours with the profit
gathered by one of those American speculators who
engineer a corner in corn, or meat, or cotton, or some
other vital commodity, and that the unearned increment in
land is reaped by the land monopolist in exact
proportion, not to the service but to the disservice
done. ...
Now let the Manchester Ship Canal tell its tale
about the land. It has a story to tell which is just as
simple and just as pregnant as its story about Free
Trade. When it was resolved to build the Canal, the first
thing that had to be done was to buy the land. Before the
resolution to build the Canal was taken, the land on
which the Canal flows -- or perhaps I should say 'stands'
-- was, in the main, agricultural land, paying rates on
an assessment from 30s. to L2 an acre. I am told that
4,495 acres of land purchased fell within that
description out of something under 5,000 purchased
altogether. Immediately after the decision, the 4,495
acres were sold for L777,000 sterling -- or an average of
L172 an acre -- that is to say, five or six times the
agricultural value of the land and the value on which it
had been rated for public purposes.
Now what had the landowner done for the community;
what enterprise had he shown; what service had he
rendered; what capital had he risked in order that he
should gain this enormous multiplication of the value of
his property! I will tell you in one word what he had
done. Can you guess it! Nothing.
But it was not only the owners of the land that
was needed for making the Canal, who were automatically
enriched. All the surrounding land either having a
frontage on the Canal or access to it rose and rose
rapidly, and splendidly, in value. By the stroke of a
fairy wand, without toil, without risk, without even a
half-hour's thought many landowners in Salford, Eccles,
Stretford, Irlam, Warrington Runcorn, etc., found
themselves in possession of property which had trebled,
quadrupled, quintupled in value.
Apart from the high prices which were paid, there
was a heavy bill for compensation, severance,
disturbance, and injurious affection where no land was
taken -- injurious affection, namely, raising the land
not taken many times in value -- all this was added to
the dead-weight cost of construction. All this was a
burden on those whose labour skill, and capital created
this great public work. Much of this land today is still
rated at ordinary agricultural value, and in order to
make sure that no injustice is done, in order to make
quite certain that these landowners are not injured by
our system of government, half their rates are, under the
Agricultural Rates Act, paid back to them. The balance is
made up by you. The land is still rising in value, and
with every day's work that every man in this
neighbourhood does and with every addition to the
prosperity of Manchester and improvement of this great
city, the land is further enhanced in
value.
The shareholders and the
ratepayers I have told you what
happened to the landowners. Let us see what happened to
the shareholders and the
ratepayers who found the money. The ordinary
shareholders, who subscribed eight millions, have had no
dividend yet. The Corporation loan of five millions
interest on which is borne on the rates each year, had,
until 1907, no return upon its capital. A return has come
at last, and no doubt the future prospects are good; but
there was a long interval -- even for the corporation.
These are the men who did the work. These are the men who
put up the money. I want to ask you a question. Do you
think it would be very unfair if the owners of all this
automatically created land value due to the growth of the
city, to the enterprise of the community, and to the
sacrifices made by the shareholders -- do you think it
would have been very unfair, if they had been made to pay
a proportion, at any rate, of the unearned increment
which they secured, back to the city and the community?
... Read the whole piece
Bill Batt: Painless
Taxation
Abstract Real tax reform could
do away with those taxes that are resented by the large
proportion of our population. We could replace all taxes
on wages and on interest by instead taxing economic rent.
Rent is windfall income; it is income that arises not
from the efforts of any person or corporation; it comes
about as a surplus gain from common social enterprise.
There is ample moral warrant for society to lay claim to
that which it has created, as well as to that which no
individual or party has earned. Analysis increasingly
makes clear that economic rent in all its forms is far
larger than official government figures indicate; in fact
it is likely sufficient to supplant all current taxes on
labor and capital (wages and interest) which are
acknowledged to have so many negative effects. Recovering
economic rent in all its manifestations by taxing its
various bases actually can foster economic performance
and yield other benefits that make it the natural source
of revenue for governments. Such a tax is essentially
painless. ...
The Tax Base
The next concern should be upon what base to impose a
tax — not about taxing whom but taxing what. There
are only three possibilities, as all revenue streams
necessarily come from one of three factors of economic
production —
1) upon resources found raw in nature (what was
classically called land),
2) upon our labor, or
3) upon things created by human hands or minds
(capital).
No other source exists; every possible tax must be on
one or some combination of these parts. Each of these
factors has its price: the price of land is counted in
economic rent; the price of labor is in wages, and the
price of capital (its liquid form) is in interest.
Any tax on capital has its downside effects, so that
taxing savings causes people to save less, taxing
consumption causes people to buy less, and taxing
buildings causes people to build less. The result is that
economists as well as businessmen usually frown upon
taxing capital. Another alternative is to tax labor, but
it is even more widely understood that taxing labor
normally discourages people from working as much as they
would in the absence of a tax. From this comes sentiment
against taxing labor, even though for want of any
alternative, people have today commonly come to accept it
as a necessity. But electing to tax labor, just as for
taxing capital, forecloses a discussion of the virtues of
taxing land — not necessarily land as earth, but
rather land as location. Yet land rent is the most
attractive tax base of all, as rent is not earned; it is
windfall income, entirely the result of being well
situated in any market of scarce natural resources and
where community demand (rather than one's own efforts)
leads to an appreciation of that land's price. To be sure
many people have learned to position themselves in
situations where a land's market value is likely to rise
— indeed these people come to think of themselves
as astute investors. But the fact is that that market
gain is not of their own doing at all; it is the result
of common enterprise creating a surplus that comes to
settle on land sites. An investment in land, in any form
it might take, is speculation in greater or lesser
degree.
Land in all its forms is a tax base that also conforms
well to all the classic principles of sound tax theory as
enumerated above. Land is classically taken to mean not
just surfaces of the earth but places in time, in space,
in any medium whether it be solid, liquid or gas, and
even as a form of light, in the electromagnetic spectrum,
and in life forms. One needs to return to 19th century
classical economic definitions of the factors of
production to appreciate the separate significance of
land as it was understood in its manifold forms. One
should ask how it is that land, so important to 19th
century classical economic theory, has been given so
little attention today in neoclassical economics. This is
a story only now recovered from the dusty archives of
academic economic history. Once understood and
appreciated, it may be one of the greatest, if very
silent, political revolutions of world
history.[4] ... read the whole
article
Bill
Batt: The Nexus of
Transportation, Economic Rent, and Land Use
What is Land
Rent?
John Houseman, an actor perhaps most widely known
as Professor Kingsfield in the long-running TV series,
The Paper Chase, later became the pitchman for Smith
Barney. In that advertisement, his tag line was "We make
money the old-fashioned way -- we earn it."
That we should earn our money rather than live off
the efforts of others seems a simple enough moral tenet.
But it seems to have lost its cogency in contemporary
economic thought. More than a century ago John Stuart
Mill noted that
Landlords grow richer in their
sleep without working, risking or economizing. The
increase in the value of land, arising as it does from
the efforts of an entire community, should belong to the
community and not to the individual who might hold
title.(1)
Today, on the other hand, the
unearned surplus which classical economists called
rent attaches to monopoly titles -- largely the
scarce goods and services of nature like locational
sites, and has totally disappeared from economic
calculus. Yet this is the primary vehicle by which wealth
is captured by economic elites. If government recaptured
the socially-created economic rent from land sites that
comes from the investment of the collective community, we
could eliminate other taxes that are both more onerous
and create a drag on the economy that makes us all
poorer. There are many websites that explain how this can
be done, ways that not only beget greater economic
efficiency but also bring about economic
justice.(2) The
surplus economic rent that derives from community effort
is its rightful entitlement.
Where does economic rent most tend to lodge? In
the center of cities where people are. And also proximate
to heavy social investments -- such as railroad and metro
stations, public and office buildings, hotels and
conference centers, and anywhere there is high traffic in
personal or market exchanges. The land value in New York
City is higher than all the rest of the New York state
combined, even though it is only a minute fraction of the
area. One 9-acre site south of the United Nations
Building was recently sold to a developer intent on
building luxury condominiums facing the East River. That
site sold for $680 million, and would have been higher
had the existing structure, an obsolete power plant, not
have to be razed.(3) Land values in any given area
tend to rise and fall together, and tend also to form a
contour somewhat comparable to a topographical survey
map. In a city's center are the highest value locations,
analogous to a mountain peak. Once one departs from that
center, land values fall in direct proportion to the
value of their use, made more or less attractive by
whatever social attributes are provided in the proximate
areas. Two illustrations from small and medium sized
cities in the United States illustrate the point. ...
read the whole article
Bill Batt: The
Compatibility of Georgist Economics and Ecological
Economics
As with all nineteenth century moral philosophers,
Henry George subscribed to a belief in natural law. The
natural order of things as he saw it required that land
be held in usufruct and that rent from such should be
returned to society. The theory was inspired by his
deeply religious roots and grounded in his reading of the
prominent thinkers that predated him. The natural order
was also a moral order, and the failure to comply with
the order of nature and society as he saw it was a
perversion of justice. The fruits of the land belonged to
everyone, just as the fruits of one’s own labor
were uniquely one’s own. Since one owned
one’s body, one was entitled to keep the product of
one’s physical efforts. Society had no more right
to confiscate the earnings of one’s sweat and brow
than it ought to leave in the hands of rich landowners
the rent that was everyone’s inherent birthright to
be shared. There were just and unjust
taxes, and the only just tax was that which grew out of
rent, of the unearned increment that visited certain land
sites as windfall gains because of the efforts and
investments by the community. Income and excise
taxes were unjust and confiscatory — even theft, as
especially were tariffs. Taxing or collecting land rent
alone was the means of ending poverty and restoring
progress. Indeed many Georgists reject use of the word
tax entirely, preferring instead to talk instead about
rent collection. There is even a lapel button Georgists
use that says “Abolish all taxes; collect ground
rent instead.”... read the whole
article
Bill Batt: How the
Railroads Got Us On the Wrong Economic Track
In classical economics, the definition of capital
grew out of labor mixed with earlier capital. Land, by
conventional definition, was not capital, nor was it a
component of wealth. Rather land was its own category.
Conflating land into capital allowed land rent to be
hidden and diluted in ways so that the unearned increment
arising from social improvements fell to speculators
rather than being returned to society in rent....
read the whole article
Mason Gaffney: Nonpoint Pollution:
Tractable Solutions to Intractable Problems
The public has learned what is being done to it,
finally, and is rebelling at the Coase logic, which only
a Chicago economist could love. Offset rights are
on the ropes. To simplify, therefore, I am not
going to speculate how Coase might be applied to
nonpoint, but just ignore it. I will treat effluent
charges, and taxes on surrogates, as the conventional
economic solution to pollution.
But before leaving this there is a lesson in
it. The holders of offset
rights, whether "ancient and honorable" or "innocent
purchasers," are demanding compensation. Never mind
about asking them to pay the victims; they demand payment
to stop! (Polakovic, 1987)
They will probably get it, for if
the system be changed, there will be a taking of
something, which they claim is property.
Such is the force of the Great Secular
Superstition, that unearned gains are sacred, even those
originating with something as unworthy as dumping crud on
other human beings. This superstition is why
effective control seems so expensive. My remarks
will not be instructed by it.
...
THE COMMON THEME FROM FOREST,
CITY AND FARM
Market failure, public programs and perverse
incentives in the land market create a gross bias towards
spreading out too much. This aggravates otherwise
fairly tractable runoff problems. The more Tierra
Desnuda, the more runoff.
This perversion does not occur by accident.
Spread and sprawl in forestry, cities and agriculture are
common results of the dominant force driving American
politics, the quest for unearned increments to land
value.
Thorstein Veblen in his final testament,
Absentee Ownership, noted that
American farmers
...have always, ... wanted
something more than their ... share of the soil; not
because they were driven by a felt need of doing more
than their fair share of work ..., but with a view to ...
getting a little something for nothing in allowing their
holdings to be turned to account (Veblen, pp.
138-40).
To enhance those values they will now invoke any
complaisant higher power, and since God already did His
bit by donating the Earth, they turn to Government.
But the profile of land values is
like a volcanic island. To raise the top and the
slopes and the shores we must also raise the shallows
above sea level, where they shed the waters and come into
use.
Rising population is one factor pushing up the
profile of values, but not the strongest one.
Increased demand per capita is the main factor.
These demands include all the spurious demands described
above, like the demand of government for land to "bank"
and hold idle, and the demand of speculators "with a view
to getting a little something for nothing."
... Read the
whole article
Frank Stilwell and Kirrily Jordan: The Political Economy of Land:
Putting Henry George in His Place
George saw land as a community resource provided by
nature, to which every human being had an equal right. He
argued that, since land was fixed in supply, the system
of private land ownership allowed the wealthy few to
enjoy exclusive rights to land and its benefits, while
alienating the poorer majority from land ownership and
forcing them to pay rent to landowners in order to access
this necessary resource. Moreover, the collection of
rents by landowners allowed them to increase their wealth
without contributing to the productive efforts of
society. As the population grew, so too did the demand
for land, forcing rents and land values ever higher. In
addition, increases in land value resulting from
publicly-funded developments, such as roads and public
transport systems, unduly benefited landowners at the
expense of the community. Such unearned gains from
landownership encouraged speculation in land, pushing
prices even higher, while exposing the economy to the
risks of speculative ‘booms’ and
‘busts’. ... read the whole
article
Peter Barnes:
Capitalism 3.0 — Chapter 6: Trusteeship of Creation
(pages 79-100)
Commons Rent
It shouldn’t be thought that the commons is, or
ought to be, a money-free zone. In fact, an important
subject for economists (and the rest of us) to understand
is commons rent.
By this I don’t mean the monthly check you send
to a landlord. In economics, rent has a more precise
meaning: it’s money paid because of scarcity. If
you’re not an economist, that may sound puzzling,
but consider this. A city has available a million
apartments. In absolute terms, that means apartments
aren’t scarce. But the city is confined
geographically and demand for apartments is intense. In
this economic sense, apartments are scarce. Now think
back to that check you pay your landlord, or the mortgage
you pay the bank. Part of it represents the
landlord’s operating costs or the bank’s cost
of money, but part of it is pure rent — that is,
money paid for scarcity. That’s why New Yorkers and
San Franciscans write such large checks to landlords and
banks, while people in Nebraska don’t.
Rent rises when an increase in demand bumps into a
limit in supply. Rent due to such bumping isn’t
good or bad; it just is.We can (and should) debate the
distribution of that rent, but the rent itself arises
automatically. And it’s important that it does so,
because this helps the larger economy allocate scarce
resources efficiently. Other methods of allocation are
possible. We can distribute scarce things on a first
come, first served basis, or by lottery, political power,
seniority, or race. Experience has shown, though, that
selling scarce resources in open markets is usually the
best approach, and such selling inevitably creates
rent.
Rent was of great interest to the early economists
— Adam Smith, David Ricardo, and John Stuart Mill,
among others — because it constituted most of the
money earned by landowners, and land was then a major
cost of production. The supply of land, these economists
noted, is limited, but demand for it steadily increases.
So, therefore, does its rent. Thus, landowners benefit
from what Mill called the unearned increment — the
rise in land value attributable not to any effort of the
owner, but purely to a socially created increase in
demand bumping into a limited supply of good land.
The underappreciated American economist Henry George
went further. Seeing both the riches and the miseries of
the Gilded Age, he asked a logical question: Why does
poverty persist despite economic growth? The answer, he
believed, was the appropriation of rent by landowners.
Even as the economy grew, the property rights system and
the scarcity of land diverted almost all the gains to a
landowning minority. Whereas competition limited the
gains of working people, nothing kept down the
landowners’ gains. As Mill had noted, the value of
their land just kept rising. To fix the problem, George
advocated a steep tax on land and the abolition of other
taxes. His bestselling book Progress and Poverty
catapulted him to fame in the 1880s, but mainstream
economists never took him seriously.
By the twentieth century, economists had largely lost
interest in rent; it seemed a trivial factor in wealth
production compared to capital and labor. But the
twenty-first century ecological crisis brings rent back
to center-stage. Now it’s not just land
that’s scarce, but clean water, undisturbed
habitat, biological diversity, waste absorption capacity,
and entire ecosystems.
This brings us back to common property rights. The
definition and allocation of property rights are the
primary factors in determining who pays whom for what.
If, in the case of pollution rights, pollution rights are
given free to past polluters, the rent from the polluted
ecosystem will also go to them. That’s because
prices for pollution-laden products will rise as
pollution is limited (remember, if demand is constant, a
reduction in supply causes prices to go up), and those
higher prices will flow to producers (which is to say,
polluters).
By contrast, if pollution rights are assigned to
trusts representing pollutees and future generations, and
if these trusts then sell these rights to polluters, the
trusts rather than the polluters will capture the commons
rent. If the trusts split this money between per capita
dividends and expenditures on public goods, everyone
benefits.
At this moment, based on pollution rights allocated so
far, polluting corporations are getting most of the
commons rent. But the case for trusts getting the rent in
the future is compelling. If this is done, consumers will
pay commons rent not to corporations or government, but
to themselves as beneficiaries of commons trusts. Each
citizen’s dividend will be the same, but his
payments will depend on his purchases of pollution-laden
products. The more he pollutes, the more rent he’ll
pay. High polluters will get back less than they put in,
while low polluters will get back more. The microeconomic
incentives, in other words, will be perfect. (See figure
6.1.)
What’s equally significant, though less obvious,
is that the macroeconomic incentives will be perfect too.
That is, it will be in everyone’s interest to
reduce the total level of pollution. Remember how rent
for scarce things works: the lower the supply, the higher
the rent. Now, imagine you’re a trustee of an
ecosystem, and leaving aside (for the sake of argument)
your responsibility to preserve the asset for future
generations, you want to increase dividends. Do you raise
the number of pollution permits you sell, or lower it?
The correct, if counterintuitive answer is: you lower the
number of permits. ...
read the whole chapter
from
A History of Pennsylvania, by Phillip S. Klein and Ari
Hoogenboom, p. 441
More than any other person, Gifford Pinchot dominated
Pennsylvania in the 1920s and early 1930s. Serving as
governor from 1923 to 1927 and from 1932 to 1935, Pinchot
gave Pennsylvania a progressive administration during the
reactionary 1920s. Pinchot was born in Connecticut, but
his family came from Milford, where his grandfather had
settled and prospered. His father made a fortune as a New
York merchant, married the daughter of millionaire New
Yorker Amos R. Eno, and built the family mansion Grey
Towers just outside Milford. Pinchot was committed to
public service. "My own money," he remarked in 1914,
"came from the unearned increment on land in New York
held by my grandfather, who willed the money, not the
land, to me. Having got my wages in advance that way, I
am now trying to work them out." ...
|
To share this page with a friend:
right click, choose "send," and add your
comments.
|
|
Red links have not been
visited; .
Green links are pages you've seen
|
Essential Documents pertinent
to this theme:
|
|