Ownership
For a while we were hearing a lot about
the Ownership Society, which seemed to seek to
privatize as many things as possible and withdraw the
social safety nets.
Georgists have a different idea about
ownership: that which one makes, one is
entitled to keep. But the economic value of
that which society creates or nature provided
us, society should receive back, in the form
of a user fee or land rent, for reinvestment in the
commons.
Thus, instead of pork projects like
Alaska's "bridge to nowhere" being funded from taxes on
wages and creating a huge increase in land value to
benefit the lucky folks who own land on a particular
island (allowing them to charge their fellow human
beings more to use or buy that land!), Georgists would
collect the resulting increase in land value from the
"lucky folks," and recycle it to fund the next
public project — without tapping that which is
inherently private — one's work, one's wages,
one's savings — to do it! We'd recycle the
revenue, using it over and over again, rather than
having to collect it from wage-earners. (And if a
capital project like a bridge is unlikely to create an
increase in land value sufficient to cover the
project's costs within a reasonable period of time, it
probably doesn't make sense to do it yet!)
Isn't this a better vision of a good
society? A place where common spending benefits all of
us, and where one gets to keep one's wages, instead of
having them taxed to enrich others?
What constitutes the rightful basis of property?
What is it that enables a man justly to say of a thing,
"It is mine!" From what springs the sentiment which
acknowledges his exclusive right as against all the
world? Is it not, primarily, the right of a man to
himself, to the use of his own powers, to the enjoyment
of the fruits of his own exertions? Is it not this
individual right, which springs from and is testified to
by the natural facts of individual organization —
the fact that each particular pair of hands obey a
particular brain and are related to a particular stomach;
the fact that each man is a definite, coherent,
independent whole — which alone justifies
individual ownership? As a man belongs to himself, so his
labor when put in concrete form belongs to him.
...
This right of ownership that springs from
labor excludes the possibility of any other right of
ownership. If a man be rightfully entitled to the produce
of his own labor, then no one can be rightfully entitled
to the ownership of anything which is not the produce of
his labor, or the labor of someone else from whom the
right has passed to him. If production give to the
producer the right to exclusive possession and enjoyment,
there can rightfully be no exclusive possession and
enjoyment of anything not the production of labor, and
the recognition of private property in land is a
wrong.
Henry George,
Progress & Poverty,
Book VII (Justice of the Remedy),
Chapter 1 (Injustice of private property)
"The neoclassical economists' view of
their proper role is rather like that in The Realtor's
Oath, which includes a vow 'To protect the
individual right of real estate ownership. ' The word 'individual ' is
construed broadly to include corporations, estates,
trusts, anonymous offshore funds, schools, government
agencies, institutions, partnerships, cooperatives, the
Duke of Westminster, the Sultan of Brunei, the Medellin
Cartel, Saddam Hussein, congregations, Archbishops,
families (including criminal families) and so on, but
'individual ' sounds more
all-American and subsumes them all. This is a potent
chant that stirs people to extremes of self-righteousness
and siege mentality when challenged." - Mason Gaffney
Owe and own ...
Henry George: The Condition of Labor
— An Open Letter to Pope Leo XIII in response to
Rerum Novarum (1891)
As to the right of ownership, we hold: That
—
Being created individuals, with individual wants and
powers, men are individually entitled (subject of course
to the moral obligations that arise from such relations
as that of the family) to the use of their own powers and
the enjoyment of the results. There thus arises, anterior
to human law, and deriving its validity from the law of
God, a right of private ownership in things produced by
labor — a right that the possessor may transfer,
but of which to deprive him without his will is
theft.
This right of property, originating in the right of
the individual to himself, is the only full and complete
right of property. It attaches to things produced by
labor, but cannot attach to things created by God.
Thus, if a man take a fish from the ocean he acquires
a right of property in that fish, which exclusive right
he may transfer by sale or gift. But he cannot obtain a
similar right of property in the ocean, so that he may
sell it or give it or forbid others to use it.
Or, if he set up a windmill he acquires a right of
property in the things such use of wind enables him to
produce. But he cannot claim a right of property in the
wind itself, so that he may sell it or forbid others to
use it.
Or, if he cultivate grain he acquires a right of
property in the grain his labor brings forth. But he
cannot obtain a similar right of property in the sun
which ripened it or the soil on which it grew. For these
things are of the continuing gifts of God to all
generations of men, which all may use, but none may claim
as his alone.
To attach to things created by God the same right of
private ownership that justly attaches to things produced
by labor is to impair and deny the true rights of
property. For a man who out of the proceeds of his labor
is obliged to pay another man for the use of ocean or air
or sunshine or soil, all of which are to men involved in
the single term land, is in this deprived of his rightful
property and thus robbed.
As to the use of land, we hold: That —
While the right of ownership that justly attaches to
things produced by labor cannot attach to land, there may
attach to land a right of possession. As your Holiness
says, “God has not granted the earth to mankind in
general in the sense that all without distinction can
deal with it as they please,” and regulations
necessary for its best use may be fixed by human laws.
But such regulations must conform to the moral law
— must secure to all equal participation in the
advantages of God’s general bounty. The principle
is the same as where a human father leaves property
equally to a number of children. Some of the things thus
left may be incapable of common use or of specific
division. Such things may properly be assigned to some of
the children, but only under condition that the equality
of benefit among them all be preserved.
In the rudest social state, while industry consists in
hunting, fishing, and gathering the spontaneous fruits of
the earth, private possession of land is not necessary.
But as men begin to cultivate the ground and expend their
labor in permanent works, private possession of the land
on which labor is thus expended is needed to secure the
right of property in the products of labor. For who would
sow if not assured of the exclusive possession needed to
enable him to reap? who would attach costly works to the
soil without such exclusive possession of the soil as
would enable him to secure the benefit?
This right of private possession in things created by
God is however very different from the right of private
ownership in things produced by labor. The one is
limited, the other unlimited, save in cases when the
dictate of self-preservation terminates all other rights.
The purpose of the one, the exclusive possession of land,
is merely to secure the other, the exclusive ownership of
the products of labor; and it can never rightfully be
carried so far as to impair or deny this. While any one
may hold exclusive possession of land so far as it does
not interfere with the equal rights of others, he can
rightfully hold it no further.
Thus Cain and Abel, were there only two men on earth,
might by agreement divide the earth between them. Under
this compact each might claim exclusive right to his
share as against the other. But neither could rightfully
continue such claim against the next man born. For since
no one comes into the world without God’s
permission, his presence attests his equal right to the
use of God’s bounty. For them to refuse him any use
of the earth which they had divided between them would
therefore be for them to commit murder. And for them to
refuse him any use of the earth, unless by laboring for
them or by giving them part of the products of his labor
he bought it of them, would be for them to commit theft.
...
God’s laws do not change. Though their
applications may alter with altering conditions, the same
principles of right and wrong that hold when men are few
and industry is rude also hold amid teeming populations
and complex industries. In our cities of millions and our
states of scores of millions, in a civilization where the
division of labor has gone so far that large numbers are
hardly conscious that they are land-users, it still
remains true that we are all land animals and can live
only on land, and that land is God’s bounty to all,
of which no one can be deprived without being murdered,
and for which no one can be compelled to pay another
without being robbed. But even in a state of society
where the elaboration of industry and the increase of
permanent improvements have made the need for private
possession of land wide-spread, there is no difficulty in
conforming individual possession with the equal right to
land. For as soon as any piece of land will yield to the
possessor a larger return than is had by similar labor on
other land a value attaches to it which is shown when it
is sold or rented. Thus, the value of the land itself,
irrespective of the value of any improvements in or on
it, always indicates the precise value of the benefit to
which all are entitled in its use, as distinguished from
the value which, as producer or successor of a producer,
belongs to the possessor in individual right.
To combine the advantages of private possession with
the justice of common ownership it is only necessary
therefore to take for common uses what value attaches to
land irrespective of any exertion of labor on it. The
principle is the same as in the case referred to, where a
human father leaves equally to his children things not
susceptible of specific division or common use. In that
case such things would be sold or rented and the value
equally applied.
It is on this common-sense principle that we, who term
ourselves single-tax men, would have the community
act.
We do not propose to assert equal rights to land by
keeping land common, letting any one use any part of it
at any time. We do not propose the task, impossible in
the present state of society, of dividing land in equal
shares; still less the yet more impossible task of
keeping it so divided.
We propose — leaving land in the private
possession of individuals, with full liberty on their
part to give, sell or bequeath it — simply to levy
on it for public uses a tax that shall equal the annual
value of the land itself, irrespective of the use made of
it or the improvements on it. And since this would
provide amply for the need of public revenues, we would
accompany this tax on land values with the repeal of all
taxes now levied on the products and processes of
industry — which taxes, since they take from the
earnings of labor, we hold to be infringements of the
right of property.
This we propose, not as a cunning device of human
ingenuity, but as a conforming of human regulations to
the will of God.
God cannot contradict himself nor impose on his
creatures laws that clash.
If it be God’s command to men that they should
not steal — that is to say, that they should
respect the right of property which each one has in the
fruits of his labor;
And if he be also the Father of all men, who in his
common bounty has intended all to have equal
opportunities for sharing;
Then, in any possible stage of civilization, however
elaborate, there must be some way in which the exclusive
right to the products of industry may be reconciled with
the equal right to land.
If the Almighty be consistent with himself, it cannot
be, as say those socialists referred to by you, that in
order to secure the equal participation of men in the
opportunities of life and labor we must ignore the right
of private property. Nor yet can it be, as you yourself
in the Encyclical seem to argue, that to secure the right
of private property we must ignore the equality of right
in the opportunities of life and labor. To say the one
thing or the other is equally to deny the harmony of
God’s laws.
But, the private possession of land, subject to the
payment to the community of the value of any special
advantage thus given to the individual, satisfies both
laws, securing to all equal participation in the bounty
of the Creator and to each the full ownership of the
products of his labor. ...
Your Holiness will see from the explanation I have
given that the reform we propose, like all true reforms,
has both an ethical and an economic side. By ignoring the
ethical side, and pushing our proposal merely as a reform
of taxation, we could avoid the objections that arise
from confounding ownership with possession and
attributing to private property in land that security of
use and improvement that can be had even better without
it. All that we seek practically is the legal abolition,
as fast as possible, of taxes on the products and
processes of labor, and the consequent concentration of
taxation on land values irrespective of improvements. To
put our proposals in this way would be to urge them
merely as a matter of wise public expediency. ...
Your use, in so many passages of your Encyclical, of
the inclusive term “property” or
“private” property, of which in morals
nothing can be either affirmed or denied, makes your
meaning, if we take isolated sentences, in many places
ambiguous. But reading it as a whole, there can be no
doubt of your intention that private property in land
shall be understood when you speak merely of private
property. With this interpretation, I find that the
reasons you urge for private property in land are eight.
Let us consider them in order of presentation. You
urge:
1. That what is bought with rightful property is
rightful property. (RN, paragraph 5) ...
2. That private property in land proceeds from
man’s gift of reason. (RN, paragraphs 6-7.)
...
3. That private property in land deprives no one of the
use of land. (RN, paragraph 8.) ...
4. That Industry expended on land gives ownership in the
land itself. (RN, paragraphs 9-10.) ...
5. That private property in land has the support of the
common opinion of mankind, and has conduced to peace and
tranquillity, and that it is sanctioned by Divine Law.
(RN, paragraph 11.) ...
6. That fathers should provide for their children and
that private property in land is necessary to enable them
to do so. (RN, paragraphs 14-17.) ...
7. That the private ownership of land stimulates
industry, increases wealth, and attaches men to the soil
and to their country. (RN, paragraph 51.) ...
8. That the right to possess private property in land is
from nature, not from man; that the state has no right to
abolish it, and that to take the value of landownership
in taxation would be unjust and cruel to the private
owner. (RN, paragraph 51.)
1. That what is bought with rightful
property is rightful property. (5.)*
Clearly, purchase and sale cannot give, but can only
transfer ownership. Property that in itself has no moral
sanction does not obtain moral sanction by passing from
seller to buyer.
If right reason does not make the slave the
property of the slave-hunter it does not make him the
property of the slave-buyer. Yet your reasoning as to
private property in land would as well justify property
in slaves. To show this it is only needful to
change in your argument the word land to the word slave.
It would then read:
It is surely undeniable that, when a man engages
in remunerative labor, the very reason and motive of
his work is to obtain property, and to hold it as his
own private possession.
If one man hires out to another his strength or
his industry, he does this for the purpose of receiving
in return what is necessary for food and living; he
thereby expressly proposes to acquire a full and legal
right, not only to the remuneration, but also to the
disposal of that remuneration as he pleases.
Thus, if he lives sparingly, saves money, and
invests his savings, for greater security, in a slave,
the slave in such a case is only his wages in another
form; and consequently, a working-man’s slave
thus purchased should be as completely at his own
disposal as the wages he receives for his
labor.
Nor in turning your argument for private property in
land into an argument for private property in men am I
doing a new thing. In my own country, in my own
time, this very argument, that purchase gave ownership,
was the common defense of slavery. It was made
by statesmen, by jurists, by clergymen, by bishops; it
was accepted over the whole country by the great mass of
the people. By it was justified the separation of wives
from husbands, of children from parents, the compelling
of labor, the appropriation of its fruits, the buying and
selling of Christians by Christians. In language almost
identical with yours it was asked, “Here is
a poor man who has worked hard, lived sparingly, and
invested his savings in a few slaves. Would you rob him
of his earnings by liberating those
slaves?” Or it was said: “Here is a
poor widow; all her husband has been able to leave her is
a few negroes, the earnings of his hard toil. Would you
rob the widow and the orphan by freeing these
negroes?” And because of this perversion of reason,
this confounding of unjust property rights with just
property rights, this acceptance of man’s law as
though it were God’s law, there came on our nation
a judgment of fire and blood.
The error of our people in thinking that what in
itself was not rightfully property could become rightful
property by purchase and sale is the same error into
which your Holiness falls. It is not merely formally the
same; it is essentially the same. Private
property in land, no less than private property in
slaves, is a violation of the true rights of
property. They are different forms of the same
robbery; twin devices by which the perverted ingenuity of
man has sought to enable the strong and the cunning to
escape God’s requirement of labor by forcing it on
others.
What difference does it make whether I merely
own the land on which another man must live or own the
man himself? Am I not in the one case as much his master
as in the other? Can I not compel him to work for me? Can
I not take to myself as much of the fruits of his labor;
as fully dictate his actions? Have I not over him the
power of life and death?
For to deprive a man of land is as certainly to kill
him as to deprive him of blood by opening his veins, or
of air by tightening a halter around his neck.
The essence of slavery is in empowering one
man to obtain the labor of another without recompense.
Private property in land does this as fully as chattel
slavery. The slave-owner must leave to the slave
enough of his earnings to enable him to live. Are there
not in so-called free countries great bodies of
working-men who get no more? How much more of the fruits
of their toil do the agricultural laborers of Italy and
England get than did the slaves of our Southern States?
Did not private property in land permit the landowner of
Europe in ruder times to demand the jus primae noctis?
Does not the same last outrage exist today in diffused
form in the immorality born of monstrous wealth on the
one hand and ghastly poverty on the other?
In what did the slavery of Russia consist but in
giving to the master land on which the serf was forced to
live? When an Ivan or a Catherine enriched their
favorites with the labor of others they did not give men,
they gave land. And when the appropriation of land has
gone so far that no free land remains to which the
landless man may turn, then without further violence the
more insidious form of labor robbery involved in private
property in land takes the place of chattel slavery,
because more economical and convenient. For under it the
slave does not have to be caught or held, or to be fed
when not needed. He comes of himself, begging the
privilege of serving, and when no longer wanted can be
discharged. The lash is unnecessary; hunger is as
efficacious. This is why the Norman conquerors of England
and the English conquerors of Ireland did not divide up
the people, but divided the land. This is why European
slave-ships took their cargoes to the New World, not to
Europe.
Slavery is not yet abolished. Though in all Christian
countries its ruder form has now gone, it still exists in
the heart of our civilization in more insidious form, and
is increasing. There is work to be done for the glory of
God and the liberty of man by other soldiers of the cross
than those warrior monks whom, with the blessing of your
Holiness, Cardinal Lavigerie is sending into the Sahara.
Yet, your Encyclical employs in defense of one form of
slavery the same fallacies that the apologists for
chattel slavery used in defense of the other!
The Arabs are not wanting in acumen. Your Encyclical
reaches far. What shall your warrior monks say, if when
at the muzzle of their rifles they demand of some Arab
slave-merchant his miserable caravan, he shall declare
that he bought them with his savings, and producing a
copy of your Encyclical, shall prove by your reasoning
that his slaves are consequently “only his wages in
another form,” and ask if they who bear your
blessing and own your authority propose to “deprive
him of the liberty of disposing of his wages and thus of
all hope and possibility of increasing his stock and
bettering his condition in life”?
3. That private property in land deprives
no one of the use of land. (8.)
Your own statement that land is the inexhaustible
storehouse that God owes to man must have aroused in your
Holiness’s mind an uneasy questioning of its
appropriation as private property, for, as though to
reassure yourself, you proceed to argue that its
ownership by some will not injure others. You say in
substance, that even though divided among private owners
the earth does not cease to minister to the needs of all,
since those who do not possess the soil can by selling
their labor obtain in payment the produce of the
land.
Suppose that to your Holiness as a judge of morals one
should put this case of conscience:
I am one of several children to whom our father
left a field abundant for our support. As he assigned
no part of it to any one of us in particular, leaving
the limits of our separate possession to be fixed by
ourselves, I being the eldest took the whole field in
exclusive ownership. But in doing so I have not
deprived my brothers of their support from it, for I
have let them work for me on it, paying them from the
produce as much wages as I would have had to pay
strangers. Is there any reason why my conscience should
not be clear?
What would be your answer? Would you not tell him that
he was in mortal sin, and that his excuse added to his
guilt? Would you not call on him to make restitution and
to do penance?
Or, suppose that as a temporal prince your Holiness
were ruler of a rainless land, such as Egypt, where there
were no springs or brooks, their want being supplied by a
bountiful river like the Nile. Supposing that having sent
a number of your subjects to make fruitful this land,
bidding them do justly and prosper, you were told that
some of them had set up a claim of ownership in the
river, refusing the others a drop of water, except as
they bought it of them; and that thus they had become
rich without work, while the others, though working hard,
were so impoverished by paying for water as to be hardly
able to exist?
Would not your indignation wax hot when this was
told?
Suppose that then the river-owners should send to you
and thus excuse their action:
The river, though divided among private owners,
ceases not thereby to minister to the needs of all, for
there is no one who drinks who does not drink of the
water of the river. Those who do not possess the water
of the river contribute their labor to get it; so that
it may be truly said that all water is supplied either
from one’s own river, or from some laborious
industry which is paid for either in the water, or in
that which is exchanged for the water.
Would the indignation of your Holiness be abated?
Would it not wax fiercer yet for the insult to your
intelligence of this excuse?
I do not need more formally to show your Holiness that
between utterly depriving a man of God’s gifts and
depriving him of God’s gifts unless he will buy
them, is merely the difference between the robber who
leaves his victim to die and the robber who puts him to
ransom. But I would like to point out how your statement
that “the earth, though divided among private
owners, ceases not thereby to minister to the needs of
all” overlooks the largest facts.
From your palace of the Vatican the eye may rest on
the expanse of the Campagna, where the pious toil of
religious congregations and the efforts of the state are
only now beginning to make it possible for men to live.
Once that expanse was tilled by thriving husbandmen and
dotted with smiling hamlets. What for centuries has
condemned it to desertion? History tells us. It was
private property in land; the growth of the great estates
of which Pliny saw that ancient Italy was perishing; the
cause that, by bringing failure to the crop of men, let
in the Goths and Vandals, gave Roman Britain to the
worship of Odin and Thor, and in what were once the rich
and populous provinces of the East shivered the thinned
ranks and palsied arms of the legions on the simitars of
Mohammedan hordes, and in the sepulcher of our Lord and
in the Church of St. Sophia trampled the cross to rear
the crescent!
If you will go to Scotland, you may see great tracts
that under the Gaelic tenure, which recognized the right
of each to a foothold in the soil, bred sturdy men, but
that now, under the recognition of private property in
land, are given up to wild animals. If you go to Ireland,
your Bishops will show you, on lands where now only
beasts graze, the traces of hamlets that, when they were
young priests, were filled with honest, kindly, religious
people.*
* Let any one who wishes visit this
diocese and see with his own eyes the vast and
boundless extent of the fairest land in Europe that has
been ruthlessly depopulated since the commencement of
the present century, and which is now abandoned to a
loneliness and solitude more depressing than that of
the prairie or the wilderness. Thus has this land
system actually exercised the power of life and death
on a vast scale, for which there is no parallel even in
the dark records of slavery. — Bishop Nulty’s Letter
to the Clergy and Laity of the Diocese of
Meath.
If you will come to the United States, you will find
in a land wide enough and rich enough to support in
comfort the whole population of Europe, the growth of a
sentiment that looks with evil eye on immigration,
because the artificial scarcity that results from private
property in land makes it seem as if there is not room
enough and work enough for those already here.
Or go to the Antipodes, and in Australia, as in
England, you may see that private property in land is
operating to leave the land barren and to crowd the bulk
of the population into great cities. Go wherever you
please where the forces loosed by modern invention are
beginning to be felt and you may see that private
property in land is the curse, denounced by the prophet,
that prompts men to lay field to field till they
“alone dwell in the midst of the earth.
To the mere materialist this is sin and shame. Shall
we to whom this world is God’s world — we who
hold that man is called to this life only as a prelude to
a higher life — shall we defend it?
4. That Industry expended on land gives
ownership in the land itself. (9-10.)
Your Holiness next contends that industry expended on
land gives a right to ownership of the land, and that the
improvement of land creates benefits indistinguishable
and inseparable from the land itself.
This contention, if valid, could only justify the
ownership of land by those who expend industry on it. It
would not justify private property in land as it exists.
On the contrary, it would justify a gigantic no-rent
declaration that would take land from those who now
legally own it, the landlords, and turn it over to the
tenants and laborers. And if it also be that improvements
cannot be distinguished and separated from the land
itself, how could the landlords claim consideration even
for improvements they had made?
But your Holiness cannot mean what your words imply.
What you really mean, I take it, is that the original
justification and title of landownership is in the
expenditure of labor on it. But neither can this justify
private property in land as it exists. For is it not all
but universally true that existing land titles do not
come from use, but from force or fraud?
Take Italy! Is it not true that the greater part of
the land of Italy is held by those who so far from ever
having expended industry on it have been mere
appropriators of the industry of those who have? Is this
not also true of Great Britain and of other countries?
Even in the United States, where the forces of
concentration have not yet had time fully to operate and
there has been some attempt to give land to users, it is
probably true today that the greater part of the land is
held by those who neither use it nor propose to use it
themselves, but merely hold it to compel others to pay
them for permission to use it.
And if industry give ownership to land what
are the limits of this ownership? If a man may
acquire the ownership of several square miles of land by
grazing sheep on it, does this give to him and his heirs
the ownership of the same land when it is found to
contain rich mines, or when by the growth of population
and the progress of society it is needed for farming, for
gardening, for the close occupation of a great city? Is
it on the rights given by the industry of those who first
used it for grazing cows or growing potatoes that you
would found the title to the land now covered by the city
of New York and having a value of thousands of millions
of dollars?
But your contention is not valid. Industry expended on
land gives ownership in the fruits of that industry, but
not in the land itself, just as industry expended on the
ocean would give a right of ownership to the fish taken
by it, but not a right of ownership in the ocean. Nor yet
is it true that private ownership of land is necessary to
secure the fruits of labor on land; nor does the
improvement of land create benefits indistinguishable and
inseparable from the land itself. That secure possession
is necessary to the use and improvement of land I have
already explained, but that ownership is not necessary is
shown by the fact that in all civilized countries land
owned by one person is cultivated and improved by other
persons. Most of the cultivated land in the British
Islands, as in Italy and other countries, is cultivated
not by owners but by tenants. And so the costliest
buildings are erected by those who are not owners of the
land, but who have from the owner a mere right of
possession for a time on condition of certain payments.
Nearly the whole of London has been built in this way,
and in New York, Chicago, Denver, San Francisco, Sydney
and Melbourne, as well as in continental cities, the
owners of many of the largest edifices will be found to
be different persons from the owners of the ground. So
far from the value of improvements being inseparable from
the value of land, it is in individual transactions
constantly separated. For instance, one-half of the land
on which the immense Grand Pacific Hotel in Chicago
stands was recently separately sold, and in Ceylon it is
a not infrequent occurrence for one person to own a
fruit-tree and another to own the ground in which it is
implanted.
There is, indeed, no improvement of land, whether it
be clearing, plowing, manuring, cultivating, the digging
of cellars, the opening of wells or the building of
houses, that so long as its usefulness continues does not
have a value clearly distinguishable from the value of
the land. For land having such improvements will always
sell or rent for more than similar land without them.
If, therefore, the state levy a tax equal to what the
land irrespective of improvement would bring, it will
take the benefits of mere ownership, but will leave the
full benefits of use and improvement, which the
prevailing system does not do. And since the holder, who
would still in form continue to be the owner, could at
any time give or sell both possession and improvements,
subject to future assessment by the state on the value of
the land alone, he will be perfectly free to retain or
dispose of the full amount of property that the exertion
of his labor or the investment of his capital has
attached to or stored up in the land.
Thus, what we propose would secure, as it is
impossible in any other way to secure, what you properly
say is just and right — “that the results of
labor should belong to him who has labored.” But
private property in land — to allow the holder
without adequate payment to the state to take for himself
the benefit of the value that attaches to land with
social growth and improvement — does take the
results of labor from him who has labored, does turn over
the fruits of one man’s labor to be enjoyed by
another. For labor, as the active factor, is the producer
of all wealth. Mere ownership produces nothing. A man
might own a world, but so sure is the decree that
“by the sweat of thy brow shalt thou eat
bread,” that without labor he could not get a meal
or provide himself a garment. Hence, when the owners of
land, by virtue of their ownership and without laboring
themselves, get the products of labor in abundance, these
things must come from the labor of others, must be the
fruits of others’ sweat, taken from those who have
a right to them and enjoyed by those who have no right to
them.
The only utility of private ownership of land
as distinguished from possession is the evil utility of
giving to the owner products of labor he does not earn.
For until land will yield to its owner some return beyond
that of the labor and capital he expends on it —
that is to say, until by sale or rental he can without
expenditure of labor obtain from it products of labor,
ownership amounts to no more than security of possession,
and has no value. Its importance and value begin only
when, either in the present or prospectively, it will
yield a revenue — that is to say, will enable the
owner as owner to obtain products of labor without
exertion on his part, and thus to enjoy the results of
others’ labor.
What largely keeps men from realizing the robbery
involved in private property in land is that in the most
striking cases the robbery is not of individuals, but of
the community. For, as I have before explained, it is
impossible for rent in the economic sense — that
value which attaches to land by reason of social growth
and improvement — to go to the user. It can go only
to the owner or to the community. Thus those who pay
enormous rents for the use of land in such centers as
London or New York are not individually injured.
Individually they get a return for what they pay, and
must feel that they have no better right to the use of
such peculiarly advantageous localities without paying
for it than have thousands of others. And so, not
thinking or not caring for the interests of the
community, they make no objection to the system.
It recently came to light in New York that a man
having no title whatever had been for years collecting
rents on a piece of land that the growth of the city had
made very valuable. Those who paid these rents had never
stopped to ask whether he had any right to them. They
felt that they had no right to land that so many others
would like to have, without paying for it, and did not
think of, or did not care for, the rights of all. ...
7. That the private ownership of land
stimulates industry, increases wealth, and attaches men
to the soil and to their country. (51.)
The idea, as expressed by Arthur Young, that
“the magic of property turns barren sands to
gold” springs from the confusion of ownership with
possession, of which I have before spoken, that
attributes to private property in land what is due to
security of the products of labor. It is needless for me
again to point out that the change we propose, the
taxation for public uses of land values, or economic
rent, and the abolition of other taxes, would give to the
user of land far greater security for the fruits of his
labor than the present system and far greater permanence
of possession. Nor is it necessary further to show how it
would give homes to those who are now homeless and bind
men to their country. For under it every one who wanted a
piece of land for a home or for productive use could get
it without purchase price and hold it even without tax,
since the tax we propose would not fall on all land, nor
even on all land in use, but only on land better than the
poorest land in use, and is in reality not a tax at all,
but merely a return to the state for the use of a
valuable privilege. And even those who from circumstances
or occupation did not wish to make permanent use of land
would still have an equal interest with all others in the
land of their country and in the general prosperity.
But I should like your Holiness to consider how
utterly unnatural is the condition of the masses in the
richest and most progressive of Christian countries; how
large bodies of them live in habitations in which a rich
man would not ask his dog to dwell; how the great
majority have no homes from which they are not liable on
the slightest misfortune to be evicted; how numbers have
no homes at all, but must seek what shelter chance or
charity offers. I should like to ask your Holiness to
consider how the great majority of men in such countries
have no interest whatever in what they are taught to call
their native land, for which they are told that on
occasions it is their duty to fight or to die. What
right, for instance, have the majority of your countrymen
in the land of their birth? Can they live in Italy
outside of a prison or a poorhouse except as they buy the
privilege from some of the exclusive owners of Italy?
Cannot an Englishman, an American, an Arab or a Japanese
do as much? May not what was said centuries ago by
Tiberius Gracchus be said today: “Men of Rome! you
are called the lords of the world, yet have no right to a
square foot of its soil! The wild beasts have their dens,
but the soldiers of Italy have only water and
air!”
What is true of Italy is true of the civilized world
— is becoming increasingly true. It is the
inevitable effect as civilization progresses of private
property in land. ...
Since man can live only on land and from land,
since land is the reservoir of matter and force from
which man’s body itself is taken, and on which he
must draw for all that he can produce, does it not
irresistibly follow that to give the land in ownership to
some men and to deny to others all right to it is to
divide mankind into the rich and the poor, the privileged
and the helpless? Does it not follow that those
who have no rights to the use of land can live only by
selling their power to labor to those who own the land?
Does it not follow that what the socialists call
“the iron law of wages,” what the political
economists term “the tendency of wages to a
minimum,” must take from the landless masses
— the mere laborers, who of themselves have no
power to use their labor — all the benefits of any
possible advance or improvement that does not alter this
unjust division of land? For having no power to employ
themselves, they must, either as labor-sellers or as
land-renters, compete with one another for permission to
labor. This competition with one another of men shut out
from God’s inexhaustible storehouse has no limit
but starvation, and must ultimately force wages to their
lowest point, the point at which life can just be
maintained and reproduction carried on. ... read the whole
letter
Henry George: The
Common Sense of Taxation (1881 article)
To consider what is included in the category of
property is to see the absurdity of saying that all
property should be equally taxed. For not to speak of
minor differences that arise from application and use,
there are commonly included under this term things of
essentially different nature. Whatever is
recognized by municipal law as subject to ownership is
property. But between things thus classed
together are wide differences. In the first place, there
are certain of them which have in themselves no value,
but are merely the representatives or doubles of property
in itself valuable. Such are stocks, bonds, mortgages,
promissory notes of all kinds, whether made by
individuals or issued by governments to serve as money,
solvent debts, book-accounts, etc. These things may be to
the individual valuable property, and are correctly
included in any estimate of his wealth. But they are no
part of the wealth of the community. Their increase does
not make the community a whit the richer; and they may be
utterly destroyed without the community becoming a whit
the poorer. If I buy a horse, giving my note for the
amount, the result of the transaction (supposing me to be
solvent) is that the seller gets property to the value of
the horse, while I get the horse. But there has been no
increase in wealth. To the seller, my note may be quite
as good as the horse, and in estimating his wealth it may
be as properly included as the horse; but if the note be
destroyed, the community is nothing the poorer, while if
the horse break his neck, there is a lessening of the
general wealth by one horse. And so, the issuance of
bonds by a government, or the watering of stock by a
corporation, can in no wise increase the general sum of
wealth, nor will any diminution either in the amount or
in the selling price of such bonds or stock reduce it. If
all the governments of the world were to repudiate their
debts tomorrow, an immense amount of property, now
carefully guarded, would become waste paper, and
thousands of people now rich would be made poor, but the
wealth of the human race would not be diminished one
iota. ...
For, keeping in mind the fact that all wealth is the
result of human exertion, it is clearly seen that, having
in view the promotion of the general prosperity, it is
the height of absurdity to tax wealth for purposes of
revenue while there remains, unexhausted by taxation, any
value attaching to land. We may tax land values as much
as we please, without in the slightest degree lessening
the amount of land, or the capabilities of land, or the
inducement to use land. But we cannot tax wealth without
lessening the inducement to the production of wealth, and
decreasing the amount of wealth. We might take the whole
value of land in taxation, so as to make the ownership of
land worth nothing, and the land would still remain, and
be as useful as before. The effect would be to throw land
open to users free of price, and thus to increase its
capabilities, which are brought out by increased
population. But impose anything like such taxation upon
wealth, and the inducement to the production of wealth
would be gone. Movable wealth would be hidden or carried
off, immovable wealth would be suffered to go to decay,
and where was prosperity would soon be the silence of
desolation.
And the reason of this difference is clear. The
possession of wealth is the inducement to the exertion
necessary to the production and maintenance of wealth.
Men do not work for the pleasure of working, but to get
the things their work will give them. And to tax the
things that are produced by exertion is to lessen the
inducement to exertion. But over and above the benefit to
the possessor, which is the stimulating motive to the
production of wealth, there is a benefit to the
community, for no matter how selfish he may be, it is
utterly impossible for any one to entirely keep to
himself the benefit of any desirable thing he may
possess. These diffused benefits when localized give
value to land, and this may be taxed without in any wise
diminishing the incentive to production.
To illustrate: A man builds a fine house or large
factory in a poorly improved neighborhood. To tax this
building and its adjuncts is to make him pay for his
enterprise and expenditure — to take from him part
of his natural reward. But the improvement thus made has
given new beauty or life to the neighborhood, making it a
more desirable place than before for the erection of
other houses or factories, and additional value is given
to land all about. Now to tax improvements is not only to
deprive of his proper reward the man who has made the
improvement, but it is to deter others from making
similar improvements. But, instead of taxing
improvements, to tax these land values is to leave the
natural inducement to further improvement in full force,
and at the same time to keep down an obstacle to further
improvement, which, under the present system, improvement
itself tends to raise. For the advance of land values
which follows improvement, and even the expectation of
improvement, makes further improvement more costly.
See how unjust and short-sighted is this system. Here
is a man who, gathering what little capital he can, and
taking his family, starts West to find a place where he
can make himself a home. He must travel long distances;
for, though he will pass plenty of land nobody is using,
it is held at prices too high for him. Finally he will go
no further, and selects a place where, since the creation
of the world, the soil, so far as we know, has never felt
a plowshare. But here, too, in nine cases out of ten, he
will find the speculator has been ahead of him, for the
speculator moves quicker, and has superior means of
information to the emigrant. Before he can put this land
to the use for which nature intended it, and to which it
is for the general good that it should be put, he must
make terms with some man who in all probability never saw
the land, and never dreamed of using it, and who, it may
be, resides in some city, thousands of miles away. In
order to get permission to use this land, he must give up
a large part of the little capital which is seed-wheat to
him, and perhaps in addition mortgage his future labor
for years. Still he goes to work: he works himself, and
his wife works, and his children work — work like
horses, and live in the hardest and dreariest manner.
Such a man deserves encouragement, not discouragement;
but on him taxation falls with peculiar severity. Almost
everything that he has to buy — groceries,
clothing, tools — is largely raised in price by a
system of tariff taxation which cannot add to the price
of the grain or hogs or cattle that he has to sell. And
when the assessor comes around he is taxed on the
improvements he has made, although these improvements
have added not only to the value of surrounding land, but
even to the value of land in distant commercial centers.
Not merely this, but, as a general rule, his land,
irrespective of the improvements, will be assessed at a
higher rate than unimproved land around it, on the ground
that "productive property" ought to pay more than
"unproductive property" — a principle just the
reverse of the correct one, for the man who makes land
productive adds to the general prosperity, while the man
who keeps land unproductive stands in the way of the
general prosperity, is but a dog-in-the-manger, who
prevents others from using what he will not use
himself.
Or, take the case of the railroads. That railroads are
a public benefit no one will dispute. We want more
railroads, and want them to reduce their fares and
freight. Why then should we tax them? for taxes upon
railroads deter from railroad building, and compel higher
charges. Instead of taxing the railroads, is it not clear
that we should rather tax the increased value which they
give to land? To tax railroads is to check railroad
building, to reduce profits, and compel higher rates; to
tax the value they give to land is to increase railroad
business and permit lower rates. The elevated railroads,
for instance, have opened to the overcrowded population
of New York the wide, vacant spaces of the upper part of
the island. But this great public benefit is neutralized
by the rise in land values. Because these vacant lots can
be reached more cheaply and quickly, their owners demand
more for them, and so the public gain in one way is
offset in another, while the roads lose the business they
would get were not building checked by the high prices
demanded for lots. The increase of land values, which the
elevated roads have caused, is not merely no advantage to
them — it is an injury; and it is clearly a public
injury. The elevated railroads ought not to be taxed. The
more profit they make, with the better conscience can
they be asked to still further reduce fares. It is the
increased land values which they have created that ought
to be taxed, for taxing them will give the public the
full benefit of cheap fares.
So with railroads everywhere. And so not alone with
railroads, but with all industrial enterprises. So long
as we consider that community most prosperous which
increases most rapidly in wealth, so long is it the
height of absurdity for us to tax wealth in any of its
beneficial forms. We should tax what we want to repress,
not what we want to encourage. We should tax that which
results from the general prosperity, not that which
conduces to it. It is the increase of population, the
extension of cultivation, the manufacture of goods, the
building of houses and ships and railroads, the
accumulation of capital, and the growth of commerce that
add to the value of land — not the increase in the
value of land that induces the increase of population and
increase of wealth. It is not that the land of Manhattan
Island is now worth hundreds of millions where, in the
time of the early Dutch settlers, it was only worth
dollars, that there are on it now so many more people,
and so much more wealth. It is because of the increase of
population and the increase of wealth that the value of
the land has so much increased. Increase of land values
tends of itself to repel population and prevent
improvement. And thus the taxation of land values, unlike
taxation of other property, does not tend to prevent the
increase of wealth, but rather to stimulate it. It is the
taking of the golden egg, not the choking of the goose
that lays it.
Every consideration of policy and ethics squares with
this conclusion. The tax upon land values is the most
economically perfect of all taxes. It does not raise
prices; it maybe collected at least cost, and with the
utmost ease and certainty; it leaves in full strength all
the springs of production; and, above all, it consorts
with the truest equality and the highest justice. For, to
take for the common purposes of the community that value
which results from the growth of the community, and to
free industry and enterprise and thrift from burden and
restraint, is to leave to each that which he fairly
earns, and to assert the first and most comprehensive of
equal rights — the equal right of all to the land
on which, and from which, all must live.
Thus it is that the scheme of taxation which conduces
to the greatest production is also that which conduces to
the fairest distribution, and that in the proper
adjustment of taxation lies not merely the possibility of
enormously increasing the general wealth, but the
solution of these pressing social and political problems
which spring from unnatural inequality in the
distribution of wealth.
"There is," says M. de Laveleye, in concluding that
work in which he shows that the first perceptions of
mankind have everywhere recognized a most vital
distinction between property in land and property which
results from labor, — "there is in human affairs
one system which is the best; it is not that system which
always exists, otherwise why should we desire to change
it; but it is that system which should exist for the
greatest good of humanity. God knows it, and wills it;
man's duty it is to discover and establish it." ...
read the whole
article
Poverty deepens as wealth increases, and wages are
forced down while productive power grows, because land,
which is the source of all wealth and the field of all
labor, is monopolized. To extirpate poverty, to make
wages what justice commands they should be, the full
earnings of the laborer, we must therefore substitute
for the individual ownership of land a common
ownership.*
*By the phrase "common ownership" of
land, Henry George did not mean that land should be
held in common or by the State, nor did he propose to
interfere with the existing system of land tenures.
(See Sections 7 and 12, post.) As in this
condensation much of George's argument necessarily
has been omitted, the following extracts from his
later work "Protection or Free Trade," chapter XXVI,
are appended to make his position clear to the
present reader.
"No one would sow a crop, or
build a house, or open a mine, or plant an orchard,
or cut a drain, so long as any one else could come
in and turn him out of the land in which or on
which such improvement must be fixed. Thus is it
absolutely necessary to the proper use and
improvement of land that society should secure to
the user and improver safe possession. ... We can
leave land now being used in the secure possession
of those using it. ... on condition that those who
hold land shall pay to the community a ... rent
based on the value of the privilege the individual
receives from the community in being accorded the
exclusive use of this much of the common property,
and which should have no reference to any
improvement he has made in or on it, or to any
profit due to the use of his labor and capital. In
this way all would be placed on an equality in
regard to the use and enjoyment of those natural
elements which are clearly the common
heritage."
Henry George: The Wages of
Labor
Thus, to take the annual value of land
irrespective of improvements cannot lessen the rewards of
industry, nor in any way take from the individual what
belongs to the individual. It can only take the value
that attaches to land by the growth of the community, and
which therefore belongs to the community as a
whole.
To take land values
for the State, abolishing all taxes on the products of
labor, would leave to the laborer the full produce of
labor; to the individual all that rightfully belongs to the
individual. It would impose no burden on industry,
no check on commerce, no punishment on thrift; it would
secure the largest production and the fairest distribution
of wealth, by leaving men free to produce and to exchange
as they please, without any artificial enhancement of
prices; and by taking far public purposes a value that
cannot be carried off, that cannot be hidden, that of all
values is most easily ascertained and most certainly and
cheaply collected, it would enormously lessen the number of
officials, dispense with oaths, and do away with
temptations to bribery and evasion.... read the whole
article Henry George: The Land for the
People (1889 speech)
NOW, as to the rights of ownership -- as to that
principle which enables a man to say of any certain thing
--"This is mine; it is my property" -- where does that
come from? If you look you will see that it comes from
the right of the producer to the thing which he produces.
What a man makes he can justly claim to
be his. Whatever any individual, by the exercise
of his powers, takes from the reservoirs of nature, molds
into shapes fitted to satisfy human needs, that is his;
to that a just and sacred right of property attaches.
That is a right based on the right of the individual to
improvement, the right to the enjoyment of his own
powers, to the possession of the fruits of his exertions.
That is a sacred right, to violate which is to violate
the sacred command, "Thou shalt not steal." There is the
right of ownership. Now that right, which gives by
natural and Divine laws, the thing produced to him whose
exertion has produced it, which gives to the man who
builds a house the right to that house, to the man who
raises a crop the right to that crop, to the man who
raises a domestic animal a right to that domestic animal
-- how can that right attach to the
reservoirs of nature? How can that right attach to the
earth itself?
WE start out with these two principles, which I
think are clear and self-evident: that which a man makes
belongs to him and can by him be given or sold to anyone
that he pleases But that which existed before man came
upon the earth, that which was not produced by man, but
which was created by God -- that belongs equally to all
men. As no man made the land, so no
man can claim a right of ownership in the land. As God
made the land, and as we know both from natural
perception and from revealed religion, that God the
Creator is no respecter of persons, that in His eyes all
men are equal, so also do we know that He made this earth
equally for all the human creatures that He has called to
dwell upon it. We start out with this clear
principle that as all men are here by the equal
permission of the Creator, as they are all here under His
laws equally requiring the use of land, as they are all
here with equal right to live, so they are all here with
equal right to the enjoyment of His bounty. Read the whole speech
Rev. A. C. Auchmuty: Gems from George, a themed
collection of excerpts from the writings of Henry
George (with links to sources)
NATURE acknowledges no ownership or control in man
save as the result of exertion. In no other way can her
treasures be drawn forth, her powers directed, or her
forces utilized or controlled. She makes no
discriminations among men, but is to all absolutely
impartial. She knows no distinction between master and
slave, king and subject, saint and sinner. All men to her
stand upon an equal footing and have equal rights. She
recognizes no claim but that of labor, and recognizes
that without respect to the claimant. If a pirate spread
his sails, the wind will fill them as well as it will
fill those of a peaceful merchantman or missionary bark;
if a king and a common man be thrown overboard, neither
can keep his head above the water except by swimming;
birds will not come to be shot by the proprietor of the
soil any quicker than they will come to be shot by the
poacher; fish will bite or will not bite at a hook in
utter disregard as to whether it is offered them by a
good little boy who goes to Sunday school, or a bad
little boy who plays truant; grain will grow only as the
ground is prepared and the seed is sown; it is only at
the call of labor that ore can be raised from the mine;
the sun shines and the rain falls alike upon just and
unjust. The laws of nature are the decrees of the
Creator. There is written in them no recognition of any
right save that of labor; and in them is written broadly
and clearly the equal right of all men to the use and
enjoyment of nature; to apply to her by their exertions,
and to receive and possess her reward. Hence, as nature
gives only to labor, the exertion of labor in production
is the only title to exclusive possession. —
Progress & Poverty
— Book VII, Chapter 1, Justice of the Remedy:
Injustice of private property in land
PRIVATE property is not of one species, and moral
sanction can no more be asserted universally of it than
of marriage. That proper marriage conforms to the law of
God does not justify the polygamic or polyandric or
incestuous marriages that are in some countries permitted
by the civil law. And as there may be immoral marriage,
so may there be immoral private property. —
The Condition of Labor, an Open Letter to Pope Leo
XIII
THAT any species of property is permitted by the State,
does not of itself give it moral sanction. The State has
often made things property that are not justly property
but involve violence and robbery. —
The Condition of Labor, an Open Letter to Pope Leo
XIII
TO attach to things created by God the same right of
private ownership that justly attaches to things produced
by labor, is to impair and deny the true rights of
property. For a man, who out of the proceeds of his labor
is obliged to pay another man for the use of ocean or air
or sunshine or soil, all of which are to men involved in
the single term land, is in this deprived of his rightful
property, and thus robbed. —
The Condition of Labor, an Open Letter to Pope Leo
XIII
HOW then is it that we are called deniers of the right of
property? It is for the same reason that caused
nine-tenths of the good people in the United States,
north as well as south, to regard abolitionists as
deniers of the right of property; the same reason that
made even John Wesley look on a smuggler as a kind of
robber, and on a custom-house seizer of other men's goods
as a defender of law and order. Where violations of
the right of property have been long sanctioned by
custom and law, it is inevitable that those who really
assert the right of property will at first be thought to
deny it. For under such circumstances the idea of
property becomes confused, and that is thought to be
property which is in reality a violation of property.
—
A Perplexed Philosopher
(The Right Of Property And The Right Of
Taxation)
LANDLORDS must elect to try their case either by human
law or by moral law. If they say that land is
rightly property because made so by human law, they
cannot charge those who would change that law with
advocating robbery. But if they charge that such
change in human law would be robbery, then they must show
that land is rightfully property irrespective of human
law. — The Reduction to Iniquity (a reply to
the Duke of Argyll), The Nineteenth Century, July,
1884 ... go to "Gems
from George"
Louis Post: Outlines
of Louis F. Post's Lectures, with Illustrative Notes and
Charts (1894)
Note 56: The ownership of the land is
essentially the ownership of the men who must use
it.
"Let the circumstances be what they may
— the ownership of land will always give the
ownership of men to a degree measured by the necessity
(real or artificial) for the use of land. Place one
hundred men on an island from which there is no escape,
and whether you make one of these men the absolute
owner of the other ninety-nine, or the absolute owner
of the soil of the island, will make no difference
either to him or to them." — Progress and
Poverty, book vii, ch. ii.
Let us imagine a shipwrecked sailor who,
after battling with the waves, touches land upon an
uninhabited but fertile island. Though hungry and naked
and shelterless, he soon has food and clothing and a
house — all of them rude, to be sure, but
comfortable. How does he get them? By applying his
Labor to the Land of the island. In a little while he
lives as comfortably as an isolated man can.
Now let another shipwrecked sailor be
washed ashore. As he is about to step out of the water
the first man accosts him:
"Hello, there! If you want to come
ashore you must agree to be my slave."
The second replies: "I can't. I come
from the United States, where they don't believe in
slavery."
"Oh, I beg your pardon. I didn't know
you came from the United States. I had no intention of
hurting your feelings, you know. But say, they believe
in owning land in the United States, don't they?"
"Yes."
"Very well; you just agree that this
island is mine, and you may come ashore a free
man."
"But how does the island happen to be
yours? Did you make it?"
"No, I didn't make it."
"Have you a title from its maker?"
"No, I haven't any title from its
maker."
"Well, what is your title, anyhow?"
"Oh, my title is good enough. I got here
first."
Of course he got there first. But he
didn't mean to, and he wouldn't have done it if he
could have helped it. But the newcomer is satisfied,
and says:
"Well, that's a good United States
title, so I guess I'll recognize it and come ashore.
But remember, I am to be a free man."
"Certainly you are. Come right along up
to my cabin."
For a time the two get along well enough
together. But on some fine morning the proprietor
concludes that he would rather lie abed than scurry
around for his breakfast and not being in a good humor,
perhaps, he somewhat roughly commands his "brother man"
to cook him a bird.
"What?" exclaims the brother.
"I tell you to go and kill a bird and
cook it for my breakfast."
"That sounds big," sneers the second
free and equal member of the little community; "but
what am I to get for doing this?"
"Oh," the first replies languidly, "if
you kill me a fat bird and cook it nicely, then after I
have had my breakfast off the bird you may cook the
gizzard for your own breakfast. That's pay enough. The
work is easy."
"But I want you to understand that I am
not your slave, and I won't do that work for that pay.
I'll do as much work for you as you do for me, and no
more."
"Then, sir," the first comer shouts in
virtuous wrath, "I want you to understand that my
charity is at an end. I have treated you better than
you deserved in the past, and this is your gratitude.
Now I don't propose to have any loafers on my property.
You will work for the wages I offer or get off my land!
You are perfectly free. Take the wages or leave them.
Do the work or let it alone. There is no slavery here.
But if you are not satisfied with my terms, leave my
island!"
The second man, if accustomed to the
usages of the labor unions, would probably go out and,
to the music of his own violent language about the
"greed of capital," destroy as many bows and arrows as
he could, so as to paralyze the bird-shooting industry;
and this proceeding he would call a strike for honest
wages and the dignity of labor. If he were accustomed
to social reform notions of the namby-pamby variety, he
would propose an arbitration, and be mildly indignant
when told that there was nothing to arbitrate —
that he had only to accept the other's offer or get off
his property. But if a sensible man, he would notify
his comrade that the privilege of owning islands in
that latitude had expired. ...
c. The Law of Division of Labor and
Trade
Now, what is it that leads men to conform their
conduct to the principle illustrated by the last chart?
Why do they divide their labor, and trade its products? A
simple, universal and familiar law of human nature moves
them. Whether men be isolated, or be living in primitive
communities, or in advanced states of civilization, their
demand for consumption determines the direction of Labor
in production.67 That is the law. Considered in
connection with a solitary individual, like Robinson
Crusoe upon his island, it is obvious. What he demanded
for consumption he was obliged to produce. Even as to the
goods he collected from stranded ships — desiring
to consume them, he was obliged to labor to produce them
to places of safety. His demand for consumption always
determined the direction of his labor in production.68
And when we remember that what Robinson Crusoe was to his
island in the sea, civilized man as a whole is to this
island in space, we may readily understand the
application of the same simple law to the great body of
labor in the civilized world.69 Nevertheless, the
complexities of civilized life are so likely to obscure
its operation and disguise its relations to social
questions like that of the persistence of poverty as to
make illustration desirable.
68. It is highly significant that while
Robinson Crusoe had unsatisfied wants he was never out
of a job. ...
f. The Single Tax Retains Rent for Common
Use.
To retain Rent for common use it is not necessary to
abolish land-titles, nor to let land out to the highest
bidder, nor to invent some new mechanism of taxation, nor
in any other way to directly change existing modes of
holding land for use, or existing machinery for
collecting public revenues. "Great changes can be best
brought about under old forms."109 Let land be held
nominally as it is now. Let taxes be collected by the
same kind of machinery as now. But abolish all taxes
except those that fall upon actual and potential Rent,
that is to say, upon land values.
109. "Such dupes are men to custom, and
so prone
To rev'rence what is ancient and can plead
A course of long observance for its use,
That even servitude, the worst of ills,
Because delivered down from sire to son
Is kept and guarded as a sacred thing."
—Cowper.
It is only custom that makes the
ownership of land seem reasonable. I have frequently
had occasion to tell of the necessity under which the
city of Cleveland, Ohio, found itself, of paying a
land-owner several thousand dollars for the right to
swing a bridge-draw over his land. When I described the
matter in that way, the story attracted no attention;
it seemed perfectly reasonable to the ordinary lecture
audience. But when I described the transaction as a
payment by the city to a land-owner of thousands of
dollars for the privilege of swinging the draw "through
that man's air," the audience invariably manifested its
appreciation of the absurdity of such an ownership. The
idea of owning air was ridiculous; the idea of owning
land was not. Yet who can explain the difference,
except as a matter of custom?
To the same effect was the question of
the Rev. F. L. Higgins to a friend. While stationed at
Galveston, Tex., Mr. Higgins fell into a discussion
with his friend as to the right of government to make
land private property. The friend argued that no matter
what the abstract right might be, the government had
made private property of land, and people had bought
and sold upon the strength of the government title, and
therefore land titles were morally absolute.
"Suppose," said Mr. Higgins, "that the
government should vest in a corporation title to the
Gulf of Mexico, so that no one could fish there, or
sail there, or do anything in or upon the waters of the
Gulf without permission from the corporation. Would
that be right?"
"No," answered the friend.
"Well, suppose the corporation should
then parcel out the Gulf to different parties until
some of the people came to own the whole Gulf to the
exclusion of everybody else, born and unborn. Could any
such title be acquired by these purchasers, or their
descendants or assignees, as that the rest of the
people if they got the power would not have a moral
right to abrogate it?"
"Certainly not," said the friend.
"Could private titles to the Gulf
possibly become absolute in morals?"
"No."
"Then tell me," asked Mr. Higgins, "what
difference it would make if all the water were taken
off the Gulf and only the bare land left."
If that were done it is doubtful if land-owners could
any longer confiscate enough Rent to be worth the
trouble. Even though some surplus were still kept by
them, it would be so much more easy to secure Wealth by
working for it than by confiscating Rent to private use,
to say nothing of its being so much more respectable,
that speculation in land values would practically be
abandoned. At any rate, the question of a surplus —
Rent in excess of the requirements of the community
— may be readily determined when the principle that
Rent justly belongs to the community and Wages to the
individual shall have been recognized by society in the
adoption of the Single Tax. 110
110. Thomas G. Shearman, Esq., of New
York, author of the famous magazine article on "Who
Owns the United States," estimates that sixty-five per
cent of the present annual value of the land in the
United States would pay all the present expenses of
American government — federal, state, county, and
municipal. ...
Q32. Is not ownership of land necessary to induce
its improvement? Does not history show that private
ownership is a step in advance of common
ownership?
A. No. Private use was doubtless a step in advance of
common use. And because private use seems to us to have
been brought about under the institution of private
ownership, private ownership appears to the superficial
to have been the real advance. But a little observation
and reflection will remove that impression. Private
ownership of land is not necessary to its private use.
And so far from inducing improvement, private ownership
retards it. When a man owns land he may accumulate wealth
by doing nothing with the land, simply allowing the
community to increase its value while he pays a merely
nominal tax, upon the plea that he gets no income from
the property. But when the possessor has to pay the value
of his land every year, as he would have to under the
single tax, and as ground renters do now, he must improve
his holding in order to profit by it. Private possession
of land, without profit except from use, promotes
improvement; private ownership, with profit regardless of
use, retards improvement. Every city in the world, in its
vacant lots, offers proof of the statement. It is the
lots that are owned, and not those that are held upon
ground-lease, that remain vacant.
Q52. Is not the right of ownership of a gold ring
the same as the ownership of a gold mine? and if the
latter is wrong is not the former also wrong?
A. If it be wrong for you to own the spring of water
which you and your fellows use, is it therefore wrong for
you to own the water that you lift from the spring to
drink? If so how do you propose to slake your thirst? If
you argue in reply that it is not wrong for you to own
the spring, then how shall your fellows slake their
thirst when you treat them, as you would have a right to,
as trespassers upon your property? To own the source of
labor products is to own the labor of others; to own what
you produce from that source is to own only your own
labor. Nature furnishes gold mines, but men fashion gold
rings. The right of ownership is radically different. ...
read the book
Charles B. Fillebrown: A Catechism of Natural
Taxation, from Principles of Natural Taxation
(1917)
Q11. Does not the common right to rent involve
common ownership of land?
A. Not in the least. When the economic rent is
appropriated by the community for common purposes,
individual ownership of land could and should continue.
Such ownership would carry all the present rights of the
landowner to use, control, and dispose of land, so that
nothing like common ownership of land would be
necessary.
Q12. Did not Henry George believe in the abolition
of private property in land?
A. Assuredly not. If he did, why was it that he suggested
no modification whatever of present land tenure or
"estate in land"? If he did, how could he have said that
the sole "sovereign" and sufficient remedy for the wrongs
of private property in land was "to appropriate rent by
taxation"?
Q13. What is meant by the right of
property?
A. As to the grain a man raises, or the house that he
builds, it means ownership full and complete. As to land,
it means legal title, tenure, "estate in land," perpetual
right of exclusive possession, a right not absolute, but
superior to that of any other man.
... read
the whole article
Clarence Darrow: The Land Belongs To The
People (1916)
This earth is a little raft moving in the endless sea
of space, and the mass of its human inhabitants are
hanging on as best they can. It is as if some raft filled
with shipwrecked sailors should be floating on the ocean,
and a few of the strongest and most powerful would take
all the raft they could get and leave the most of the
people, especially the ones who did the work, hanging to
the edges by their eyebrows. These men who have taken
possession of this raft, this little planet in this
endless space, are not even content with taking all there
is and leaving the rest barely enough to hold onto, but
they think so much of themselves and their brief day that
while they live they must make rules and laws and
regulations that parcel out the earth for thousands of
years after they are dead and, gone, so that their
descendants and others of their kind may do in the tenth
generation exactly what they are doing today —
keeping the earth and all the good things of the earth
and compelling the great mass of mankind to toil for
them.
Now, the question is, how are you going to get it
back? Everybody who thinks knows that private ownership
of the land is wrong. If ten thousand men can own
America, then one man can own it, and if one man may own
it he may take all that the rest produce or he may kill
them if he sees fit. It is inconsistent with the spirit
of manhood. No person who thinks can doubt but that he
was born upon this planet with the same birthright that
came to every man born like him. And it is for him to
defend that birthright. And the man who will not defend
it, whatever the cost, is fitted only to be a slave. The
earth belongs to the people — if they can get it
— because if you cannot get it, it makes no
difference whether you have a right to it or not, and if
you can get it, it makes no difference whether you have a
right to it or not, you just take it. The earth has been
taken from the many by the few. It made no difference
that they had no right to it; they took it.
Now, there are some methods of getting access to the
earth which are easier than others. The easiest, perhaps,
that has been contrived is by means of taxation of the
land values and land values alone; and I need only say a
little upon that question. One trouble with it which
makes it almost impossible to achieve, is that it is so
simple and so easy. You cannot get people to do anything
that is simple; they want it complex so they can be
fooled.
Now the theory of Henry George and of those who really
believe in the common ownership of land is that the
public should take not alone taxation from the land, but
the public should take to itself the whole value of the
land that has been created by the public — should
take it all. It should be a part of the public wealth,
should be used for public improvements, for pensions, and
belong to the people who create the wealth — which
is a strange doctrine in these strange times. It can be
done simply and easily; it can be done by taxation. All
the wealth created by the public could be taken back by
the public and then poverty would disappear, most of it
at least. The method is so simple, and so legal even
— sometimes a thing is legal if it is simple
— that it is the easiest substantial reform for men
to accomplish, and when it is done this great problem of
poverty, the problem of the ages, will be almost solved.
We may need go farther. ... read the whole
article
Upton Sinclair: The
Consequences of Land Speculation are Tenantry and Debt on
the Farms, and Slums and Luxury in the Cities
I know of a woman — I have never had the
pleasure of making her acquaintance, because she lives in
a lunatic asylum, which does not happen to be on my
visiting list. This woman has been mentally incompetent
from birth. She is well taken care of, because her father
left her when he died the income of a large farm on the
outskirts of a city. The city has since grown and the
land is now worth, at conservative estimate, about twenty
million dollars. It is covered with office buildings, and
the greater part of the income, which cannot be spent by
the woman, is piling up at compound interest. The woman
enjoys good health, so she may be worth a hundred million
dollars before she dies.
I choose this case because it is one about which there
can be no disputing; this woman has never been able to do
anything to earn that twenty million dollars. And if a
visitor from Mars should come down to study the
situation, which would he think was most insane, the
unfortunate woman, or the society which compels thousands
of people to wear themselves to death in order to pay her
the income of twenty million dollars?
The fact that this woman is insane makes it easy to
see that she is not entitled to the "unearned increment"
of the land she owns. But how about all the other people
who have bought up and are holding for speculation the
most desirable land? The value of this land increases,
not because of anything these owners do — not
because of any useful service they render to the
community — but purely because the community as a
whole is crowding into that neighborhood and must have
use of the land.
The speculator who bought this land thinks that he
deserves the increase, because he guessed the fact that
the city was going to grow that way. But it seems clear
enough that his skill in guessing which way the community
was going to grow, however useful that skill may be to
himself, is not in any way useful to the community. The
man may have planted trees, or built roads, and put in
sidewalks and sewers; all that is useful work, and for
that he should be paid. But should he be paid for
guessing what the rest of us were going to need?
Before you answer, consider the consequences of this
guessing game. The consequences of land speculation are
tenantry and debt on the farms, and slums and luxury in
the cities. A great part of the necessary land is held
out of use, and so the value of all land continually
increases, until the poor man can no longer own a home.
The value of farm land also increases; so year by year
more independent farmers are dispossessed, because they
cannot pay interest on their mortgages. So the land
becomes a place of serfdom, that land described by the
poet, "where wealth accumulates and men decay." The great
cities fill up with festering slums, and a small class of
idle parasites are provided with enormous fortunes, which
they do not have to earn, and which they cannot
intelligently spend. ...
In Philadelphia, as in all our great cities, are
enormously wealthy families, living on hereditary incomes
derived from crowded slums. Here and there among these
rich men is one who realizes that he has not earned what
he is consuming, and that it has not brought him
happiness, and is bringing still less to his children.
Such men are casting about for ways to invest their money
without breeding idleness and parasitism. Some of them
might be grateful to learn about this enclave plan, and
to visit the lovely village of Arden, and see what its
people are doing to make possible a peaceful and joyous
life, even in this land of bootleggers and jazz
orchestras. ... read
the whole article
Karl Williams: Social Justice In Australia:
ADVANCED KIT - Part 2
WHO WILL OWN THE
LAND?
"For justice to be done between
men it is not necessary for the State to take the land;
it is only necessary to take its rent." - Henry
George (1839 -1897)
The above quote just about says it all. However,
because of a good deal of misinformation about this
aspect of Geonomics (with a liberal sprinkling of
half-baked, alarmist words such as socialisation,
nationalisation or confiscation with respect to land), we
need to get things straight.
Land titles would definitely still exist with
Geonomics. People would still have "their" home and
"their" privacy, and there's nothing unfair or
unreasonable about that. Indeed, it is a universal human
need that cannot be denied and should not be thwarted.
Importantly, land occupancy requires not so much absolute
and outright ownership, but security of tenure, and as a
corollary, the freedom to do as one wishes with the site,
within the limits of course, of existing social mores.
Whether building a house, enrolling your kids in the
nearby school, or just wanting to contribute towards
building up a neighbourhood, you would want to know that
you would be able to occupy your home site for as long as
you wished. Hence, your name would still be on a register
of land titles, and no one could compulsorily buy or
force you out as long as you paid your community dues in
the form of LVT. Council by-laws allowing, you could even
put up fences and "Keep Out" signs. All the trappings of
present-day land ownership would still be
there.
WHAT IS
OWNERSHIP?
But what does "ownership" really mean?
- Do we own our income if the government takes a
big cut of it and calls it taxation?
- Are we all part-owners of urban infrastructure
and national parks?
- Do we fully own our cars if we have to pay
registration and insurance, or if we are subject to all
sorts of restrictions on their use?
- Can we be said to fully own our personal
assets if inheritance taxes take a big chunk of their
value when we drop off the twig?
- If you employ people, can you say that you own
part of their time (and that you own them to a
degree)?
The point is that the concept of ownership is not
always black and white, and the same applies to land
under Geonomics.
On the one hand, occupiers of land would be owners
in the sense that they would have the legal security of
tenure as well as all the privacy and personal liberty
today accruing to home ownership. On the other hand,
occupiers would be required to discharge their dues to
the community for their exclusive occupancy of land, the
value of which they did not produce. So with Geonomics,
what people do not "own" is the community-created
benefits of the land they occupy, for which they would
have to pay.
BUT WHAT'S YOURS IS
YOURS!
But don't forget these important points. Occupiers
will unquestionably own outright their houses and other
improvements to their homes - and they would never get
penalised for improvements through local rates, which
today are often partly based on the value of
improvements. Nor will people see a part of their income
or purchases confiscated through the tax system.
Effectively, we would all become co-owners of all the
land and natural resources, as the rent from them is
pooled into the community coffers for the benefit of all.
By some calculations we could even receive a considerable
Citizen's Dividend from the unspent
surplus.
What about those who might be disadvantaged by the
introduction of Geonomics? It should be stressed that
there would be few such people, but there would be a few
deserving types who would qualify for schemes (too
detailed to mention here) such as limited compensation or
deferral of LVT for some on valuable land with low
incomes and too old or incapacitated for employment.
There is no reason why other types of pensions and
disability payments would need to change.
"Whilst another man has no land,
my title to mine, and your title to yours, is at once
vitiated." - Ralph Waldo Emerson, (1803 -1882),
noted American poet and essayist ...
Read the entire article
Lindy Davies: Land and Justice
We were talking about the tendency for landowners to
use land as an investment — a sensible thing to do
— not to use it now if they don't need to, but to
think in terms of enjoying its increase in value over
time. We even identified that as the key to the problem
of poverty. But — good heavens, what can we do
about that? Isn't that just how the economy works? Isn't
the private ownership of land a basic part of a modern
economy? How can we do without such an important
institution?
Or in other words — won't the poor always be
with us?
Not necessarily. It has been plain, since very
earliest days of civil society, that the private
ownership of land leads to exploitation and great
extremes of wealth and poverty. And, since the time of
the Book of Leviticus, we have had a pretty good idea of
what to do about it. In that book were recorded the words
"The land shall not be sold for ever, for the land is
Mine, for ye are strangers and sojourners with me."
This ideal was codified into a remarkable three-stage
program for economic justice and social harmony: the land
laws of Leviticus. The stages were:
1. The Sabbath. Every seventh day
was the Lord's day; people were enjoined to keep it
holy and refrain from work. Now, we were told in Sunday
school that this was all about going to church, but, as
so often happens, our teachers missed the deeper
significance. Kids who try to get out of, say, taking
out the garbage on the Sabbath realized that the
prohibition was really against gainful work; folks were
still allowed to weed the garden and stuff.
What the Sabbath did was to force people to focus on
things that had meaning beyond striving and striving to
get ahead. Indeed, if one did work on the Sabbath,
while one's neighbors did not, one could become
wealthier, at their expense — which was why the
Sabbath was a very big deal: one of the ten
commandments.
2. The Sabbatical. Every seventh year,
the fields were to lie fallow — thus recognizing
the right of the earth itself to be protected against
depletion and misuse. And, in the sabbatical year,
debts were to be forgiven. A debt that could not be
paid off after six years was well on the way to
becoming a usurious burden, a guaranteed flow from the
labors of one into the coffers of another. The
canceling of debts in the seventh year was designed to
ensure that nobody got too far ahead, or too far
behind.
3. The Jubilee. Even seven times seven
years (actually, every 50th year), each family could
return to its original allotment, or heritage, of land
— even if it had been sold in the meantime. Under
biblical law, then, land could not be sold for ever
— never for more than a single generation.
Now it is interesting to note that the economic vision
presented in the bible is not a precursor of communism.
Two of the ten commandments explicitly support the
institution of private property, and the prophets
consistently railed against landlords and rulers who
robbed the people of the fruits of their labor. The laws
of Leviticus, which Jesus said he "came not to destroy
but to fulfill," envisioned a community in which everyone
was secure in his own home and property, "beneath his
vine and fig tree".
(Incidentally, the quote on the American Liberty Bell,
from Leviticus, chapter 25, was a direct reference to
these principles : "Proclaim liberty throughout the land
and to all the people thereof." It was a reference to the
Jubilee, and the freedom it provided was from debt and
servitude.)
The division is clear: there is to be a sacred right
of private property in the things that are made by
people. But people were not to own the things that were
made by God. The 7th commandment sums up both principles
in 4 words: Thou shalt not steal.
Modern society has looked away from these principles,
calling them quaint, naive, inapplicable to the
complexities of our time — yet, modern society
finds itself mired in chronic economic and social
problems for which it can find no solutions — and
which threaten to pull down all the advances of
civilization into a dark age — occasioned by some
combination of war, financial implosion or ecological
collapse.
If there is any way out of this dark future, it can
only come by way of solving the problem of land and
justice.
Fortunately, there exists a plan for that.
This plan takes the shape of a "fiscal reform",
because it applies a definition of the relationship
between the individual and the society that is consistent
with both economic efficiency and moral law. It calls for
us to respect the right of labor to create and to save
wealth, and we acknowledge that the value of land is
created not by its “owners”, but by the
entire community.
Therefore, we will abolish all taxes on income,
products and sales — and collect the full rental
value of land and other natural resources for public
revenue. ... read the whole
speech
James Kiefer: James Huntington and the
ideas of Henry George
Henry George, author of Progress and Poverty, argued
that, while some forms of wealth are produced by human
activity, and are rightly the property of the producers
(or those who have obtained them from the previous owners
by voluntary gift or exchange), land and natural
resources are bestowed by God on the human race, and that
every one of the N inhabitants of the earth has a claim
to 1/Nth of the coal beds, 1/Nth of the oil wells, 1/Nth
of the mines, and 1/Nth of the fertile soil. God wills a
society where everyone may sit in peace under his own
vine and his own fig tree.
The Law of Moses undertook to implement this by making
the ownership of land hereditary, with a man's land
divided among his sons (or, in the absence of sons, his
daughters), and prohibiting the permanent sale of land.
(See Leviticus 25:13-17,23.) The most a man might do with
his land is sell the use of it until the next Jubilee
year, an amnesty declared once every fifty years, when
all debts were cancelled and all land returned to its
hereditary owner.
Henry George's proposed implementation is to tax all
land at about 99.99% of its rental value, leaving the
owner of record enough to cover his bookkeeping expenses.
The resulting revenues would be divided equally among the
natural owners of the land, viz. the people of the
country, with everyone receiving a dividend check
regularly for the use of his share of the earth (here I
am anticipating what I think George would have suggested
if he had written in the 1990's rather than the
1870's).
This procedure would have the effect of making the
sale price of a piece of land, not including the price of
buildings and other improvements on it, practically zero.
The cost of being a landholder would be, not the original
sale price, but the tax, equivalent to rent. A man who
chose to hold his "fair share," or 1/Nth of all the land,
would pay a land tax about equal to his dividend check,
and so would break even. By 1/Nth of the land is meant
land with a value equal to 1/Nth of the value of all the
land in the country.
Naturally, an acre in the business district of a great
city would be worth as much as many square miles in the
open country. Some would prefer to hold more than one
N'th of the land and pay for the privilege. Some would
prefer to hold less land, or no land at all, and get a
small annual check representing the dividend on their
inheritance from their father Adam.
Note that, at least for the able-bodied, this solves
the problem of poverty at a stroke. If the total land and
total labor of the world are enough to feed and clothe
the existing population, then 1/Nth of the land and 1/Nth
of the labor are enough to feed and clothe 1/Nth of the
population. A family of 4 occupying 4/Nths of the land
(which is what their dividend checks will enable them to
pay the tax on) will find that their labor applied to
that land is enough to enable them to feed and clothe
themselves. Of course, they may prefer to apply their
labor elsewhere more profitably, but the situation from
which we start is one in which everyone has his own plot
of ground from which to wrest a living by the strength of
his own back, and any deviation from this is the result
of voluntary exchanges agreed to by the parties directly
involved, who judge themselves to be better off as the
result of the exchanges.
Some readers may think this a very radical proposal.
In fact, it is extremely conservative, in the sense of
being in agreement with historic ideas about land
ownership as opposed to ownership of, say, tools or
vehicles or gold or domestic animals or other movables.
The laws of English-speaking countries uniformly
distinguish between real property (land) and personal
property (everything else). In this context, "real" is
not the opposite of "imaginary." It is a form of the word
"royal," and means that the ultimate owner of the land is
the king, as symbol of the people. Note that
English-derived law does not recognize "landowners." The
term is "landholders." The concept of eminent domain is
that the landholder may be forced to surrender his
landholdings to the government for a public purpose.
Historically, eminent domain does not apply to property
other than land, although complications arise when there
are buildings on the land that is being seized.
I will mention in passing that the proposals of Henry
George have attracted support from persons as diverse as
Felix Morley, Aldous
Huxley, Woodrow Wilson, Helen Keller, Winston Churchill, Leo Tolstoy, William F Buckley Jr, and Sun
Yat-sen. To the Five Nobel Prizes authorized by Alfred
Nobel himself there has been added a sixth, in Economics,
and the Henry George Foundation claims eight of the Economics
Laureates as supporters, in whole or in part, of the
proposals of Henry George (Paul Samuelson, 1970; Milton Friedman, 1976; Herbert A
Simon, 1978; James Tobin, 1981; Franco Modigliani, 1985;
James M Buchanan, 1986; Robert M Solow, 1987; William S Vickrey, 1996).
The immediate concrete proposal favored by most
Georgists today is that cities shall tax land within
their boundaries at a higher rate than they tax buildings
and other improvements on the land. (In case anyone is
about to ask, "How can we possibly distinguish between
the value of the land and the value of the buildings on
it?" let me assure you that real estate assessors do it
all the time. It is standard practice to make the two
assessments separately, and a parcel of land in the
business district of a large city very often has a
different owner from the building on it.) Many cities
have moved to a system of taxing land more heavily than
improvements, and most have been pleased with the
results, finding that landholders are more likely to use
their land productively -- to their own benefit and that
of the public -- if their taxes do not automatically go
up when they improve their land by constructing or
maintaining buildings on it.
An advantage of this proposal in the eyes of many is
that it is a Fabian proposal, "evolution, not
revolution," that it is incremental and reversible. If a
city or other jurisdiction does not like the results of a
two-level tax system, it can repeal the arrangement or
reduce the difference in levels with no great upheaval.
It is not like some other proposals of the form,
"Distribute all wealth justly, and make me absolute
dictator of the world so that I can supervise the
distribution, and if it doesn't work, I promise to
resign." The problem is that absolute dictators seldom
resign. ... read
the whole article
Weld Carter: An
Introduction to Henry George
The Ethics of Property
Any discussion of Henry George should
include a consideration of his ethical ideas, for
throughout his works the question of right and wrong is
dominant. In Progress and Poverty,
for instance, he struck this keynote:
'. ..whatever dispute arouses the
passions of men, the conflict is sure to rage, not so much
as to the question 'Is it wise?' as to the question 'Is it
right?'. ..I bow to this arbitrament, and accept this
test."
George wrote as a social philosopher.
Therefore his preoccupation in the field of ethics was with
the relations of man to man, rather than with man himself
-- with stealing rather than with thriftlessness. This
necessarily involves the matter of property and
ownership.
Once again, the student will find
George's analysis to be based on the differences inherent
in the two categories of land and products. "The real and
natural distinction is between things which are the produce
of labor and things which are the gratuitous offerings of
nature. ...These two classes of things are in essence and
relations widely different, and to class them together as
property is to confuse all thought when we come to consider
the justice or the injustice, the right or the wrong of
property."
What is the moral basis of
property?
Is it not, primarily, the right of a
man to himself, to the use of his own powers, to the
enjoyment of the fruits of his own exertions? ... As a man
belongs to himself, so his labor when put in concrete form
belongs to him.
And for this reason, that which a man
makes or produces is his own, as against all the world --
to enjoy or to destroy, to use, to exchange, or to give. No
one else can rightfully claim it, and his exclusive right
to it involves no wrong to anyone else. Thus there is to
everything produced by human exertion a clear and
indisputable title to exclusive possession and enjoyment,
which is perfectly consistent with justice, as it descends
from the original producer.
...
Here is a justification for private
property in products. But what of land, which is not
produced by man? Is there any other basis from which a
justification for private property in land might be
derived? In addition, is there anything in the right of
private property in products which precludes the right of
private property in land?
George explains, "Now this [the right
of the individual to the use of his own faculties] is not
only the original source from which all ideas of exclusive
ownership arise ... but it is necessarily the only source.
There can be to the ownership of anything no rightful title
which is not derived from the title of the producer and
does not rest upon the natural right of the man to himself.
There can be no other rightful title, because (lst) there
is no other natural right from which any other title can be
derived, and (2nd) because the recognition of any other
title is inconsistent with and destructive of
this."
To substantiate the first reason he
further said,
Nature acknowledges no
ownership or control in man save as the result of
exertion. In no other way can her treasures be drawn
forth, her powers directed, or her forces utilized or
controlled. ...All men to her stand upon an equal footing
and have equal rights. She recognizes no claim but that
of labor, and recognizes that without respect to the
claimant. If a pirate spread his sails, the wind will
fill them as well as it will fill those of a peaceful
merchantman. ...The laws of nature are the decrees of the
Creator. There is written in them no recognition of any
right save that of labor; and in them is written broadly
and clearly the equal right of all men to the use and
enjoyment of nature; to apply to her by their exertions,
and to receive and possess her reward. Hence, as nature
gives only to labor, the exertion of labor in production
is the only title to exclusive possession (1879, rpt.
1958, pp. 335-36).
As to the second reason he
said:
This right of ownership
that springs from labor excludes the possibility of any
other right of ownership. ...If production give to the
producer the right to exclusive possession and enjoyment,
there can rightfully be no exclusive possession and
enjoyment of anything not the production of labor, and
the recognition of private property in land is a wrong.
For the right to the produce of labor cannot be enjoyed
without the right to the free use of the opportunities
offered by nature, and to admit the right of property in
these is to deny the right of property in the produce of
labor. When nonproducers can claim as rent a portion of
the wealth created by producers, the right of the
producers to the fruits of their labor is to that extent
denied (1879, rpt. 1958, p. 336).
Private property in land, according
to George, is unjust because it lets owners of land refuse
access to land, and thereby threatens livelihood and life
itself. Private property in land is also unjust because it
enables owners of land to levy toll on production for the
use of land; therefore it is robbery. So another difference
between products and land, in George's view, is that
private property in products is right, and private property
in land is wrong.... read the
whole article
Lindy Davies: Ownership and the
Law
President Bush's announcement of his vision for an
"ownership society" met with thunderous cheers at the
Republican Convention, and much eye-rolling elsewhere.
The Bush Administration would like to start by
encouraging private ownership of our retirement funds and
our health-care decisions. They want to get the heavy
hand of government out of such things and unleash the
tremendous efficiency of millions upon millions of
Self-Interested Individual Actors, the husky, brawling,
broad-shouldered capitalism that made this country great.
Prosperity depends on the security of private property
and the potency of individual initiative! This is the
self-evident truth that has been obscured by Hollywood
Socialists, Democratic Girlie-men and purveyors of the
Homosexual Agenda.
We should realize, however, that this is hardly a
new initiative. It is really just the latest wave of an
argument that has raged throughout the history of the
United States, about just what -- if anything -- and on
what basis -- if any -- the government can require us to
surrender what we possess. There are some people out
there -- and actually a fair number, after all -- who
don't view the Bush Administration's privatization
proposals as extremist at all -- but, rather, too soft.
...
Unfortunately, though, the law is not at all
clear. Thomas Jefferson fudged the topic in the United
States Declaration of Independence, inserting "the
pursuit of happiness" where people expected the more
loaded term "property". The Bill of Rights, however, is
strong on property rights. It provides for security of
"persons, houses, papers, and effects," that "private
property shall not be taken for public use without just
compensation" and that rights not specifically prohibited
are reserved to the states or to the people. In fact, the
US Constitution was so bullish on property that it
provided for private property in human beings, a
principle made explicit in Dred Scott vs. Sandford and
many other cases.
Slavery was made unconstitutional by means of the
13th Amendment in 1865. This, however, left much to be
resolved, and the Congress had a very difficult job --
perhaps, in strictly logical terms, an impossible job --
in drafting Amendment number fourteen.
...
The 14th amendment reaffirms the rights of life,
liberty and property, and binds the states to the same
due process and equal protection restrictions as the
federal government. However, it places the Constitution's
first limit on the right of property, stating that the
United States or any state shall not pay "any claim for
the loss or emancipation of any slave". This could be
seen as somewhat fishy in terms of the Fifth Amendment.
After all the 13th amendment had taken the slaveholders'
property three years before. Had not the Supreme Court
ruled that slaves were property and had to be returned to
their owners, even if they escaped to non-slaveholding
states?
Although it would have been impracticable (to say
the least) to enforce the Takings Clause to the tune of
the market value of some four
million human beings, that was what the Constitution
required the government to do. ...
The next amendment to the Constitution following
the Reconstruction Amendments was another milestone in
the debate over property rights. The 16th Amendment,
ratified in 1913, allows Congress to “lay and
collect taxes on incomes, from whatever source
derived” -- contravening the restriction of this
practice that had been laid out in Article I. The
“from whatever source derived” part has been
making people scream bloody murder ever since.
...
The original advocates of the income tax (many of
them Single Taxers) sought to tax accumulation, not
industry and initiative. They saw that the massive
concentration of wealth among a privileged few was
harmful to the nation, and they persuaded the states to
accept a progressive tax that would compel robber barons
to pay for public goods while letting entrepreneurs gain
from their contributions to overall prosperity.
And yet, over the years, a tax on
income “from whatever source derived” came,
one loophole at a time, to be a tax on exactly those
productive, hardworking, middle-class people that it was
designed to help. ...
In most people's minds, after all, land is the
most solid and important kind of property; in fact, the
word "property" in general conversation most often means
"land". However, it has long been recognized that
sometimes privately-held land must be taken for public
purposes. The principle of eminent domain is not
(particularly) controversial. If the state wants to put a
highway through your house, it must pay you the fair
market value of your property.
...
This decision was important because it extended
the Takings doctrine beyond physical seizure to the
taking of value -- but it was also relatively
uncontroversial in that the state legislature had removed
all of the parcel's market value. ...
If government were to be held liable for every
single action that took away a portion of real estate
value, it could scarcely do anything at all. That might
be how some of the most strident militia-folk would like
it. However, it would certainly not suit real estate
owners in general -- who, while they might not enjoy
paying for government, do benefit from the things that
government does.
What the property-rights folks are forgetting (or
disregarding) is that if a piece of land has a market
value, that means that the net benefits conferred upon it
by the community (which includes the government) are
greater than the net costs. Location value is far and
away the most important component of land value -- and
location value is almost entirely the result of services
and infrastructure that the government provides.
...
It's no accident that the issue of "regulatory
takings" is such a stew of contradictions. Indeed, the
terms of the argument deny the possibility of coherence
(in much the same way as they did in 1868). Land is not the fruit of human labor, and its value
is not the result of any actions taken by its owner.
Therefore, private property in land is an entirely
different sort of phenomenon than private property in the
products of labor -- and as long as the law fails to
recognize this fact, it cannot hope to make sense of the
issue of "regulatory takings". ...
It could be suggested that "the conditions of the
grant" could, without doing any violence to the secure
right of private property, require the payment to the
community of the land's rental value, to cover the cost
of the community's expenses which, it turn, provide the
land's value in the first place. That would, of course,
require a clearer definition of the moral basis of
property that the United States has ever been able to
come to. Yet -- think of it for a
moment -- what would have happened if the original Bill
of Rights had articulated the individual's absolute right
to property only in the products of labor -- and the
community's right to the community-created value of the
land?
It would have saved us an awful lot of trouble.
True, the "slavery" states would have balked at joining
the union under those rules. But under them, the nation
would have been so prosperous that they would quite soon
have seen the advantage of joining. We would have avoided
the Civil War, and probably even World War I -- it is
dazzling to think about how different -- and vastly
better -- our history would have been, had the Framers
taken the brave step of setting forth the moral basis of
property along these lines.
It's interesting that we use the
word "own" to mean two different things: the sense of
possession, and the sense of personal acknowledgment, as
in "owning up" to one's responsibilities. The
relationship between the two was once closer than it now
seems to be; the word "ought" is an archaic past
participle of "owe". As we consider how to arrange our
"ownership society", we'd do well to remember what we
"ought" -- and bring the two senses of the word back
together. Read the
whole article
Nic Tideman: Global Economic
Justice, followed by Creating Global Economic
Justice
To summarize George's
rights-based theory of justice: Each person has an
exclusive right to his or her productive powers.
We understand this intuitively, and on this basis accept
the idea that people own what they produce. But if this is what ownership means, then no one can
claim to own land, since no one produced it. People do
have rights to the productive opportunities that nature
offers, which are here for our use, but the rights of
each person are limited by the equal rights of all other
persons. ... Read the
whole article
Nic Tideman: The Shape
of a World Inspired by Henry George
How would the world look if its political
institutions were shaped by the conception of social
justice advanced by Henry George?
Jeff Smith and Kris Nelson: Giving Life to the Property Tax
Shift (PTS)
John Muir is right. "Tug on any one thing and find
it connected to everything else in the universe." Tug on
the property tax and find it connected to urban slums,
farmland loss, political favoritism, and unearned equity
with disrupted neighborhood tenure. Echoing Thoreau, the
more familiar reforms have failed to address this
many-headed hydra at its root. To think that the root
could be chopped by a mere shift in the property tax base
-- from buildings to land -- must seem like the epitome
of unfounded faith. Yet the evidence shows that state and
local tax activists do have a powerful, if subtle, tool
at their disposal. The "stick" spurring efficient use of
land is a higher tax rate upon land, up to even the
site's full annual value. The "carrot" rewarding
efficient use of land is a lower or zero tax rate upon
improvements. ...
What's won or lost is a value generated by
society. That is, land rises in
value
- where a new resource is
discovered (during a gold rush, more money is made by
land developers than by
prospectors),
- where population grows (see the
Sun Belt and verdant
Northwest),
- where technology advances
(witness the land values in the various Silicon
Valleys, Forests, etc),
- where infrastructure expands
(e.g., near a new road or sewer),
and
- where society cooperates (e.g.,
in communities that organize street fairs, neighborhood
watches, etc).
These factors driving land value
are not improvements made by lone owners but by the
entire community. The closest correlation to land value
is density and no one person creates that. Hence the site
value levy merely puts public values in the public
treasury for public benefit, as untaxing homes, sales,
and income leaves privately-generated values in private
pockets.
"Home equity" (actually, site equity), the only equity
most people have, would be consumed by the land dues.
Eventho' the complete geonomic tax shift would let
people improve their homes, increase their incomes,
expand their businesses, and augment their savings
without increasing their tax liability, homeowners would
still lose their "home equity." Proponents need to lead
off with the bottom line and underscore the fact that
even with lost equity, numbers show a vast majority would
pay less were taxes shifted. Those savings could be
invested in stocks or bonds for an equivalent return. And
were the new policy to include a per capita rebate, then
the geonomic package would merely convert one's expected
equity into a certain annuity. Instead of cashing in one
big lump sum later, residents would be cashing in smaller
amounts all along.
A big problem needs a big solution which in
turn needs a matching shift of our prevailing paradigm.
Geonomics -- advocating that we share the social value of
sites and natural resources and untax earnings -- does
just that.
Read the whole
article
Jeff Smith Share Rent,
Transform Society
If society decided to share among its members all
the annual value of society's sites and resources and air
space, what would happen?
... It doesn't matter who owns
what. What matters is who gets the rent. We have
millions of acres of forest we Americans own together,
and we are losing rent on it. ...
What other social relations might change? Increase
land ownership participation in community and it benefits
community, with town hall meetings and block parties.
Those kinds of communities have less crime.
Read the whole
article
Bill Batt: The
Compatibility of Georgist Economics and Ecological
Economics
Hence it becomes important, critically important,
to understand the meaning of “ownership” and
“property” in the Georgist lexicon. But it is
not difficult, for they continue to have their classical
meanings, just as for John Locke, Adam Smith, and all the
major forerunners and thinkers of classical economics
until the advent of neoclassical economics. What was the
meaning of ownership and property in their classical
sense? Property was the product of human labor and
capital, and that alone. Items of property were household
goods, personal attire, armaments, and similar such
goods. Property belonged in the category of capital. Land
was not part of property, but rather was its own
category. Land, broadly defined,
belonged to everyone and was the common heritage of all
humanity.15 One could no
more “own” land than one could own water,
air, or other parts of nature, at least in the sense of
ownership that people often use today. Much like
the native-American concept of ownership, it was part of
what was classically called “ the commons.”
16 “What is
this you call property?” Massasoit, a leader of the
Wampanoag, asked the Plymouth colonists whom he had
befriended in the 1620s. “It cannot be the earth,
for the land is our mother, nourishing all her children,
beasts, birds, fish, and all men. The woods, the streams,
everything on it belongs to everybody and is for the use
of all. How can one man say it belongs to him?”
17 Indeed
Georgists see a moral equivalency between monopoly
ownership of land and nature and the ownership of
slaves!
Georgists' assumptions about property ownership
rest upon premises profoundly different from their
conventional use in western society — indeed
increasingly in world society. In the discourse of legal
philosophy, the notion of property and ownership are
better understood as a collection of legal rights and
responsibilities among people; for example, the right to
possess, to use, to capitalize, to manage, and to retain
the income from such.18 If one disaggregates these
rights, one has a far clearer understanding of the
potential array of socio-economic arrangements that are
possible. The primary distinction to Georgists is that
between ownership for use and ownership for gain. More
will be said about the merit of this division at a later
point, but it should be noted even here that the
distinction is ancient,19 and has had expression at various
times in human history long before the appearance of
Henry George. Two sets of contrasting terms are often
employed to distinguish the separate notions of
ownership:
- leasehold versus freehold, or
- usufruct title versus fee-simple
title.
In fact compensation for land held in usufruct was
far more often in kind than it was in money. Typically,
in Middle Eastern as well as in Asian societies, a
percentage of a crop or of other products gained from the
land were accepted as just payment for its use, paid
usually to a king or nobleman in exchange for services
which they in turn were expected to provide. This usually
meant the protection against ravaging bands, arbitration
of disputes, provision of sustenance in times of
emergency, and so on. The pattern of leasehold ownership
with either in-kind services, goods, or later fees paid
to lords and kings is the hallmark feature of feudalism,
widely known not only in the European past but throughout
Asia and prehistoric Central American
civilizations.
In the Georgist context a
titleholder has the right to ownership of land in
usufruct, but not in fee simple. As long as an owner uses
land and other elements of nature in accord with the
rules and laws of society, one retains a possessory
interest. That interest extends to the privilege
to use land for all purposes consistent with its proper
maintenance and care. It extends even in some cases to
the right to preclude others from any trespass at all.
But what it typically does not include
is the right to any speculative gain that would follow
from title in freehold, or the right to use land beyond
what it is capable of sustaining. Use implies that
its quality is not diminished for the future availability
of others, and that there is an obligation for the user
to pay to society a just price in exchange for such use.
One had no right, for example, to strip a forest of its
trees. Enough is known now about the arrangements of land
ownership and use in comparative perspective to assert
with confidence that the historical practice of title in
fee simple or freehold has been far more the exception
than rule.20
Taking the long view of history, title in usufruct has
been by far the more common pattern of ownership of
natural resources, except where Roman jurisprudence and
its offspring have spread throughout the world and come
to dominate. ...
The justice in the Georgist tradition grows out of
the premise that one is entitled to what one makes with
one’s own hands or mind, but one is not personally
entitled to the gains that grow out of communal efforts.
Those are owed to and should be returned to the
community. The justice inherent in ecological economics,
to the extent that it has solidified, involves a
recognition that preservation of natural capital is in
the interest of everyone. Both recognize and value the
preservation of a world commons in nature. Both
appreciate the diversity preserved in local community
institutions and cultures. Both accept models based on
self-regulating assumptions — in one case using the
phrase “steady state” economics, in the other
case the recovery of land rent in the pursuit of open and
stable markets over monopoly control. There is great
promise in the confluence of the two perspectives: they
offer a solution to the age-old challenge of resolving
what in the world ought to be public and common, and what
else ought to be individual and private. It remains now
for proponents of each perspective to continue exploring
commonalities.
Alternatives that have been tried in the
past, both classic capitalism and socialism, suggest that
neither has served the interests of humanity well in the
long term. Ecological economics has no theory of property
as such, and Georgism here offers a proven course of
application. To Georgists, ownership is linked to use and
not to freehold title. Holding individual property under
license of the community, and under terms which the
community stipulates, is an idea with a long tradition,
well accepted, and needing only to be revived in
contemporary political, legal and economic discourse.
Combined with the pricing device of collecting land rent,
ecological economics will have a tool by which to
circumscribe and even reverse the centrifugal forces of a
new economic imperialism. This is truly the beginning of
a “Third Way” when other theories seem to be
moribund.... read the whole article
Mason Gaffney: 18
Fallacies
2. "Real Property is Sacred and
Untouchable"
Wrong! Suppose this layman writer and the Oregon
Chief Justice were in error, and water permits were real
property. That is out of the frying pan, into the
fire.
What does 'real' mean,
applied to property or estate? It is not the opposite of
'imaginary.' No, 'real' is an elided English form of the
French 'regal' taken into English when English kings spoke
their native French. Real property is The
King's.
We threw out kings in 1783, but not
the royal powers. Rather, we transferred those powers to
our State governments. By succession, real property means
government property!
Every landowner is a tenant of the
king or his successors in interest. The very word 'own'
comes from 'owe.' An owner is one who owes. What he owed
historically was fealty to his sovereign.
That used to mean bending the knee,
kissing the royal foot, swearing allegiance, and showing up
on demand to smite the enemy.
It has evolved into
servitudes like eminent domain, police power, the public
trust doctrine, and something else that our lawyers may
have glided over, but economists underline: the tax
power.
These concepts are basic to common
law which has been brought into every U.S. state
constitution (save Louisiana's). Moses was not just
whistling Dixie when he quoted The Lord as saying "The land
shall not be sold forever; for the land is mine, and ye are
strangers and sojourners with me."
Chief Seattle would have approved. So
would Brigham Young, who founded the once-independent
nation of Deseret on that principle.
Moses was also speaking just as
William the Norman spoke after conquered England, except
that Moses was also a theocrat. "You hold title to this
land from me; observe my rules."
That's the law we have inherited;
that's how the system works. In one form or another it is
found around the world, except in the minds abstract
economic theorists like those of the Chicago
School.... Read the whole
article
Nic
Tideman:
Applications of Land Value Taxation to Problems of
Environmental Protection, Congestion, Efficient Resource
Use, Population, and Economic Growth
The idea that natural opportunities
are everyone's common heritage is often defended with
religious language. John Locke said:
Whether we consider natural reason, which tells us
that men, being once born, have a right to their
preservation, and consequently to meat and drink, and
such other things as nature affords for their sustenance,
or revelation, which gives us an account of those grants
God made of the world to Adam, and to Noah, and his sons,
'tis very clear that God, as King David says, Psal. CXV.
xvi. has given the Earth to the children of men, given it
to mankind in common.2
John Locke did not advocate land
value taxation. Writing in about 1690, he said that there
was so much unclaimed land in America that no one could
properly complain about the private appropriation of land
in Europe.3 Writing nearly 200 year later, when
it was becoming impossible for people to appropriate good
unclaimed land in America, Henry George said:
If we are all here by the equal permission of the
creator, we are all here with an equal title to the
enjoyment of his bounty -- with an equal right to the use
of all that nature so impartially offers. This is a right
which is natural and inalienable; it is a right which
vests in every human being as he enters the world, and
which during his continuance in the world can be limited
only by the equal rights of others. There is in nature no
such thing as a fee simple in land. There is on earth no
power which can rightfully make a grant of exclusive
ownership in land. If all existing men were to unite to
grant away their equal rights, they could not grant away
the right of those who follow them.
George preceded this argument with a
psychological and linguistic one. He said
that our conception of property, of a right of exclusive
possession, is based on the idea that each person has a
right to his or her productive powers, and therefore to
what he or she produces. Since no one produced land, no one
can properly claim to own it.
This psychological and linguistic argument is not
entirely convincing. It seems clear that humans, like
other species, have an impulse toward the appropriation
and defense of territory. Natural selection has worked in
favor of those who are skilled in appropriating natural
opportunities and deterring others from encroaching on
them. It seems possible that, as a way of limiting
violence, humans have merged an idea of ownership based
on production with an idea of ownership based on the
ability to appropriate territory and deter
encroachment.If this is the social and biological
reality, then there is a different argument for treating
natural opportunities as everyone's common
heritage. ...
Read the entire article
Henry George:
The Land Question (1881)
The galleys that carried Caesar to Britain, the
accoutrements of his legionaries, the baggage that they
carried, the arms that they bore, the buildings that they
erected; the scythed chariots of the ancient Britons, the
horses that drew them, their wicker boats and wattled
houses–where are they now? But the land for which
Roman and Briton fought, there it is still. That British
soil is yet as fresh and as new as it was in the days of
the Romans. Generation after generation has lived on it
since, and generation after generation will live on it
yet. Now, here is a very great difference. The
right to possess and to pass on the ownership of things
that in their nature decay and soon cease to be is a very
different thing from the right to possess and to pass on
the ownership of that which does not decay, but from
which each successive generation must live.
To show how this difference between land and such
other species of property as are properly styled wealth
bears upon the argument for the vested rights of
landholders, let me illustrate again.
Captain Kidd was a pirate. He made a business of
sailing the seas, capturing merchantmen, making their
crews walk the plank, and appropriating their cargoes. In
this way he accumulated much wealth, which he is thought
to have buried. But let us suppose, for the sake of the
illustration, that he did not bury his wealth, but left
it to his legal heirs, and they to their heirs and so on,
until at the present day this wealth or a part of it has
come to a great-great-grandson of Captain Kidd. Now, let
us suppose that some one – say a
great-great-grandson of one of the shipmasters whom
Captain Kidd plundered, makes complaint, and says: "This
man's great-great-grandfather plundered my
great-great-grandfather of certain things or certain
sums, which have been transmitted to him, whereas but for
this wrongful act they would have been transmitted to me;
therefore, I demand that he be made to restore them."
What would society answer?
Society, speaking by its proper tribunals, and in
accordance with principles recognized among all civilized
nations, would say: "We cannot entertain such a demand.
It may be true that Mr. Kidd's great-great-grandfather
robbed your great-great-grandfather, and that as the
result of this wrong he has got things that otherwise
might have come to you. But we cannot inquire into
occurrences that happened so long ago. Each generation
has enough to do to attend to its own affairs. If we go
to righting the wrongs and reopening the controversies of
our great-great-grandfathers, there will be endless
disputes and pretexts for dispute. What you say may be
true, but somewhere we must draw the line, and have an
end to strife. Though this man's great-great-grandfather
may have robbed your great-great-grandfather, he has not
robbed you. He came into possession of these things
peacefully, and has held them peacefully, and we must
take this peaceful possession, when it has been continued
for a certain time, as absolute evidence of just title;
for, were we not to do that, there would be no end to
dispute and no secure possession of anything."
Now, it is this common-sense principle that is
expressed in the statute of limitations – in the
doctrine of vested rights. This is the
reason why it is held – and as to most things held
justly – that peaceable possession for
a certain time cures all defects of title.
But let us pursue the illustration a little
further:
Let us suppose that Captain Kidd, having established a
large and profitable piratical business, left it to his
son, and he to his son, and so on, until the
great-great-grandson, who now pursues it, has come to
consider it the most natural thing in the world that his
ships should roam the sea, capturing peaceful
merchantmen, making their crews walk the plank, and
bringing home to him much plunder, whereby he is enabled,
though he does no work at all, to live in very great
luxury, and look down with contempt upon people who have
to work. But at last, let us suppose, the merchants get
tired of having their ships sunk and their goods taken,
and sailors get tired of trembling for their lives every
time a sail lifts above the horizon, and they demand of
society that piracy be stopped.
Now, what should society say if Mr. Kidd got
indignant, appealed to the doctrine of vested rights, and
asserted that society was bound to prevent any
interference with the business that he had inherited, and
that, if it wanted him to stop, it must buy him out,
paying him all that his business was worth–that is
to say, at least as much as he could make in twenty
years' successful pirating, so that if he stopped
pirating he could still continue to live in luxury off of
the profits of the merchants and the earnings of the
sailors?
What ought society to say to such a claim as this?
There will be but one answer. We will all say that
society should tell Mr. Kidd that his was a business to
which the statute of limitations and the doctrine of
vested rights did not apply; that because his father, and
his grandfather, and his great- and
great-great-grandfather pursued the business of capturing
ships and making their crews walk the plank, was no
reason why lie should be permitted to pursue it. Society,
we will all agree, ought to say he would have to stop
piracy and stop it at once, and that without getting a
cent for stopping.
Or supposing it had happened that Mr. Kidd had sold
out his piratical business to Smith, Jones, or Robinson,
we will all agree that society ought to say that their
purchase of the business gave them no greater right than
Mr. Kidd had.
We will all agree that that is what society ought to
say. Observe, I do not ask what society would say.
For, ridiculous and preposterous as it may appear, I
am satisfied that, under the circumstances I have
supposed, society would not for a long time say what we
have agreed it ought to say. Not only would all the Kidds
loudly claim that to make them give up their business
without full recompense would be a wicked interference
with vested rights, but the justice of this claim would
at first be assumed as a matter of course by all or
nearly all the influential classes–the great
lawyers, the able journalists, the writers for the
magazines, the eloquent clergymen, and the principal
professors in the principal universities. Nay, even the
merchants and sailors, when they first began to complain,
would be so tyrannized and browbeaten by this public
opinion that they would hardly think of more than of
buying out the Kidds, and, wherever here and there any
one dared to raise his voice in favor of stopping piracy
at once and without compensation, he would only do so
under penalty of being stigmatized as a reckless
disturber and wicked foe of social order.
If any one denies this, if any one says mankind are
not such fools, then I appeal to universal history to
bear me witness. I appeal to the facts of to-day.
Show me a wrong, no matter how monstrous, that ever
yet, among any people, became ingrafted in the social
system, and I will prove to you the truth of what I say.
...
What is the slave-trade but piracy of the worst kind?
Yet it is not long since the slave-trade was looked upon
as a perfectly respectable business, affording as
legitimate an opening for the investment of capital and
the display of enterprise as any other. The proposition
to prohibit it was first looked upon as ridiculous, then
as fanatical, then as wicked. It was only slowly and by
hard fighting that the truth in regard to it gained
ground. Does not our very Constitution bear witness to
what I say? Does not the fundamental law of the nation,
adopted twelve years after the enunciation of the
Declaration of Independence, declare that for twenty
years the slave-trade shall not be prohibited nor
restricted? Such dominion had the idea of vested
interests over the minds of those who had already
proclaimed the inalienable right of man to life, liberty,
and the pursuit of happiness! ...
read the whole
article
Nic Tideman:
The Case for Site Value Rating
In primitive societies, land is generally regarded as
not ownable. No one made the land, so how can anyone own
it? Ownership generally originates in conquest. In
England, titles to land originated in the claim of
William the Conqueror to own all the land because he was
king. He granted to dukes, earls, etc. the right to
collect rent from designated territories in exchange for
their promises to fulfill various obligations to him. In
the seventeenth century the nobility succeeded in
removing all of their obligations to the crown, but they
retained their rights to land. A substantial part of the
great inequality in wealth in the United Kingdom can be
traced to ancient patents of nobility that granted rights
to collect rent.
One highly visible consequence of allowing land rents
to be privately appropriated is that young people find it
nearly impossible to buy houses. The price of a "house,"
in the Southeast of Britain at least, is primarily the
price of land. If the rent of land were collected
publicly, the price of land would be inconsequential, and
the price of a house would be the cost of the materials
and labour that went into building it. It should be
recognized that if the site value of land were taxed, the
payment of such taxes would make it more expensive to
live in large cities than in small towns, but young
people would be better able to afford it because other
taxes would be reduced, and the mortgages to which people
would need to commit themselves would not be nearly as
great.
The justice of collecting the rent of land can be
generalized to the justice of collecting a fee for any
privilege that governments grant to some individuals and
not others. ...
read the whole article
Charles T. Root — Not a Single Tax! (1925)
But again the voice of the objector is heard, possibly
to this effect: "This plan may be all right for the
community, but how about poor Mr. Rhinelastor?"
In reality the landowner would not suffer so much from
the restoration of the public revenue as might at first
appear. For one thing, whereas he is now taxed, at least
in theory, not only on land, but on buildings, cash,
bonds, and all other personal property, and perhaps on
his income as well, he would then have no taxes at all to
pay. Furthermore the economic rent is not the full
measure of the possible earning capacity of the land, but
will always be less than the offerer expects to make out
of its use.
Again, while it must be firmly insisted that the
economic rent is the rightful property of the community
and not of the landowner, the community would probably
never take it all. Communal ownership of land is not
desirable, even if it were practicable. Individual
ownership and management are best, and it is not at all
improper for the community to allow the owner something
for caring for the land to which he holds title, and for
collecting and transmitting to the treasury the economic
rent. ... read the whole
article
Peter Barnes:
Capitalism 3.0 — Chapter 2: A Short History of
Capitalism (pages 15-32)
In the beginning, the commons was everywhere. Humans
and other animals roamed around it, hunting and
gathering. Like other species, we had territories, but
these were tribal, not individual.
About ten thousand years ago, human agriculture and
permanent settlements arose, and with them came private
property. Rulers granted ownership of land to heads of
families (usually males). Often, military conquerors
distributed land to their lieutenants. Titles could then
be passed to heirs — typically, oldest sons got
everything.
In Europe, Roman law codified many of these practices.
Despite the growth in private property, much land in
Europe remained part of the commons. In Roman times,
bodies of water, shorelines, wildlife, and air were
explicitly classified as res communes, resources
available to all. During the Middle Ages, kings and
feudal lords often claimed title to rivers, forests, and
wild animals, only to have such claims periodically
rebuked. The Magna Carta, which King John of England was
forced to sign in 1215, established forests and fisheries
as res communes. Given that forests were sources of game,
firewood, building materials, medicinal herbs, and
grazing for livestock, this was no small shift.
In the seventeenth century, John Locke sought to
balance the commons and private property. Like others of
his era, he saw that private property doesn’t exist
in a vacuum; it exists in relationship to a commons,
vis-à-vis which there are takings and leavings. The
rationale for private property is that it boosts economic
production, but the commons has a rationale, too: it
provides sustenance for all. Both sides must be
respected.
Locke believed that God gave the earth to
“mankind in common,” but that private
property is justified because it spurs humans to work.
Whenever a person mixes his labor with nature, he
“joins to it something that is his own, and thereby
makes it his property.” But here Locke added an
important proviso: “For this labor being the
unquestionable property of the laborer,” he wrote,
“no man but he can have a right to what that is
once joined to, at least where there is enough, and as
good, left in common for others.” In other words, a
person can acquire property, but there’s a limit to
how much he or she can rightfully appropriate. That limit
is set by two considerations: first, it should be no more
than he can join his labor to, and second, it has to
leave “enough and as good” in common for
others. This was consistent with English common law at
the time, which held, for example, that a riparian
landowner could withdraw water for his own use, but
couldn’t diminish the supply available to
others.
Despite Locke’s quest for balance, the English
commons didn’t last. In the eighteenth and
nineteenth centuries, the movement to enclose and
privatize it accelerated greatly. According to historian
Karl Polanyi, this enclosure was the great transformation
that launched the modern era. Local gentry, backed by
Parliament, fenced off village lands and converted them
to private holdings. Impoverished peasants then drifted
to cities and became industrial workers. Landlords
invested their agricultural profits in manufacturing, and
modern times, economically speaking, began.
One observer of this transformation was Thomas Paine,
America’s pro-independence pamphleteer. Seeing how
enclosure of the commons benefited a few and disinherited
many others, Paine proposed a remedy — not a
reversal of enclosure, which he considered necessary for
economic reasons, but compensation for it.
Like Locke, Paine believed nature was a gift of God to
all. “There are two kinds of property,” he
wrote. “Firstly, natural property, or that which
comes to us from the Creator of the universe — such
as the earth, air, water. Secondly, artificial or
acquired property — the invention of men.” In
the latter, he went on, equality is impossible, but in
the former, “all individuals have legitimate
birthrights.” Since such birthrights were
diminished by enclosure, there ought to be an
“indemnification for that loss.” ...
read the whole chapter
Peter Barnes:
Capitalism 3.0 — Chapter 3: The Limits of Government
(pages 33-48)
Three points are worth making here.
- First, ownership isn’t the same thing as
trusteeship. Owners of property — even government
owners — have wide latitude to do whatever they
want with it; a trustee does not. Trustees are bound by
the terms of their trust and by centuries-old
principles of trusteeship, foremost among which is
“undivided loyalty” to beneficiaries.
- Second, in a capitalist democracy, the state is a
dispenser of many valuable prizes. Whoever amasses the
most political power wins the most valuable prizes. The
rewards include property rights, friendly regulators,
subsidies, tax breaks, and free or cheap use of the
commons. The notion that the state promotes “the
common good” is sadly naive.
- Third, while free marketers are fond of saying that
capitalism is a precondition for democracy, what they
neglect to add is that capitalism also distorts
democracy. Like gravity, its tug is constant. The
bigger the concentrations of capital, the stronger the
tug.
We face a disheartening quandary here.
Profit-maximizing corporations dominate our economy.
Their programming makes them enclose and diminish common
wealth. The only obvious counterweight is government, yet
government is dominated by these same corporations.
One possible way out of this dilemma is to reprogram
corporations — that is, to make them driven by
something other than profit. This, however, is like
asking elephants to dance — they’re just not
built to do it. Corporations are built to make money, and
the truth is, as a society we want them to make money.
We’ll look at this further in the next chapter.
Another possible way out is to liberate government
from corporations, not just momentarily, but
long-lastingly. This is easier said than done.
Corporations have decimated their old adversary,
organized labor, and turned the media into their
mouthpiece. Occasionally a breakthrough is made in
campaign financing — for example, corporations are
now barred from giving so-called soft money to political
parties — but corporate money soon finds other
channels to flow through. The return on such investments
is simply too high to stop them.
Does this mean there’s no hope? I don’t
think so. The window of opportunity is small, but not
nonexistent. Throughout American history, anticorporate
forces have come to power once or twice per century. In
the nineteenth century, we had the eras of Jackson and
Lincoln; in the twentieth century, those of Theodore and
Franklin Roosevelt. Twenty-first century equivalents
will, I’m sure, arise. It may take a calamity of
some sort — another war, a depression, or an
ecological disaster — to trigger the next
anticorporate ascendancy, but sooner or later it will
come. Our job is to be ready when it comes. ...
read the whole chapter
Peter Barnes:
Capitalism 3.0 — Chapter 7: Universal Birthrights
(pages 101-116)
Dividends from Common Assets
A cushion of reliable income is a wonderful thing. It
can be saved for rainy days or used to pursue happiness
on sunny days. It can encourage people to take risks,
care for friends and relatives, or volunteer for
community service. For low-income families, it can pay
for basic necessities.
Conversely, the absence of reliable income is a
terrible thing. It heightens anxiety and fear. It
diminishes our ability to cope with crises and
transitions. It traps many families on the knife’s
edge of poverty, and makes it harder for the poor to
rise.
So why don’t we, as Monopoly does, pay everyone
some regular income — not through redistribution of
income, but through predistribution of common property?
One state — Alaska — already does this. As
noted earlier, the Alaska Permanent Fund uses revenue
from state oil leases to invest in stocks, bonds, and
similar assets, and from those investments pays yearly
dividends to every resident. Alaska’s model can be
extended to any state or nation, whether or not they have
oil. We could, for instance, have an American Permanent
Fund that pays equal dividends to long-term residents of
all 50 states. The reason is, we jointly own many
valuable assets.
Recall our discussion about common property trusts.
These trusts could crank down pollution and earn money
from selling ever-scarcer pollution permits. The scarcer
the permits get, the higher their prices would go. Less
pollution would equal more revenue. Over time, trillions
of dollars could flow into an American Permanent
Fund.
What could we do with that common income? In Alaska
the deal with oil revenue is 75 percent to government and
25 percent to citizens. For an American Permanent Fund,
I’d favor a 50/50 split, because paying dividends
to citizens is so important. Also, when scarce ecosystems
are priced above zero, the cost of living will go up and
people will need compensation; this wasn’t, and
isn’t, the case in Alaska. I’d also favor
earmarking the government’s dollars for specific
public goods, rather than tossing them into the general
treasury. This not only ensures identifiable public
benefits; it also creates constituencies who’ll
defend the revenue sharing system.
Waste absorption isn’t the only common resource
an American Permanent Fund could tap. Consider also, the
substantial contribution society makes to stock market
values. As noted earlier, private corporations can
inflate their value dramatically by selling shares on a
regulated stock exchange. The extra value derives from
the enlarged market of investors who can now buy the
corporation’s shares. Given a total stock market
valuation of about $15 trillion, this socially created
liquidity premium is worth roughly $5 trillion.
At the moment, this $5 trillion gift flows mostly to
the 5 percent of the population that own more than half
the private wealth. But if we wanted to, we could spread
it around. We could do that by charging corporations for
using the public trading system, just as investment
bankers do. (For those of you who haven’t been
involved in a public stock offering, investment bankers
are like fancy doormen to a free palace. While the public
charges almost nothing to use the capital markets,
investment bankers exact hefty fees.)
The public’s fee could be in cash or stock.
Let’s say we required publicly traded companies to
deposit 1 percent of their shares each year in the
American Permanent Fund for ten years — reaching a
total of 10 percent of their shares. This would be our
price not just for using a regulated stock exchange, but
also for all the other privileges (limited liability,
perpetual life, copyrights and patents, and so on) that
we currently bestow on private corporations for free.
In due time, the American Permanent Fund would have a
diversified portfolio worth several trillion dollars.
Like its Alaskan counterpart, it would pay equal yearly
dividends to everyone. As the stock market rose and fell,
so would everyone’s dividend checks. A rising tide
would lift all boats. America would truly be an
“ownership society.”
A Children’s Opportunity Trust
Not long ago, while researching historic documents for
this book, I stumbled across this sentence in the
Northwest Ordinance of 1787: “[T]he estates, both
of resident and nonresident proprietors in the said
territory, dying intestate, shall descent to, and be
distributed among their children, and the descendants of
a deceased child, in equal parts.” What, I
wondered, was this about?
The answer, I soon learned, was primogeniture —
or more precisely, ending primogeniture in America.
Jefferson, Madison, and other early settlers believed the
feudal practice of passing all or most property from
father to eldest son had no place in the New World. This
wasn’t about equal rights for women; that notion
didn’t arise until later. Rather, it was about
leveling the economic playing and avoiding a permanent
aristocracy.
A nation in which everyone owned some property —
in those days, this meant land — was what Jefferson
and his contemporaries had in mind. In such a society,
hard work and merit would be rewarded, while inherited
privilege would be curbed. This vision of America
wasn’t wild romanticism; it seemed quite achievable
at the time, given the vast western frontier. What
thwarted it, later, were giveaways of land to speculators
and railroads, the rise of monopolies, and the colossal
untaxed fortunes of the robber barons.
Fast-forward to the twenty-first century. Land is no
longer the basis for most wealth; stock ownership is. But
Jefferson’s vision of an ownership society is still
achievable. The means for achieving it lies not, as
George W. Bush has misleadingly argued, in the
privatization of Social Security and health insurance,
but in guaranteeing an inheritance to every child. In a
country as super-affluent as ours, there’s
absolutely no reason why we can’t do that. (In
fact, Great Britain has already done it. Every British
child born after 2002 gets a trust fund seeded by $440
from the government — $880 for children in the
poorest 40 percent of families. All interest earned by
the trust funds is tax-free.)
Let me get personal for a minute. My parents
weren’t wealthy; both were children of penniless
immigrants. They worked hard, saved, and invested —
and paid my full tuition at Harvard. Later, they helped
me buy a home and start a business. Without their
financial assistance, I wouldn’t have achieved the
success that I have. I, in turn, have set up trust funds
for my two sons. As I did, they’ll have money for
college educations, buying their own homes, and if they
choose, starting their own businesses — in other
words, what they need to get ahead in a capitalist
system.
As I hope my sons will be, I’m extremely
grateful for my economic good fortune. At the same time,
I’m painfully aware that my family’s good
fortune is far from universal. Many second-, third-, and
even seventh-generation Americans have little or no
savings to pass on to their heirs. Their children may
receive their parents’ love and tutelage, but they
don’t get the cash needed nowadays for a first-rate
education, a down payment on a house, or a business
venture. A few may rise because of extraordinary talent
and luck, but the majority will spend their lives on a
treadmill, paying bills and perhaps tucking a little away
for old age. Their sons and daughters, in turn, will face
a similar future.
It doesn’t have to be this way. One can imagine
all sorts of government programs that can help people
advance in life — free college and graduate school,
GI bills, housing subsidies, and so on. Such programs, as
we know, come and go, and I prefer more rather than less
of them. But the simplest way to help people advance is
to give them what my parents gave me, and what I’m
giving my sons: a cash inheritance. And the surest way to
do that is to build such inheritances into our economic
operating system, much the way Social Security is.
When Jefferson substituted pursuit of happiness for
Locke’s property, he wasn’t denigrating the
importance of property. Without presuming to read his
mind, I assume he altered Locke’s wording to make
the point that property isn’t an end in itself, but
merely a means to the higher end of happiness. In fact,
the importance he and other Founders placed on property
can be seen throughout the Constitution and its early
amendments. Happiness, they evidently thought, may be the
ultimate goal, but property is darn useful in the pursuit
of it.
If this was true in the eighteenth century, it’s
even truer in the twenty-first. The unalienable right to
pursue happiness is fairly meaningless under capitalism
without a chunk of capital to get started.
And while Social Security provides a cushion for the
back end of life, it does nothing for the front end.
That’s where we need something new.
A kitty for the front end of life has to be financed
differently than Social Security because children
can’t contribute in advance to their own
inheritances. But the same principle of intergenerational
solidarity can apply. Consider an intergenerational
transfer fund through which departing souls leave money
not just for their own children, but for all children.
This could replace the current inheritance tax, which is
under assault in any case. (As this is written, Congress
has temporarily phased out the inheritance tax as of
2010; a move is afoot to make the phaseout permanent.)
Mind you, I think ending the inheritance tax is a
terrible idea; it’s the least distorting (in the
sense of discouraging economic activity) and most
progressive tax possible. It also seems sadly ironic that
a nation that began by abolishing primogeniture is now on
the verge of creating a permanent aristocracy of wealth.
That said, if the inheritance tax is eliminated, an
intergenerational transfer fund would be a fitting
substitute.
The basic idea is similar to the revenue recycling
system of professional sports. Winners — that is,
millionaires and billionaires — would put money
into a kitty (call it the Children’s Opportunity
Trust), to be divided among all children equally, so the
next round of economic play can be more competitive. In
this case, the winners will have had a lifetime to enjoy
their wealth, rather than just a single season. When they
depart, half their estates, say, could be passed to their
own children, while the other half would be distributed
among all children. Their own offspring would still start
on third base, but others would at least be in the
game.
Under this plan, no money would go to the government.
Instead, every penny would go back into the market,
through the bank or brokerage accounts (managed by
parents) of newborn children. I’d call these new
accounts Individual Inheritance Accounts; they’d be
front-of-life counterparts of Individual Retirement
Accounts. After children turn eighteen, they could
withdraw from their accounts for further education, a
first home purchase, or to start a business.
Yes, contributions to the Children’s Opportunity
Trust would be mandatory, at least for estates over a
certain size (say $1 or $2 million). But such end-of-life
gifts to society are entirely appropriate, given that so
much of a millionaire’s wealth is, in reality, a
gift from society. No one has expressed this better than
Bill Gates Sr., father of the world’s richest
person. “We live in a place which is orderly.
It’s a place where markets work because
there’s legal structure to support them. It’s
a place where people can own property and protect it.
People who have the good fortune, the skill, the luck to
become wealthy in our country, simply have a debt to the
source of their opportunity.”
I like the link between end-of-life recycling and
start-of-life inheritances because it so nicely connects
the passing of one generation with the coming of another.
It also connects those who have received much from
society with those who have received little;
there’s justice as well as symmetry in that.
To top things off, I like to think that the
contributors — millionaires and billionaires all
— will feel less resentful about repaying their
debts to society if their repayments go directly to
children, rather than to the Internal Revenue Service.
They might think of the Children’s Opportunity
Trust as a kind of venture capital fund that makes
startup investments in American children. A venture
capital fund assumes nine out of ten investments
won’t pay back, but the tenth will pay back in
spades, more than compensating for the losers. So with
the Children’s Opportunity Trust. If one out of ten
children eventually departs this world with an estate
large enough to “pay back” in spades the
initial investment, then the trust will have earned its
keep. And who knows? Some of those paying back might even
feel good about it. ...
read the whole chapter
see also: http://www.landandfreedom.org/news/42505.htm
|
To share this page with a friend:
right click, choose "send," and add your
comments.
|
|
Red links have not been
visited; .
Green links are pages you've seen
|
Essential Documents pertinent
to this theme:
|
|