Rent as God's Provisioning for
All
Talk about intelligent design! As towns
— and cities and societies — grow, there
arises a social surplus. Plan A calls for it to be
privatized by those who are God's eldest sons. Plan B
recognizes that the surplus belongs equally to all of
us, because we were created
equal. Georgist thought is based on the
idea that we're all created equal, and none of us
should be able to privatize that which
all of us create. We consider
the privatization of the commons a serious form of
theft that needs to be recognized and corrected.
Our Father, who art in heaven, Hallowed be thy
Name. Thy kingdom come. Thy will be done, On earth as it
is in heaven. Give us this day our daily bread. And
forgive us our trespasses, As we forgive those who
trespass against us. Lead us not into temptation, but
deliver us from evil. For thine is the kingdom, and the
power, and the glory, for ever and ever. Amen.
Might one of the temptations which we
pray not to be led into be the temptation to allow some
of us to steal from others of us? Might one of the
evils be a system under which some of us
get to keep huge amounts of land rent, while others labor
long hours to be able to afford the bare necessities? Or
shall we just not investigate this avenue, and just to
continue to allow some of us to steal from others —
and file it under "forgive us our trespasses as we
forgive those who trespass against us?"
Should the rent on land be provisioning for a
few of us? Or is it somehow
different from the return (interest) on buildings
(capital), and therefore rightly the revenue source from
which our common needs should be funded?
Georgists will argue the latter: that God created the
land for all of us, that none of us is
entitled to privatize it, and that the way to equalize
our positions is to collect from those who own choice
sites the lion's share of the annual economic value of
those sites. This doesn't disturb title or property
rights; it only socializes that which is inherently
common: the value of the natural creation.
The opening paragraphs from the prologue to David
Brion Davis's Inhuman Bondage: The Rise and Fall of
Slavery in the New World are these:
In 1770, on the eve of the American
Revolution, African American slavery was legal and
almost unquestioned throughout the New World. The
ghastly slave trade from Africa was still expanding and
for many decades had been shipping five Africans across
the Atlantic for every European immigrant to the
Americas. An imaginary "hemispheric traveler" would
have seen black slaves in every colony from Canada and
New England all the way south to Spanish Peru and
Chile. In the incomparably rich colonies in the
Caribbean, they often constituted population majorities
of 90 percent or more. But in 1888, one hundred and
eighteen years later, when Brazil finally freed all its
slaves, the institution had been outlawed throughout
the Western Hemisphere.
This final act of liberation, building
on Abraham Lincoln's emancipation achievement in the
American Civil War, took place only a century after the
creation of the first antislavery societies in human
history — initially small groups in such places
as Philadelphia, London, Manchester, and New York.
The abolition of New World slavery depended
in large measure on a major transformation in moral
perception — on the emergence of writers,
speakers, and reformers, beginning in the
mid-eighteenth century, who were willing to condemn an
institution that had been sanctioned for thousands of
years and who also strove to make human society
something more than an endless contest of greed and
power. [emphasis mine]
Henry George: The
Common Sense of Taxation (1881 article)
To consider the nature of property of this kind is
again to see a clear distinction. That distinction is
not, as the lawyers have it, between movables and
immovables, between personal property and real estate.
The true distinction is between property which is, and
property which is not, the result of human labor; or, to
use the terms of political economy, between land and
wealth. For, in any precise use of the term, land is not
wealth, any more than labor is wealth. Land and labor are
the factors of production. Wealth is such result of their
union as retains the capacity of ministering to human
desire. A lot and the house which stands upon it are
alike property, alike have a tangible value, and are
alike classed as real estate. But there are between them
the most essential differences. The one is the free gift
of Nature, the other the result of human exertion; the
one exists from generation to generation, while men come
and go; the other is constantly tending to decay, and can
only be preserved by continual exertion. To the one, the
right of exclusive possession, which makes it individual
property, can, like the right of property in slaves, be
traced to nothing but municipal law; to the other, the
right of exclusive property springs clearly from those
natural relations which are among the primary perceptions
of the human mind. Nor are these mere abstract
distinctions. They are distinctions of the first
importance in determining what should and what should not
be taxed.
For, keeping in mind the fact that all wealth is the
result of human exertion, it is clearly seen that, having
in view the promotion of the general prosperity,
it is the height of absurdity to tax wealth for
purposes of revenue while there remains, unexhausted by
taxation, any value attaching to land. We may tax land
values as much as we please, without in the slightest
degree lessening the amount of land, or the capabilities
of land, or the inducement to use land. But we
cannot tax wealth without lessening the inducement to the
production of wealth, and decreasing the amount of
wealth. We might take the whole value of land in
taxation, so as to make the ownership of land worth
nothing, and the land would still remain, and be as
useful as before. The effect would be to throw
land open to users free of price, and thus to increase
its capabilities, which are brought out by increased
population. But impose anything like such taxation upon
wealth, and the inducement to the production of wealth
would be gone. Movable wealth would be hidden or carried
off, immovable wealth would be suffered to go to decay,
and where was prosperity would soon be the silence of
desolation.
And the reason of this difference is clear. The
possession of wealth is the inducement to the exertion
necessary to the production and maintenance of wealth.
Men do not work for the pleasure of working, but to get
the things their work will give them. And to tax the
things that are produced by exertion is to lessen the
inducement to exertion. But over and above the benefit to
the possessor, which is the stimulating motive to the
production of wealth, there is a benefit to the
community, for no matter how selfish he may be, it is
utterly impossible for any one to entirely keep to
himself the benefit of any desirable thing he may
possess. These diffused benefits when localized give
value to land, and this may be taxed without in any wise
diminishing the incentive to production.
To illustrate: A man builds a fine house or large
factory in a poorly improved neighborhood. To tax this
building and its adjuncts is to make him pay for his
enterprise and expenditure — to take from him part
of his natural reward. But the improvement thus made has
given new beauty or life to the neighborhood, making it a
more desirable place than before for the erection of
other houses or factories, and additional value is given
to land all about. Now to tax improvements is not only to
deprive of his proper reward the man who has made the
improvement, but it is to deter others from making
similar improvements. But, instead of taxing
improvements, to tax these land values is to leave the
natural inducement to further improvement in full force,
and at the same time to keep down an obstacle to further
improvement, which, under the present system, improvement
itself tends to raise. For the advance of land values
which follows improvement, and even the expectation of
improvement, makes further improvement more costly.
See how unjust and short-sighted is this system. Here
is a man who, gathering what little capital he can, and
taking his family, starts West to find a place where he
can make himself a home. He must travel long distances;
for, though he will pass plenty of land nobody is using,
it is held at prices too high for him. Finally he will go
no further, and selects a place where, since the creation
of the world, the soil, so far as we know, has never felt
a plowshare. But here, too, in nine cases out of ten, he
will find the speculator has been ahead of him, for the
speculator moves quicker, and has superior means of
information to the emigrant. Before he can put
this land to the use for which nature intended it, and to
which it is for the general good that it should be put,
he must make terms with some man who in all probability
never saw the land, and never dreamed of using it, and
who, it may be, resides in some city, thousands of miles
away. In order to get permission to use this
land, he must give up a large part of the little capital
which is seed-wheat to him, and perhaps in addition
mortgage his future labor for years. Still he goes to
work: he works himself, and his wife works, and his
children work — work like horses, and live in the
hardest and dreariest manner. Such a man deserves
encouragement, not discouragement; but on him taxation
falls with peculiar severity. Almost everything that he
has to buy — groceries, clothing, tools — is
largely raised in price by a system of tariff taxation
which cannot add to the price of the grain or hogs or
cattle that he has to sell. And when the assessor comes
around he is taxed on the improvements he has made,
although these improvements have added not only to the
value of surrounding land, but even to the value of land
in distant commercial centers. Not merely this, but, as a
general rule, his land, irrespective of the improvements,
will be assessed at a higher rate than unimproved land
around it, on the ground that "productive property" ought
to pay more than "unproductive property" — a
principle just the reverse of the correct one, for the
man who makes land productive adds to the general
prosperity, while the man who keeps land unproductive
stands in the way of the general prosperity, is but a
dog-in-the-manger, who prevents others from using what he
will not use himself.
Or, take the case of the railroads. That railroads are
a public benefit no one will dispute. We want more
railroads, and want them to reduce their fares and
freight. Why then should we tax them? for taxes upon
railroads deter from railroad building, and compel higher
charges. Instead of taxing the railroads, is it not clear
that we should rather tax the increased value which they
give to land? To tax railroads is to check railroad
building, to reduce profits, and compel higher rates; to
tax the value they give to land is to increase railroad
business and permit lower rates. The elevated railroads,
for instance, have opened to the overcrowded population
of New York the wide, vacant spaces of the upper part of
the island. But this great public benefit is neutralized
by the rise in land values. Because these vacant lots can
be reached more cheaply and quickly, their owners demand
more for them, and so the public gain in one way is
offset in another, while the roads lose the business they
would get were not building checked by the high prices
demanded for lots. The increase of land values, which the
elevated roads have caused, is not merely no advantage to
them — it is an injury; and it is clearly a public
injury. The elevated railroads ought not to be taxed. The
more profit they make, with the better conscience can
they be asked to still further reduce fares. It is the
increased land values which they have created that ought
to be taxed, for taxing them will give the public the
full benefit of cheap fares.
So with railroads everywhere. And so not alone with
railroads, but with all industrial enterprises. So long
as we consider that community most prosperous which
increases most rapidly in wealth, so long is it the
height of absurdity for us to tax wealth in any of its
beneficial forms. We should tax what we want to
repress, not what we want to encourage. We should tax
that which results from the general prosperity, not that
which conduces to it. It is the increase of population,
the extension of cultivation, the manufacture of goods,
the building of houses and ships and railroads, the
accumulation of capital, and the growth of commerce that
add to the value of land — not the increase in the
value of land that induces the increase of population and
increase of wealth. It is not that the land of
Manhattan Island is now worth hundreds of millions where,
in the time of the early Dutch settlers, it was only
worth dollars, that there are on it now so many more
people, and so much more wealth. It is because of the
increase of population and the increase of wealth that
the value of the land has so much increased.
Increase of land values tends of itself to repel
population and prevent improvement. And thus the taxation
of land values, unlike taxation of other property, does
not tend to prevent the increase of wealth, but rather to
stimulate it. It is the taking of the golden egg, not the
choking of the goose that lays it.
Every consideration of policy and ethics squares with
this conclusion. The tax upon land values is the most
economically perfect of all taxes. It does not raise
prices; it maybe collected at least cost, and with the
utmost ease and certainty; it leaves in full strength all
the springs of production; and, above all, it consorts
with the truest equality and the highest justice.
For, to take for the common purposes of the
community that value which results from the growth of the
community, and to free industry and enterprise and thrift
from burden and restraint, is to leave to each that which
he fairly earns, and to assert the first and most
comprehensive of equal rights — the equal right of
all to the land on which, and from which, all must
live.
Thus it is that the scheme of taxation which conduces
to the greatest production is also that which conduces to
the fairest distribution, and that in the proper
adjustment of taxation lies not merely the possibility of
enormously increasing the general wealth, but the
solution of these pressing social and political problems
which spring from unnatural inequality in the
distribution of wealth.
"There is," says M. de Laveleye, in concluding that
work in which he shows that the first perceptions of
mankind have everywhere recognized a most vital
distinction between property in land and property which
results from labor, — "there is in human affairs
one system which is the best; it is not that system which
always exists, otherwise why should we desire to change
it; but it is that system which should exist for the
greatest good of humanity. God knows it, and wills it;
man's duty it is to discover and establish it." ...
read the whole
article
H.G. Brown: Significant
Paragraphs from Henry George's Progress &
Poverty: 10. Effect of Remedy Upon Wealth
Production (in the unabridged P&P:
Part IX — Effects of the Remedy: Chapter 1 — Of
the effect upon the production of wealth)
The elder Mirabeau, we are told, ranked the
proposition of Quesnay, to substitute one single tax on
rent (the impôt unique) for all other
taxes, as a discovery equal in utility to the invention
of writing or the substitution of the use of money for
barter.
To whosoever will think over the matter, this saying
will appear an evidence of penetration rather than of
extravagance. The advantages which would be gained by
substituting for the numerous taxes by which the public
revenues are now raised, a single tax levied upon the
value of land, will appear more and more important the
more they are considered. ...
Consider the effect upon the production of wealth.
To abolish the taxation which, acting and reacting,
now hampers every wheel of exchange and presses upon
every form of industry, would be like removing an immense
weight from a powerful spring. Imbued with fresh energy,
production would start into new life, and trade would
receive a stimulus which would be felt to the remotest
arteries. The present method of taxation operates upon
exchange like artificial deserts and mountains;
- it costs more to get goods through a custom house
than it does to carry them around the world.
- It operates upon energy, and industry, and skill,
and thrift, like a fine upon those qualities.
- If I have worked harder and built myself a good
house while you have been contented to live in a hovel,
the taxgatherer now comes annually to make me pay a
penalty for my energy and industry, by taxing me more
than you.
- If I have saved while you wasted, I am mulct, while
you are exempt.
- If a man build a ship we make him pay for his
temerity, as though he had done an injury to the
state;
- if a railroad be opened, down comes the tax
collector upon it, as though it were a public
nuisance;
- if a manufactory be erected we levy upon it an
annual sum which would go far toward making a handsome
profit.
- We say we want capital, but if any one accumulate
it, or bring it among us, we charge him for it as
though we were giving him a privilege.
- We punish with a tax the man who covers barren
fields with ripening grain,
- we fine him who puts up machinery, and him who
drains a swamp.
How heavily these taxes burden production only those
realize who have attempted to follow our system of
taxation through its ramifications, for, as I have before
said, the heaviest part of taxation is that which falls
in increased prices.
To abolish these taxes would be to lift the whole
enormous weight of taxation from productive industry. The
needle of the seamstress and the great manufactory; the
cart horse and the locomotive; the fishing boat and the
steamship; the farmer's plow and the merchant's stock,
would be alike untaxed. All would be free to make or to
save, to buy or to sell, unfined by taxes, unannoyed by
the taxgatherer. Instead of saying to the producer, as it
does now, "The more you add to the general wealth the
more shall you be taxed!" the state would say to the
producer, "Be as industrious, as thrifty, as enterprising
as you choose, you shall have your full reward! You shall
not be fined for making two blades of grass grow where
one grew before; you shall not be taxed for adding to the
aggregate wealth."
And will not the community gain by thus refusing to
kill the goose that lays the golden eggs; by thus
refraining from muzzling the ox that treadeth out the
corn; by thus leaving to industry, and thrift, and skill,
their natural reward, full and unimpaired? For there is
to the community also a natural reward. The law of
society is, each for all, as well as all for each. No one
can keep to himself the good he may do, any more than he
can keep the bad. Every productive enterprise, besides
its return to those who undertake it, yields collateral
advantages to others. If a man plant a fruit tree, his
gain is that he gathers the fruit in its time and season.
But in addition to his gain, there is a gain to the whole
community. Others than the owner are benefited by the
increased supply of fruit; the birds which it shelters
fly far and wide; the rain which it helps to attract
falls not alone on his field; and, even to the eye which
rests upon it from a distance, it brings a sense of
beauty. And so with everything else. The building of a
house, a factory, a ship, or a railroad, benefits others
besides those who get the direct profits.
Well may the community leave to the individual
producer all that prompts him to exertion; well may it
let the laborer have the full reward of his labor, and
the capitalist the full return of his capital. For the
more that labor and capital produce, the greater grows
the common wealth in which all may share. And in the
value or rent of land is this general gain expressed in a
definite and concrete form. Here is a fund which the
state may take while leaving to labor and capital their
full reward. With increased activity of production this
would commensurately increase.
And to shift the burden of taxation from production
and exchange to the value or rent of land would not
merely be to give new stimulus to the production of
wealth; it would be to open new opportunities. For under
this system no one would care to hold land unless to use
it, and land now withheld from use would everywhere be
thrown open to improvement. ... read the whole
chapter
H.G. Brown: Significant
Paragraphs from Henry George's Progress &
Poverty: 11 Effect of Remedy Upon the Sharing
of Wealth (in the unabridged P&P:
Part IX Effects of the Remedy — Chapter 2: Of the
Effect Upon Distribution and Thence Upon Production
But great as they thus appear, the advantages of a
transference of all public burdens to a tax upon the
value of land cannot be fully appreciated until we
consider the effect upon the distribution of wealth.
Tracing out the cause of the unequal distribution of
wealth which appears in all civilized countries, with a
constant tendency to greater and greater inequality as
material progress goes on, we have found it in the fact
that, as civilization advances, the ownership of land,
now in private hands, gives a greater and greater power
of appropriating the wealth produced by labor and
capital.
Thus, to relieve labor and capital from all taxation,
direct and indirect, and to throw the burden upon rent,
would be, as far as it went, to counteract this tendency
to inequality, and, if it went so far as to take in
taxation the whole of rent, the cause of inequality would
be totally destroyed. Rent, instead of causing
inequality, as now, would then promote equality. Labor
and capital would then receive the whole produce, minus
that portion taken by the state in the taxation of land
values, which, being applied to public purposes, would be
equally distributed in public benefits.
That is to say, the wealth produced in every community
would be divided into two portions.
- One part would be distributed in wages and interest
between individual producers, according to the part
each had taken in the work of production;
- the other part would go to the community as a
whole, to be distributed in public benefits to all its
members.
In this all would share equally — the weak with
the strong, young children and decrepit old men, the
maimed, the halt, and the blind, as well as the vigorous.
And justly so — for while one part represents the
result of individual effort in production, the other
represents the increased power with which the community
as a whole aids the individual.
Thus, as material progress tends to increase rent,
were rent taken by the community for common purposes the
very cause which now tends to produce inequality as
material progress goes on would then tend to produce
greater and greater equality. ...
read the whole chapter
Henry George: The Condition of Labor
— An Open Letter to Pope Leo XIII in response to
Rerum Novarum (1891)
Nor do we hesitate to say that this way of
securing the equal right to the bounty of the Creator and
the exclusive right to the products of labor is the way
intended by God for raising public revenues. For
we are not atheists, who deny God; nor semi-atheists, who
deny that he has any concern in politics and
legislation.
It is true as you say — a salutary truth too
often forgotten — that “man is older than the
state, and he holds the right of providing for the life
of his body prior to the formation of any state.”
Yet, as you too perceive, it is also true that the state
is in the divinely appointed order. For He who
foresaw all things and provided for all things, foresaw
and provided that with the increase of population and the
development of industry the organization of human society
into states or governments would become both expedient
and necessary.
No sooner does the state arise than, as we all
know, it needs revenues. This need for revenues is small
at first, while population is sparse, industry rude and
the functions of the state few and simple. But with
growth of population and advance of civilization the
functions of the state increase and larger and larger
revenues are needed.
Now, He that made the world and placed man in
it, He that pre-ordained civilization as the means
whereby man might rise to higher powers and become more
and more conscious of the works of his Creator, must have
foreseen this increasing need for state revenues and have
made provision for it. That is to say: The increasing
need for public revenues with social advance, being a
natural, God-ordained need, there must be a right way of
raising them — some way that we can truly say is
the way intended by God. It is clear that this right way
of raising public revenues must accord with the moral
law.
Hence:
It must not take from individuals what rightfully
belongs to individuals.
It must not give some an advantage over others, as by
increasing the prices of what some have to sell and
others must buy.
It must not lead men into temptation, by requiring
trivial oaths, by making it profitable to lie, to swear
falsely, to bribe or to take bribes.
It must not confuse the distinctions of right and
wrong, and weaken the sanctions of religion and the state
by creating crimes that are not sins, and punishing men
for doing what in itself they have an undoubted right to
do.
It must not repress industry. It must not check
commerce. It must not punish thrift. It must offer no
impediment to the largest production and the fairest
division of wealth.
Let me ask your Holiness to consider the taxes on the
processes and products of industry by which through the
civilized world public revenues are collected — the
octroi duties that surround Italian cities with barriers;
the monstrous customs duties that hamper intercourse
between so-called Christian states; the taxes on
occupations, on earnings, on investments, on the building
of houses, on the cultivation of fields, on industry and
thrift in all forms. Can these be the ways God has
intended that governments should raise the means they
need? Have any of them the characteristics indispensable
in any plan we can deem a right one?
All these taxes violate the moral law. They take by
force what belongs to the individual alone; they give to
the unscrupulous an advantage over the scrupulous; they
have the effect, nay are largely intended, to increase
the price of what some have to sell and others must buy;
they corrupt government; they make oaths a mockery; they
shackle commerce; they fine industry and thrift; they
lessen the wealth that men might enjoy, and enrich some
by impoverishing others.
Yet what most strikingly shows how opposed to
Christianity is this system of raising public revenues is
its influence on thought.
Christianity teaches us that all men are brethren;
that their true interests are harmonious, not
antagonistic. It gives us, as the golden rule of life,
that we should do to others as we would have others do to
us. But out of the system of taxing the products and
processes of labor, and out of its effects in increasing
the price of what some have to sell and others must buy,
has grown the theory of “protection,” which
denies this gospel, which holds Christ ignorant of
political economy and proclaims laws of national
well-being utterly at variance with his teaching. This
theory sanctifies national hatreds; it inculcates a
universal war of hostile tariffs; it teaches peoples that
their prosperity lies in imposing on the productions of
other peoples restrictions they do not wish imposed on
their own; and instead of the Christian doctrine of
man’s brotherhood it makes injury of foreigners a
civic virtue.
“By their fruits ye shall know them.” Can
anything more clearly show that to tax the products and
processes of industry is not the way God intended public
revenues to be raised?
But to consider what we propose — the raising of
public revenues by a single tax on the value of land
irrespective of improvements — is to see that in
all respects this does conform to the moral law.
Let me ask your Holiness to keep in mind that the
value we propose to tax, the value of land irrespective
of improvements, does not come from any exertion of labor
or investment of capital on or in it — the values
produced in this way being values of improvement which we
would exempt. The value of land irrespective of
improvement is the value that attaches to land by reason
of increasing population and social progress. This is a
value that always goes to the owner as owner, and never
does and never can go to the user; for if the user be a
different person from the owner he must always pay the
owner for it in rent or in purchase-money; while if the
user be also the owner, it is as owner, not as user, that
he receives it, and by selling or renting the land he
can, as owner, continue to receive it after he ceases to
be a user.
Thus, taxes on land irrespective of improvement cannot
lessen the rewards of industry, nor add to prices,* nor
in any way take from the individual what belongs to the
individual. They can take only the value that attaches to
land by the growth of the community, and which therefore
belongs to the community as a whole.
* As to this point it may be well to add
that all economists are agreed that taxes on land
values irrespective of improvement or use — or
what in the terminology of political economy is styled
rent, a term distinguished from the ordinary use of the
word rent by being applied solely to payments for the
use of land itself — must be paid by the owner
and cannot be shifted by him on the user. To explain in
another way the reason given in the text: Price is not
determined by the will of the seller or the will of the
buyer, but by the equation of demand and supply, and
therefore as to things constantly demanded and
constantly produced rests at a point determined by the
cost of production — whatever tends to increase
the cost of bringing fresh quantities of such articles
to the consumer increasing price by checking supply,
and whatever tends to reduce such cost decreasing price
by increasing supply. Thus taxes on wheat or tobacco or
cloth add to the price that the consumer must pay, and
thus the cheapening in the cost of producing steel
which improved processes have made in recent years has
greatly reduced the price of steel. But land has no
cost of production, since it is created by God, not
produced by man. Its price therefore is fixed
—
1 (monopoly rent), where land is held
in close monopoly, by what the owners can extract
from the users under penalty of deprivation and
consequently of starvation, and amounts to all that
common labor can earn on it beyond what is necessary
to life;
2 (economic rent proper), where there is no special
monopoly, by what the particular land will yield to
common labor over and above what may be had by like
expenditure and exertion on land having no special
advantage and for which no rent is paid; and,
3 (speculative rent, which is a species of monopoly
rent, telling particularly in selling price), by the
expectation of future increase of value from social
growth and improvement, which expectation causing
landowners to withhold land at present prices has the
same effect as combination.
Taxes on land values or economic rent
can therefore never be shifted by the landowner to the
land-user, since they in no wise increase the demand
for land or enable landowners to check supply by
withholding land from use. Where rent depends on mere
monopolization, a case I mention because rent may in
this way be demanded for the use of land even before
economic or natural rent arises, the taking by taxation
of what the landowners were able to extort from labor
could not enable them to extort any more, since
laborers, if not left enough to live on, will die. So,
in the case of economic rent proper, to take from the
landowners the premiums they receive, would in no way
increase the superiority of their land and the demand
for it. While, so far as price is affected by
speculative rent, to compel the landowners to pay taxes
on the value of land whether they were getting any
income from it or not, would make it more difficult for
them to withhold land from use; and to tax the full
value would not merely destroy the power but the desire
to do so.
To take land values for the state, abolishing all
taxes on the products of labor, would therefore leave to
the laborer the full produce of labor; to the individual
all that rightfully belongs to the individual. It would
impose no burden on industry, no check on commerce, no
punishment on thrift; it would secure the largest
production and the fairest distribution of wealth, by
leaving men free to produce and to exchange as they
please, without any artificial enhancement of prices; and
by taking for public purposes a value that cannot be
carried off, that cannot be hidden, that of all values is
most easily ascertained and most certainly and cheaply
collected, it would enormously lessen the number of
officials, dispense with oaths, do away with temptations
to bribery and evasion, and abolish man-made crimes in
themselves innocent.
But, further: That God has intended the state to
obtain the revenues it needs by the taxation of land
values is shown by the same order and degree of evidence
that shows that God has intended the milk of the mother
for the nourishment of the babe.
See how close is the analogy. In that primitive
condition ere the need for the state arises there are no
land values. The products of labor have value, but in the
sparsity of population no value as yet attaches to land
itself. But as increasing density of population and
increasing elaboration of industry necessitate the
organization of the state, with its need for revenues,
value begins to attach to land. As population still
increases and industry grows more elaborate, so the needs
for public revenues increase. And at the same time and
from the same causes land values increase. The connection
is invariable. The value of things produced by labor
tends to decline with social development, since the
larger scale of production and the improvement of
processes tend steadily to reduce their cost. But the
value of land on which population centers goes up and up.
Take Rome or Paris or London or New York or Melbourne.
Consider the enormous value of land in such cities as
compared with the value of land in sparsely settled parts
of the same countries. To what is this due? Is it not due
to the density and activity of the populations of those
cities — to the very causes that require great
public expenditure for streets, drains, public buildings,
and all the many things needed for the health,
convenience and safety of such great cities? See how with
the growth of such cities the one thing that steadily
increases in value is land; how the opening of roads, the
building of railways, the making of any public
improvement, adds to the value of land. Is it not clear
that here is a natural law — that is to say a
tendency willed by the Creator? Can it mean anything else
than that He who ordained the state with its needs has in
the values which attach to land provided the means to
meet those needs?
That it does mean this and nothing else is confirmed
if we look deeper still, and inquire not merely as to the
intent, but as to the purpose of the intent. If we do so
we may see in this natural law by which land values
increase with the growth of society not only such a
perfectly adapted provision for the needs of society as
gratifies our intellectual perceptions by showing us the
wisdom of the Creator, but a purpose with regard to the
individual that gratifies our moral perceptions by
opening to us a glimpse of his beneficence.
Consider: Here is a natural law by which as
society advances the one thing that increases in value is
land — a natural law by virtue of which all growth
of population, all advance of the arts, all general
improvements of whatever kind, add to a fund that both
the commands of justice and the dictates of expediency
prompt us to take for the common uses of society. Now,
since increase in the fund available for the common uses
of society is increase in the gain that goes equally to
each member of society, is it not clear that the law by
which land values increase with social advance while the
value of the products of labor does not increase, tends
with the advance of civilization to make the share that
goes equally to each member of society more and more
important as compared with what goes to him from his
individual earnings, and thus to make the advance of
civilization lessen relatively the differences that in a
ruder social state must exist between the strong and the
weak, the fortunate and the unfortunate? Does it not show
the purpose of the Creator to be that the advance of man
in civilization should be an advance not merely to larger
powers but to a greater and greater equality, instead of
what we, by our ignoring of his intent, are making it, an
advance toward a more and more monstrous inequality?
...
That the value attaching to land with social growth is
intended for social needs is shown by the final proof.
God is indeed a jealous God in the sense that nothing but
injury and disaster can attend the effort of men to do
things other than in the way he has intended; in the
sense that where the blessings he proffers to men are
refused or misused they turn to evils that scourge us.
And just as for the mother to withhold the provision that
fills her breast with the birth of the child is to
endanger physical health, so for society to refuse to
take for social uses the provision intended for them is
to breed social disease.
For refusal to take for public purposes the increasing
values that attach to land with social growth is to
necessitate the getting of public revenues by taxes that
lessen production, distort distribution and corrupt
society. It is to leave some to take what justly belongs
to all; it is to forego the only means by which it is
possible in an advanced civilization to combine the
security of possession that is necessary to improvement
with the equality of natural opportunity that is the most
important of all natural rights. It is thus at the basis
of all social life to set up an unjust inequality between
man and man, compelling some to pay others for the
privilege of living, for the chance of working, for the
advantages of civilization, for the gifts of their God.
But it is even more than this. The very robbery that the
masses of men thus suffer gives rise in advancing
communities to a new robbery. For the value that with the
increase of population and social advance attaches to
land being suffered to go to individuals who have secured
ownership of the land, it prompts to a forestalling of
and speculation in land wherever there is any prospect of
advancing population or of coming improvement, thus
producing an artificial scarcity of the natural elements
of life and labor, and a strangulation of production that
shows itself in recurring spasms of industrial depression
as disastrous to the world as destructive wars. It is
this that is driving men from the old countries to the
new countries, only to bring there the same curses. It is
this that causes our material advance not merely to fail
to improve the condition of the mere worker, but to make
the condition of large classes positively worse. It is
this that in our richest Christian countries is giving us
a large population whose lives are harder, more hopeless,
more degraded than those of the veriest savages. It is
this that leads so many men to think that God is a
bungler and is constantly bringing more people into his
world than he has made provision for; or that there is no
God, and that belief in him is a superstition which the
facts of life and the advance of science are
dispelling.
The darkness in light, the weakness in strength, the
poverty amid wealth, the seething discontent foreboding
civil strife, that characterize our civilization of
today, are the natural, the inevitable results of our
rejection of God’s beneficence, of our ignoring of
his intent. Were we on the other hand to follow his
clear, simple rule of right, leaving scrupulously to the
individual all that individual labor produces, and taking
for the community the value that attaches to land by the
growth of the community itself, not merely could evil
modes of raising public revenues be dispensed with, but
all men would be placed on an equal level of opportunity
with regard to the bounty of their Creator, on an equal
level of opportunity to exert their labor and to enjoy
its fruits. And then, without drastic or restrictive
measures the forestalling of land would cease. For then
the possession of land would mean only security for the
permanence of its use, and there would be no object for
any one to get land or to keep land except for use; nor
would his possession of better land than others had
confer any unjust advantage on him, or unjust deprivation
on them, since the equivalent of the advantage would be
taken by the state for the benefit of all.
The Right Reverend
Dr. Thomas Nulty, Bishop of Meath, who sees all this
as clearly as we do, in pointing out to the clergy and
laity of his diocese* the design of Divine Providence
that the rent of land should be taken for the community,
says:
I think, therefore, that I may fairly infer, on the
strength of authority as well as of reason, that the
people are and always must be the real owners of the
land of their country. This great social fact appears
to me to be of incalculable importance, and it is
fortunate, indeed, that on the strictest principles of
justice it is not clouded even by a shadow of
uncertainty or doubt. There is, moreover, a charm and a
peculiar beauty in the clearness with which it reveals
the wisdom and the benevolence of the designs of
Providence in the admirable provision he has made for
the wants and the necessities of that state of social
existence of which he is author, and in which the very
instincts of nature tell us we are to spend our lives.
A vast public property, a great national fund, has been
placed under the dominion and at the disposal of the
nation to supply itself abundantly with resources
necessary to liquidate the expenses of its government,
the administration of its laws and the education of its
youth, and to enable it to provide for the suitable
sustentation and support of its criminal and pauper
population. One of the most interesting peculiarities
of this property is that its value is never stationary;
it is constantly progressive and increasing in a direct
ratio to the growth of the population, and the very
causes thatincrease and multiply the demands made on it
increase proportionately its ability to meet
them.
* Letter
addressed to the Clergy and Laity of the Diocese of
Meath, Ireland, April 2, 1881.
There is, indeed, as Bishop Nulty says, a peculiar
beauty in the clearness with which the wisdom and
benevolence of Providence are revealed in this great
social fact, the provision made for the common needs of
society in what economists call the law of rent. Of all
the evidence that natural religion gives, it is this that
most clearly shows the existence of a beneficent God, and
most conclusively silences the doubts that in our days
lead so many to materialism.
For in this beautiful provision made by natural law
for the social needs of civilization we see that God has
intended civilization; that all our discoveries and
inventions do not and cannot outrun his forethought, and
that steam, electricity and labor-saving appliances only
make the great moral laws clearer and more important. In
the growth of this great fund, increasing with social
advance — a fund that accrues from the growth of
the community and belongs therefore to the community
— we see not only that there is no need for the
taxes that lessen wealth, that engender corruption, that
promote inequality and teach men to deny the gospel; but
that to take this fund for the purpose for which it was
evidently intended would in the highest civilization
secure to all the equal enjoyment of God’s bounty,
the abundant opportunity to satisfy their wants, and
would provide amply for every legitimate need of the
state. We see that God in his dealings with men has not
been a bungler or a niggard; that he has not brought too
many men into the world; that he has not neglected
abundantly to supply them; that he has not intended that
bitter competition of the masses for a mere animal
existence and that monstrous aggregation of wealth which
characterize our civilization; but that these evils which
lead so many to say there is no God, or yet more
impiously to say that they are of God’s ordering,
are due to our denial of his moral law. We see that the
law of justice, the law of the Golden Rule, is not a mere
counsel of perfection, but indeed the law of social life.
We see that if we were only to observe it there would be
work for all, leisure for all, abundance for all; and
that civilization would tend to give to the poorest not
only necessities, but all comforts and reasonable
luxuries as well. We see that Christ was not a mere
dreamer when he told men that if they would seek the
kingdom of God and its right-doing they might no more
worry about material things than do the lilies of the
field about their raiment; but that he was only declaring
what political economy in the light of modern discovery
shows to be a sober truth.
Your Holiness, even to see this is deep and lasting
joy. For it is to see for one’s self that there is
a God who lives and reigns, and that be is a God of
justice and love — Our Father who art in Heaven. It
is to open a rift of sunlight through the clouds of our
darker questionings, and to make the faith that trusts
where it cannot see a living thing. ...
Your use, in so many passages of your Encyclical, of the
inclusive term “property” or
“private” property, of which in morals
nothing can be either affirmed or denied, makes your
meaning, if we take isolated sentences, in many places
ambiguous. But reading it as a whole, there can be no
doubt of your intention that private property in land
shall be understood when you speak merely of private
property. With this interpretation, I find that the
reasons you urge for private property in land are eight.
Let us consider them in order of presentation. You
urge:
1. That what is bought with rightful property is
rightful property. (RN, paragraph 5) ...
2. That private property in land proceeds from
man’s gift of reason. (RN, paragraphs 6-7.)
...
3. That private property in land deprives no one of the
use of land. (RN, paragraph 8.) ...
4. That Industry expended on land gives ownership in the
land itself. (RN, paragraphs 9-10.) ...
5. That private property in land has the support of the
common opinion of mankind, and has conduced to peace and
tranquillity, and that it is sanctioned by Divine Law.
(RN, paragraph 11.) ...
6. That fathers should provide for their children and
that private property in land is necessary to enable them
to do so. (RN, paragraphs 14-17.) ...
7. That the private ownership of land stimulates
industry, increases wealth, and attaches men to the soil
and to their country. (RN, paragraph 51.) ...
8. That the right to possess private property in land is
from nature, not from man; that the state has no right to
abolish it, and that to take the value of landownership
in taxation would be unjust and cruel to the private
owner. (RN, paragraph 51.) ...
6. That fathers should provide for their
children and that private property in land is necessary
to enable them to do so. (14-17.)
With all that your Holiness has to say of the
sacredness of the family relation we are in full accord.
But how the obligation of the father to the child can
justify private property in land we cannot see. You
reason that private property in land is necessary to the
discharge of the duty of the father, and is therefore
requisite and just, because —
It is a most sacred law of nature that a father must
provide food and all necessaries for those whom he has
begotten; and, similarly, nature dictates that a
man’s children, who carry on, as it were, and
continue his own personality, should be provided by him
with all that is needful to enable them honorably to keep
themselves from want and misery in the uncertainties of
this mortal life. Now, in no other way can a father
effect this except by the ownership of profitable
property, which he can transmit to his children by
inheritance. (14.)
Thanks to Him who has bound the generations of men
together by a provision that brings the tenderest love to
greet our entrance into the world and soothes our exit
with filial piety, it is both the duty and the joy of the
father to care for the child till its powers mature, and
afterwards in the natural order it becomes the duty and
privilege of the child to be the stay of the parent. This
is the natural reason for that relation of marriage, the
groundwork of the sweetest, tenderest and purest of human
joys, which the Catholic Church has guarded with such
unremitting vigilance.
We do, for a few years, need the providence of our
fathers after the flesh. But how small, how transient,
how narrow is this need, as compared with our constant
need for the providence of Him in whom we live, move and
have our being — Our Father who art in Heaven! It
is to him, “the giver of every good and perfect
gift,” and not to our fathers after the flesh, that
Christ taught us to pray, “Give us this day our
daily bread.” And how true it is that it is through
him that the generations of men exist! Let the mean
temperature of the earth rise or fall a few degrees, an
amount as nothing compared with differences produced in
our laboratories, and mankind would disappear as ice
disappears under a tropical sun, would fall as the leaves
fall at the touch of frost. Or, let for two or three
seasons the earth refuse her increase, and how many of
our millions would remain alive?
The duty of fathers to transmit to their children
profitable property that will enable them to keep
themselves from want and misery in the uncertainties of
this mortal life! What is not possible cannot be a duty.
And how is it possible for fathers to do that? Your
Holiness has not considered how mankind really lives from
hand to mouth, getting each day its daily bread; how
little one generation does or can leave another. It is
doubtful if the wealth of the civilized world all told
amounts to anything like as much as one year’s
labor, while it is certain that if labor were to stop and
men had to rely on existing accumulation, it would be
only a few days ere in the richest countries pestilence
and famine would stalk.
The profitable property your Holiness refers to, is
private property in land. Now profitable land, as all
economists will agree, is land superior to the land that
the ordinary man can get. It is land that will yield an
income to the owner as owner, and therefore that will
permit the owner to appropriate the products of labor
without doing labor, its profitableness to the individual
involving the robbery of other individuals. It is
therefore possible only for some fathers to leave their
children profitable land. What therefore your Holiness
practically declares is, that it is the duty of all
fathers to struggle to leave their children what only the
few peculiarly strong, lucky or unscrupulous can leave;
and that, a something that involves the robbery of others
— their deprivation of the material gifts of
God.
This anti-Christian doctrine has been long in practice
throughout the Christian world. What are its results?
Are they not the very evils set forth in your
Encyclical? Are they not, so far from enabling men to
keep themselves from want and misery in the uncertainties
of this mortal life, to condemn the great masses of men
to want and misery that the natural conditions of our
mortal life do not entail; to want and misery deeper and
more wide-spread than exist among heathen savages? Under
the régime of private property in land and in the
richest countries not five per cent of fathers are able
at their death to leave anything substantial to their
children, and probably a large majority do not leave
enough to bury them! Some few children are left by their
fathers richer than it is good for them to be, but the
vast majority not only are left nothing by their fathers,
but by the system that makes land private property are
deprived of the bounty of their Heavenly Father; are
compelled to sue others for permission to live and to
work, and to toil all their lives for a pittance that
often does not enable them to escape starvation and
pauperism.
What your Holiness is actually, though of course
inadvertently, urging, is that earthly fathers should
assume the functions of the Heavenly Father. It is not
the business of one generation to provide the succeeding
generation “with all that is needful to enable them
honorably to keep themselves from want and misery.”
That is God’s business. We no more create our
children than we create our fathers. It is God who is the
Creator of each succeeding generation as fully as of the
one that preceded it. And, to recall your own words (7),
“Nature [God], therefore, owes to man a storehouse
that shall never fail, the daily supply of his daily
wants. And this he finds only in the inexhaustible
fertility of the earth.” What you are now assuming
is, that it is the duty of men to provide for the wants
of their children by appropriating this storehouse and
depriving other men’s children of the unfailing
supply that God has provided for all.
The duty of the father to the child — the duty
possible to all fathers! Is it not so to conduct himself,
so to nurture and teach it, that it shall come to manhood
with a sound body, well-developed mind, habits of virtue,
piety and industry, and in a state of society that shall
give it and all others free access to the bounty of God,
the providence of the All-Father?
In doing this the father would be doing more to secure
his children from want and misery than is possible now to
the richest of fathers — as much more as the
providence of God surpasses that of man. For the justice
of God laughs at the efforts of men to circumvent it, and
the subtle law that binds humanity together poisons the
rich in the sufferings of the poor. Even the few who are
able in the general struggle to leave their children
wealth that they fondly think will keep them from want
and misery in the uncertainties of this mortal life
— do they succeed? Does experience show that it is
a benefit to a child to place him above his fellows and
enable him to think God’s law of labor is not for
him? Is not such wealth oftener a curse than a blessing,
and does not its expectation often destroy filial love
and bring dissensions and heartburnings into families?
And how far and how long are even the richest and
strongest able to exempt their children from the common
lot? Nothing is more certain than that the blood of the
masters of the world flows today in lazzaroni and that
the descendants of kings and princes tenant slums and
workhouses.
But in the state of society we strive for, where the
monopoly and waste of God’s bounty would be done
away with and the fruits of labor would go to the
laborer, it would be within the ability of all to make
more than a comfortable living with reasonable labor. And
for those who might be crippled or incapacitated, or
deprived of their natural protectors and breadwinners,
the most ample provision could be made out of that great
and increasing fund with which God in his law of rent has
provided society — not as a matter of niggardly and
degrading alms, but as a matter of right, as the
assurance which in a Christian state society owes to all
its members.
Thus it is that the duty of the father, the obligation
to the child, instead of giving any support to private
property in land, utterly condemns it, urging us by the
most powerful considerations to abolish it in the simple
and efficacious way of the single tax.
This duty of the father, this obligation to children,
is not confined to those who have actually children of
their own, but rests on all of us who have come to the
powers and responsibilities of manhood.
For did not Christ set a little child in the midst of
the disciples, saying to them that the angels of such
little ones always behold the face of his Father; saying
to them that it were better for a man to hang a millstone
about his neck and plunge into the uttermost depths of
the sea than to injure such a little one?
And what today is the result of private property in
land in the richest of so-called Christian countries? Is
it not that young people fear to marry; that married
people fear to have children; that children are driven
out of life from sheer want of proper nourishment and
care, or compelled to toil when they ought to be at
school or at play; that great numbers of those who attain
maturity enter it with under-nourished bodies,
overstrained nerves, undeveloped minds — under
conditions that foredoom them, not merely to suffering,
but to crime; that fit them in advance for the prison and
the brothel?
If your Holiness will consider these things we are
confident that instead of defending private property in
land you will condemn it with anathema! ...
Nor do we seek any “futile and ridiculous
equality.” We recognize, with you, that there must
always be differences and inequalities. In so far as
these are in conformity with the moral law, in so far as
they do not violate the command, “Thou shalt not
steal,” we are content. We do not seek to better
God’s work; we seek only to do his will. The
equality we would bring about is not the equality of
fortune, but the equality of natural opportunity; the
equality that reason and religion alike proclaim —
the equality in usufruct of all his children to the
bounty of Our Father who art in Heaven.
And in taking for the uses of society what we
clearly see is the great fund intended for society in the
divine order, we would not levy the slightest tax on the
possessors of wealth, no matter how rich they might be.
Not only do we deem such taxes a violation of the right
of property, but we see that by virtue of beautiful
adaptations in the economic laws of the Creator, it is
impossible for any one honestly to acquire wealth,
without at the same time adding to the wealth of the
world. ... read the whole
letter
Henry George: Thy
Kingdom Come (1889 speech)
... “Thy kingdom come!” We have been
praying for it and praying for it, yet it has not come.
So long has it tarried that many think it will never
come. Here is the vital point in which what we are
accustomed to call the Christianity of the present day
differs so much from that Christianity which overran the
ancient world — that Christianity which, beneath a
rotten old civilisation, planted the seeds of a newer and
a higher.
We have become accustomed to think that
God’s kingdom, is not intended for this world;
that, virtually, this is the devil’s world, and
that God’s kingdom is in some other sphere, to
which He is to take good people when they die — as
good Americans are said when they die to go to Paris. If
that be so, what is the use of praying for the coming of
the kingdom? Is God the loving Father of whom Christ told
— is He a God of that kind; a God who looks on this
world, sees its sufferings and its miseries, sees high
faculties aborted, lives stunted, innocence turned to
vice and crime, and heartstrings strained and broken,
yet, having it in His power, will not bring that kingdom
of peace, and love, and plenty and happiness? Is God
indeed a self-willed despot, whom we must coax to do the
good He might? ...
“Thy kingdom come!” When
Christ taught that prayer He did not mean that humans
should idly phrase these words, but that for the coming of
that kingdom humanity must work as well as pray!
...
When we consider the achievements of
humanity and then look upon the misery that exists today in
the very centres of wealth; upon the ignorance, the
weakness, the injustice, that characterise our highest
civilisation, we may know of a surety that it is not the
fault of God; it is the fault of humanity. May we not know
that in that very power that God has given to His children
here, in that power of rising higher, there is involved
— and necessarily involved — the power of
falling lower.
“Our Father!” “Our
Father!” Whose? Not my
Father — that is not the prayer. “Our Father” — not the
father of any sect, or any class, but the Father of all
humanity. The All- Father, the equal Father, the loving
Father. He it is we ask to bring the kingdom. Aye, we ask
it with our lips! We call Him “Our Father”, the
All, the Universal Father, when we kneel down to pray to
Him.
But that He is the All-Father —
that He is all people’s Father — we deny by our
institutions. The All-Father who made the world, the
All-Father who created us in His image, and put us upon the
earth to draw subsistence from its bosom; to find in the
earth all the materials that satisfy our wants, waiting
only to be worked up by our labour! If He is the
All-Father, then are not all human beings, all children of
the Creator, equally entitled to the use of His bounty?
And, yet, our laws say that this God’s earth is not
here for the use of all His children, but only for the use
of a privileged few!
There was a little dialogue published in the
United States, in the west, some time ago. Possibly you
may have seen it. It is between a boy and his father when
visiting a brickyard. The boy looks at the men making
bricks, and he asks who those dirty men are, why they are
making up the clay, and what they are doing it for. He
learns, and then he asks about the owner of the
brickyard. “He does not make any bricks; he gets
his income from letting the other men make
bricks.”
Then the boy wants to know how the
man who owns the brickyard gets his title to the brickyard
— whether he made it. “No, he did not make
it,” the father replies: “God made it.”
The boy asks, “Did God make it for him?”
Whereat his father tells him that he must not ask questions
such as that, but that anyhow it is all right, and it is
all in accordance with God’s law. The boy, who of
course was a Sunday school boy, and had been to church,
goes off mumbling to himself “that God so loved the
world that He gave His only begotten Son to die for all
men”; but that He so loved the owner of this
brickyard that He gave him the brickyard too.
This has a blasphemous sound. But I
do not refer to it lightly. I do not like to speak lightly
of sacred subjects. Yet it is well sometimes that we should
be fairly shocked into thinking.
Think of what Christianity teaches
us; think of the life and death of Him who came to die for
us! Think of His teachings, that we are all the equal
children of an Almighty Father, who is no respecter of
persons, and then think of this legalised injustice —
this denial of the most important, most fundamental rights
of the children of God, which so many of the very men who
teach Christianity uphold; nay, which they blasphemously
assert is the design and the intent of the Creator Himself.
...
One cannot look, it seems to me,
through nature — whether one looks at the stars
through a telescope, or have the microscope reveal to one
those worlds that we find in drops of water. Whether one
considers the human frame, the adjustments of the animal
kingdom, or any department of physical nature, one must see
that there has been a contriver and adjuster, that there
has been an intent. So strong is that feeling, so natural
is it to our minds, that even people who deny the Creative
Intelligence are forced, in spite of themselves, to talk of
intent; the claws on one animal were intended, we say, to
climb with, the fins of another to propel it through the
water.
Yet, while in looking through the
laws of physical nature, we find
intelligence we do not so clearly find beneficence. But in
the great social fact that as
population increases, and improvements are made, and men
progress in civilisation, the one thing that rises
everywhere in value is land, and in this we may see a proof
of the beneficence of the Creator.
Why, consider what it means!
It means that the social laws are adapted
to progressive humanity! In a rude state of society where
there is no need for common expenditure, there is no value
attaching to land. The only value which attaches there is
to things produced by labour. But as civilisation goes on,
as a division of labour takes place, as people come into
centres, so do the common wants increase, and so does the
necessity for public revenue arise. And so in that value
which attaches to land, not by reason of anything the
individual does, but by reason of the growth of the
community, is a provision intended — we may safely
say intended — to meet that social
want.
Just as society grows, so do the
common needs grow, and so grows this value attaching to
land — the provided fund from which they can be
supplied. Here is a value that may be taken, without
impairing the right of property, without taking anything
from the producer, without lessening the natural rewards
of industry and thrift. Nay, here is a value that must be
taken if we would prevent the most monstrous of all
monopolies. What does all this mean? It means that in the
creative plan, the natural advance in civilisation is an
advance to a greater and greater equality instead of to a
more and more monstrous inequality. ... Read the whole
speech
Henry George: Thou Shalt
Not Steal (1887 speech)
There is no need for poverty in this
world, and in our civilization. There is a provision made
by the laws of the Creator which would secure to the
helpless all that they require, which would give enough and
more than enough for all social purposes. These little
children that are dying in our crowded districts for want
of room and fresh air, they are the disinherited heirs of a
great estate.
Did you ever consider the full
meaning of the significant fact that as progress goes on,
as population increases and civilization develops, the one
thing that ever increases in value is land? Speculators
all over the country appreciate that fact. Wherever there
is a chance for population coming; wherever railroads meet
or a great city seems destined to grow; wherever some new
evidence of the bounty of the Creator is discovered, in a
rich coal or iron mine, or an oil well, or a gas deposit,
there the speculator jumps in, land rises in value, and a
great boom takes place, and people find themselves
enormously rich without ever having done a single thing to
produce wealth.
Now, it is by virtue of a natural law that land
steadily increases in value; that population adds to it;
that invention adds to it; that the discovery of every
fresh evidence of the Creator’s goodness in the
stores that He has implanted in the earth for our use
adds to the value of land, not to the value of anything
else. This natural fact is by virtue of a natural law, a
law that is as much a law of the Creator as is the law of
gravitation.
What is the intent of this natural
law of increasing land values? Is there not in it a
provision for social needs? That land values grow greater
and greater as the community grows and common needs
increase: is there not built into this law a manifest
provision for social needs — a fund
belonging to society as a whole, with which we may take
care of those who fall by the wayside — with which we
may meet public expenses, and do all the things that an
advancing civilization makes more and more necessary for
society to do on behalf of its members?
...
Today the value of land in New York city is over a
hundred million annually. Who has created that value? Is
it because a few landowners are here that that land is
worth a hundred million a year? Is it not because the
whole population of New York is here? Is it not because
this great city is the center of exchanges for a large
portion of the continent? Does not every child that is
born, every one that comes to settle in New York, does it
not add to the value of this land? Ought it not,
therefore, get some portion of the benefit? And is it not
wronged when, instead of being used for that purpose,
certain favored individuals are allowed to appropriate
the fund of land values?
We might take this vast fund for common needs; we
might with it make a city here such as the world has
never seen before — a city spacious, clean,
wholesome, beautiful — a city that should be full
of parks; a city without tenement houses; and we could do
this, not merely without imposing any tax upon
production, without interfering with the just rights of
property, but while at the same time securing far better
than they are now the rights of property, and abolishing
the taxes that now weigh on production.
We have but to throw off our taxes upon things of
human production; to cease to fine a person who puts up a
house or makes anything that adds to the wealth of the
community; to cease collecting taxes from people who
bring goods from abroad or make goods at home; and
— in substitution for all these taxes — to
collect that enormous revenue due to the growth of the
community for the benefit of the community that produced
it.
Dr Nulty, Bishop of Meath, has said in a letter
addressed to the clergy and laity of his diocese that it
is this provision of the Creator, the provision by which
the value of land increases as the community grows, that
seems to him the most beautiful of all the social
adjustments; and it is to me that which most clearly
shows the beneficence as well as the intelligence of the
Creative Mind; for here is a provision by which the
advance of civilization would, under the law of equal
justice, be an advance towards equality, instead of
being, as it now is, an advance toward a more and more
monstrous inequality.
The same good Catholic Bishop in that same letter
says: "Now, therefore, the land of every country is the
common property of the people of that country, because
its real owner, the Creator, who made it, hath given it
as a voluntary gift unto them. ‘The earth has He
given to the children of men and women.’ And as
every human being is a creature and a child of God, and
as all His creatures are equal in His sight, any settlement of the land of this or any other
country that would exclude the humblest from an equal
share in the common heritage is not only an injury and a
wrong done to that person, but an impious violation of
the benevolent intention of the
Creator."
And then Bishop Nulty goes on to show that the way
to secure equal rights to land is not by cutting land up
into equal pieces, but by taking for public use the
values attaching to land. That is the method this Society
proposes. I wish we could get that through the heads of
the editors of this city. We do not propose to divide up
land. What we propose to do is to divide
up the rent that comes from land; and that is a very easy
thing. ...
Go into Pennsylvania, and there you
will see great stretches of land, containing enormous
deposits of the finest coal, held by corporations and
individuals who are working but little part of it. On these
great estates the common American citizens who mine the
coal are not allowed even to rent a piece of land, let
alone buy it. They can only live in company houses; and
they are permitted to stay in them only on condition (and
they have to sign a paper to that effect) that they can be
evicted at any time on five days’ notice. The
companies combine and make coal artificially dear here, and
make employment artificially scarce in
Pennsylvania.
Now, why should not those miners, who
work on it half the time, why shouldn’t they dig down
in the earth and get up coal for themselves? Who made that
coal? There is only one answer — God made that coal.
Whom did He make it for? Surely you would say that God made
it for the people that would be one day called into being
on this earth. But the laws of Pennsylvania, like the laws
of New York, say God made it for this corporation and that
individual; and thus a few people are permitted to deprive
miners of work and make coal artificially dear. ...
read the whole article
Henry George: The
Single Tax: What It Is and Why We Urge It (1890)
Think about what the value of land is. It has no
reference to the cost of production, as has the value of
houses, horses, ships, clothes, or other things produced
by labor, for land is not produced by man, it was created
by God. The value of land does not come from the exertion
of labor on land, for the value thus produced is a value
of improvement. That value attaches to any piece of land
means that that piece of land is more desirable than the
land which other citizens may obtain, and that they are
willing to pay a premium for permission to use it.
Justice therefore requires that this premium of value
shall be taken for the benefit of all in order to secure
to all their equal rights.
Consider the
difference between the value of a building and the value of
land. The value of a building,
like the value of goods, or of anything properly styled
wealth, is produced by individual exertion, and therefore
properly belongs to the individual; but the value of land
only arises with the growth and improvement of the
community, and therefore properly belongs to the community.
It is not because of what its owners have
done, but because of the presence of the whole great
population, that land in New York is worth millions an
acre. This value therefore is the proper fund for defraying
the common expenses of the whole population; and it must be
taken for public use, under penalty of generating land
speculation and monopoly which will bring about artificial
scarcity where the Creator has provided in abundance for
all whom His providence has called into
existence.
It is thus a violation of justice to
tax labor, or the things produced by labor, and it is also
a violation of justice not to tax land values.
... read the whole
article
Henry George: The Wages of
Labor
It is truly said – a salutary truth too
often forgotten – “Man is older than the
State, and holds the right of providing for the life of
his body prior to the formation of any State.” It
is also true that the State is in the divinely appointed
order. For He Who foresaw all things, and provided far
all things, foresaw and provided that, with the increase
of population and the development of industry, the
organisation of human society into States or Governments
would become both expedient and necessary.
No sooner does the State arise than it needs
revenue. This need for revenue is small at first, while
population is sparse, industry rude, and the functions of
the State few and simple. But with growth of population
and advance of civilisation the functions of the State
increase, and larger and larger revenues are
needed.
Now, the raising of Public Revenue must accord
with the moral law. Hence:
- It must not take from individuals what
rightfully belongs to individuals.
- It must not give some an advantage over
others, as by, increasing prices of what some have to
sell and others must buy.
- It must not lead men into temptation, by
requiring trivial oaths, by making it profitable to lie,
to swear falsely, to bribe or to take
bribes.
- It must not confuse the distinctions of right
and wrong, and weaken the sanctions of Religion and the
State, by creating crimes and punishing men for doing
what morally they have an undoubted right to
do.
- It must not repress industry nor check
commerce. It must not punish thrift. It must offer no
impediment to the largest production and the fairest
division of wealth.
Consider the taxes on the processes
and products of industry by which public revenue is
collected:
- The monstrous customs duties that hamper
intercourse between so-called Christian
States;
- the taxes on occupations, on earnings, on
investments;
- on the building of houses;
- on the cultivation of fields;
- on industry and thrift in all
forms.
Can these be the ways that God has intended that
Governments should raise the means they need? Have any of
them the characteristics indispensable in any plan we can
deem a right one? All these taxes violate the moral law.
They take by force what belongs to the individual; they
give to the unscrupulous an advantage over the
scrupulous; their effect is, nay they are largely
intended, to increase the price of what some have to sell
and others must buy; they corrupt governments ; they make
oaths a mockery; they shackle commerce; they fine
industry and thrift; they lessen the wealth that men
might enjoy, and enrich some by impoverishing others.
...
That God has intended the value of the land to
serve for public revenue is shown by the order and degree
in which land values increase with the growth of the
State.
In that primitive condition ere the
need for the State arises there are no land values. The
products of labor have value, but in the sparsity of
population no value as yet attaches to land itself. But as
increasing density of population and increasing elaboration
of industry necessitate the organisation of the State, with
its need for revenue, value begins to attach to land. As
population still increases and industry grows more
elaborate, so the need for public revenue increases; and at
the same time, and from the same causes, land values
increase. The connection is invariable.
The value of things
produced by labor tends to decline with social development,
since the larger scale of production and the improvement of
process tend steadily to reduce their cost.
But the value of land on
which population centres goes up and up. ...
Consider: Here is a natural law by
which as society advances the one thing that increases in
value is land – a natural law by virtue of which all
growth of population, all advance of the arts, all general
improvements of whatever kind, add to a fund that both the
commands of justice and the dictates of expediency prompt
us to take for the common uses of society.
Now, since increase in the fund available for the
common uses of society is increase in the gain that goes
equally to each member of society, is it not clear that
this law by which land values increase with social
advance while the values of the products of labor do not
increase – tends, with the advance of civilisation,
to make the share that goes equally to each member of
society more and more important as compared with what
goes to him from his individual earnings, and thus to
make the advance of civilisation lessen relatively the
differences that in a ruder social state must exist
between the strong and the weak, the fortunate and the
unfortunate? Does it not show the
purpose of the Creator to be that the advance of man in
civilisation should be an advance, not merely to larger
powers, but to a greater and greater equality, instead of
what we by our ignoring of His intent are making it
– an advance towards a more and more monstrous
inequality? ...
The Right Reverend Dr. Thomas Nulty, Bishop of
Meath, Ireland, who sees all this very clearly, has made
striking testimony to the design of Divine Providence
that the rent of land should be taken for the community.
In a pastoral letter
addressed to the clergy and laity of his diocese,
April 2, 1881, he says :
“This great social fact is of incalculable
importance; and, on the strictest principles of justice,
it is not clouded even by a shadow of uncertainty or
doubt. There is, moreover, a charm and a peculiar beauty
in the clearness with which it reveals the wisdom and the
benevolence of the designs of Providence in the admirable
provision He has made for the wants and the necessities
of that state of social existence in which the very
instincts of nature tell us we are to spend our lives. A
vast public property, a great national fund, has been
placed under the dominion and at the disposal of the
nation to supply itself abundantly with resources
necessary to liquidate the expenses of its government and
the administration of its laws.
"One of the most interesting peculiarities of this
property is that its value is constantly progressive and
increasing in a direct ratio to the growth of the
population, and the very causes that increase and
multiply the demands made on it increase proportionately
its ability to meet them.”
He says further:
“Any settlement of the land of a
country that would exclude the humblest man in that
country from his share of the common inheritance would be
not only an injustice and a wrong to that man, but,
moreover, would be an impious resistance to the
benevolent intentions of his
Creator.”
There is, indeed, as Bishop Nulty says, a peculiar
beauty in the clearness with which the wisdom and
benevolence of Providence are revealed in the provision
made for the common needs of society in what economists
call the law of rent. Of all the evidence that natural
religion gives, it is this that most clearly shows the
existence of a beneficent God!
In this beautiful provision for
social needs we see that God has intended civilisation;
that all our discoveries and inventions do not, and cannot,
outrun His forethought; and that steam, electricity, and
labor-saving appliances only make the great moral laws
clearer and more important.
In the growth of this great fund, increasing with
social advance – a fund that accrues from the
growth of the community, and belongs, therefore; to the
community – we see, not only that there is no need
for the taxes that lessen wealth; that engender
corruption, and promote inequality, but, that to take
this fund for the purpose for which it was intended would
secure to all the equal enjoyment of God’s bounty
– the abundant opportunity to satisfy their wants
and provide amply for every legitimate need of the
State.
We see that God in His dealings with men has not
been a bungler or a niggard; that He has not brought too
many men into the world, that He has not neglected
abundantly to supply them; that He has not intended that
bitter competition of the masses for a mere animal
existence and that monstrous aggregation of wealth which
characterise our civilisation; but, that these evils,
which lead so many to say there is no God, or yet more
impiously to say that they are of God’s ordering,
are due to our denial of His moral law.
... read the whole article
Clarence Darrow: The Land Belongs To The
People (1916)
This earth is a little raft moving in the endless sea
of space, and the mass of its human inhabitants are
hanging on as best they can. It is as if some raft filled
with shipwrecked sailors should be floating on the ocean,
and a few of the strongest and most powerful would take
all the raft they could get and leave the most of the
people, especially the ones who did the work, hanging to
the edges by their eyebrows. These men who have taken
possession of this raft, this little planet in this
endless space, are not even content with taking all there
is and leaving the rest barely enough to hold onto, but
they think so much of themselves and their brief day that
while they live they must make rules and laws and
regulations that parcel out the earth for thousands of
years after they are dead and, gone, so that their
descendants and others of their kind may do in the tenth
generation exactly what they are doing today —
keeping the earth and all the good things of the earth
and compelling the great mass of mankind to toil for
them.
Now, the question is, how are you going to get it
back? Everybody who thinks knows that private ownership
of the land is wrong. If ten thousand men can own
America, then one man can own it, and if one man may own
it he may take all that the rest produce or he may kill
them if he sees fit. It is inconsistent with the spirit
of manhood. No person who thinks can doubt but that he
was born upon this planet with the same birthright that
came to every man born like him. And it is for him to
defend that birthright. And the man who will not defend
it, whatever the cost, is fitted only to be a slave. The
earth belongs to the people — if they can get it
— because if you cannot get it, it makes no
difference whether you have a right to it or not, and if
you can get it, it makes no difference whether you have a
right to it or not, you just take it. The earth has been
taken from the many by the few. It made no difference
that they had no right to it; they took it.
Now, there are some methods of getting access to the
earth which are easier than others. The easiest, perhaps,
that has been contrived is by means of taxation of the
land values and land values alone; and I need only say a
little upon that question. One trouble with it which
makes it almost impossible to achieve, is that it is so
simple and so easy. You cannot get people to do anything
that is simple; they want it complex so they can be
fooled.
Now the theory of Henry George and of those who really
believe in the common ownership of land is that the
public should take not alone taxation from the land, but
the public should take to itself the whole value of the
land that has been created by the public — should
take it all. It should be a part of the public wealth,
should be used for public improvements, for pensions, and
belong to the people who create the wealth — which
is a strange doctrine in these strange times. It can be
done simply and easily; it can be done by taxation. All
the wealth created by the public could be taken back by
the public and then poverty would disappear, most of it
at least. The method is so simple, and so legal even
— sometimes a thing is legal if it is simple
— that it is the easiest substantial reform for men
to accomplish, and when it is done this great problem of
poverty, the problem of the ages, will be almost solved.
We may need go farther. ... read the whole
article
Bill Batt: The
Compatibility of Georgist Economics and Ecological
Economics
Lastly, one must appreciate that the market value
of “land” of every sort is entirely rent, as
there is no human factor of labor that accounts for its
origination. Services of nature have no prior cost to
bring them into production existence — the
electromagnetic spectrum, for example, exists regardless
of human presence on earth and so presumably does time.
Ocean fish, fossil fuels, and heavy metals are all found
in nature, not the result of human creation. They are, in 19th century classical economics, the
fruits not of man’s labor but of God’s. And
it is to God, or at least to God’s representative
on earth — the lords and kings — that rent
was owed, just as much as it was their role to provide
reciprocal services to the tenants of the land.
That bargain, so well refined in feudal economic
arrangements, was an equilibrium balance, disrupted, one
might say, by the annulment of rent collection and the
exploitation of land without recognition of its price.
The practice effectively ended with what in Britain is
known as the “enclosure movement” of the
early Tudor reign, driving the peasants off the land into
cities to provide cheap labor for the early English
industrialists.28
But the theory continued long afterwards. Georgists today
argue that land rent should be collected from
titleholders so that it is not left to render economic
distortions. This in turn affects the price of labor and
the price of money. Government’s role, whatever
else it does, is at the very least responsible for
defending the commons, to ascertain titles and to collect
rent. Although there are many differences about the
proper role, scope and domain of government among
Georgist adherents, the collection of rent and the
supervision of open markets is central to its tenets.
...
The heart of George’s economics was, in a
way, Biblical. As the son of a religious book publisher
born in Philadelphia, he had adequate opportunity to
witness the early growth of the American republic in a
unique way. On his own in San Francisco and responsible
for a wife and child at a young age, his first effort at
resolving the puzzles of injustice were a manuscript
printed in 1871. But only after additional exposure to
Ricardian rent theory was he able to refine his ideas
such that they could form the basis of his Progress and Poverty eight years later. His
Christian roots led him to a deep commitment to the basic
moral equality of all people; his challenge was to find a
way to ensure that this equality was manifest in economic
fairness.
As noted earlier, the starting point of Georgist
philosophy is that nature belongs to owners only in
usufruct and not in freehold. Because any monetary wealth
that accrued to that nature stemmed directly from the
physical presence of people and was therefore social in
character, the resulting added increment of value that
constituted rent belonged in turn to the community that
created it. Nature would have no economic price without
people. Hence rent was the
community’s entitlement and not that of
individuals, and the land rent that accrued to parcels as
a result of social investment should be returned to
— recaptured by — the community. It
was obvious to George that the wealthiest people in the
nation usually owed their fortune not to the sweat of
their brow or the inventiveness of their minds. Rather
their position was due to their success as land
speculators, to an increase in rent on land they had
captured title to, land rightfully belonging to all. The
earth and all its product, he argued, was the common
heritage of humanity, a birthright of all people.
... read
the whole article
Joseph Fels: True
Christianity and My Own Religious Beliefs
I believe that the Creator freely gave the earth
to all of His children, that all may have equal rights to
its use. Do you agree to that?
I believe that the injunction, "In the sweat of
thy brow shalt thou eat bread," necessarily implies,
"Thou shalt not eat bread in the sweat of thy brother's
brow." Do you agree?
I believe that all are violating the divine law
who live in idleness on wealth produced by others, since
they eat bread in the sweat of their brothers' brows. Do
you agree?
I believe that no man should have power to take
wealth he has not produced or earned unless freely given
to him by the producer. Do you agree?
I believe that brotherhood requires giving an
equivalent for every service received from a brother. Do
you agree?
I believe it is blasphemous to assert or insinuate
that God has condemned some of His children to hopeless
poverty, and to the Crimea, want, and misery resulting
therefrom, and has, at the same time, awarded to others
lives of ease and luxury, without labor. Do you
agree?
I believe that involuntary poverty and involuntary
idleness are unnatural, and are due to the denial by some
of the right of others to use freely the gift of God to
all. Do you agree?
Since labor products are needed to sustain life,
and since labor must be applied to land in order to
produce, I believe that every child comes into life with
divine permission to use land without the consent of any
other child of God. Do you agree?
Where men congregate in organized society, land
has a value apart from the value of things produced by
labor; as population and industry increase, the value of
land increases, but the value of labor products does not.
That increase in land value is community-made value.
Inasmuch as your power to labor is a gift of God, all the
wealth produced by your labor is yours, and no man nor
collection of men has a right to take any of it from you.
Do you agree to that?
I believe the community-made value of land belongs
to the community, just as the wealth produced by you
belongs to you. Do you agree to that?
Therefore, I believe that the fundamental evil,
the great God-denying crime of society, is the iniquitous
system under which men are permitted to put into their
pocket, confiscate, in fact, the community-made values of
land, while organized society confiscates for public
purposes a part of the wealth created by individuals. Do
you agree to that?
Using a concrete illustration: I own in the city
of Philadelphia 11-1/2 acres of land, for which I paid
32,500 dollars a few years ago. On account of increase of
population and industry in Philadelphia, that land is now
worth about 125,000 dollars. I have expended no labor or
money upon it. So I have done nothing to cause that
increase of 92,500 dollars in a few years. My
fellow-citizens in Philadelphia created it, and I believe
it therefore belongs to them, not to me. I believe that
the man-made law which gives to me and other landlords
values we have not created is a violation of the divine
law. I believe that Justice demands that these
community-made values be taken by the community for
common purposes instead of taxing enterprise and
industry. Do you agree? ...
Do you question the relationship between taxation
and righteousness? Let us see. If
government is a natural growth, then surely God's natural
law provides food and sustenance for government as that
food is needed; for where in Nature do we find a creature
coming into the world without timely provision of natural
food for it? It is in our system of taxation that
we find the most emphatic denial of the Fatherhood of God
and the Brotherhood of Man, because, first, in order to
meet our common needs, we take from individuals what does
not belong to us in common; second, we permit individuals
to take for themselves what does belong to us in common;
thus, third, under the pretext of taxation for public
purposes, we have established a system that permits some
men to tax other men for private profit. ...
read the
whole letter
Mason Gaffney: For
Want of a Landlord
In 1620 the Mayflower landed at Plymouth Rock with
its intrepid band, and supplies and provisions for the
first winter. These Pilgrims were of the working poor,
ready and able to turn their hands to labor. They had
carpenters, masons, joiners, bakers, farmers, chandlers,
boatsmen, fishers, hunters, and other useful types.
...
Yet all their hard work and frugality and mutual
aid and shrewd trading availed them nought, God did not
prosper their ventures. Poverty and distress prevailed;
crops withered; timbers rotted; stores spoiled; women
sued for divorce; discontent ran riot. The Elders
pondered. As luck would have it, one bachelor had packed
along a book on Political Economy for the lonely
evenings. Studying one night he suddenly cried "Eureka!
Political Economy will save us!" ... read the whole article
Martin Luther King, Jr: Where Do We
Go From Here? (1967)
... I want to say to you as I move to my conclusion,
as we talk about "Where do we go from here," that we
honestly face the fact that the Movement must address
itself to the question of restructuring the whole of
American society. There are forty million poor people
here. And one day we must ask the question, "Why are
there forty million poor people in America?" And when you
begin to ask that question, you are raising questions
about the economic system, about a broader distribution
of wealth. When you ask that question, you begin to
question the capitalistic economy. And I'm simply saying
that more and more, we've got to begin to ask questions
about the whole society. We are called upon to help the
discouraged beggars in life's market place. But one day
we must come to see that an edifice which produces
beggars needs restructuring. It means that questions must
be raised. You see, my friends, when you deal with
this,
- you begin to ask the question, "Who owns the
oil?"
- You begin to ask the question, "Who owns the iron
ore?"
- You begin to ask the question, "Why is it that people
have to pay water bills in a world that is two thirds
water?"
These are questions that must be asked. ... read the
book excerpt and whole speech
Bill Batt: Comment on Parts of the
NYS Legislative Tax Study Commission's 1985 study
“Who Pays New York Taxes?”
Land value taxation, on the other hand, overcomes all
these obstacles. Locations are the beneficiaries of
community services whether they are improved or not. As
has been forcefully argued by this writer and others
elsewhere,32 a tax on land value conforms to all the
textbook principles of sound tax theory. Some further
considerations are worth reviewing, however, when looking
at ground rent as a flow rather than as a “present
value” stock. The technical ability to trace
changes in the market prices of sites – or as can
also be understood, the variable flow of ground rent to
those sites – by the application of GIS (geographic
information systems) real-time recording of sales
transactions invites wholesale changes in the maintenance
of cadastral data. The transmittal of sales records as
typically received in the offices of local governments
for purposes of title registration over to
Assessors’ offices allows for the possibility of a
running real-time mapping of market values. Given also
that GIS algorithms can now calculate the land value
proportions reasonably accurately, this means that
“landvaluescapes” are easily created in ways
analogous to maps that portray other common geographic
features. These landvaluescapes reflect the flow
of ground rent through local or regional economies, and
can also be used to identify the areas of greatest market
vitality and enterprise. The flow of economic rent can
easily be taxed in ways that overcomes the mistaken
notion that it is a stock. Just as income is recognized
as a flow of money, rent too can (and should) be
understood as such.
The question still begs to be answered, “why tax
land?” And what happens when we don’t tax
land? Henry George answered this more than a century ago
more forcefully and clearly, perhaps, than anyone has
since. He recognized full well that the economic surplus
not expended by human hands or minds in the production of
capital wealth gravitates to land. Particular land sites
come to reflect the value of their strategic location for
market exchanges by assuming a price for their monopoly
use. Regardless whether those who acquire title to such
sites use them to the full extent of their potential, the
flow of rent to such locations is commensurate with their
full capacity. This is why John Stuart Mill more than a
century ago observed that, “Landlords grow richer
in their sleep without working, risking or economizing.
The increase in the value of land, arising as it
does from the efforts of an entire community, should
belong to the community and not to the individual who
might hold title.”33 Absent its recovery
by taxation this rent becomes a “free lunch”
to opportunistically situated titleholders. When offered
for sale, the projected rental value is capitalized in
the present value for purposes of attaching a market
price and sold as a commodity. Yet simple justice calls
for the recovery in taxes what is the community’s
creation. Moreover, the failure to recover the land rent
connected to sites makes it necessary to tax productive
activities in our economy, and this leads to economic and
technical inefficiency known as “deadweight
loss.”34 It means that the economy performs
suboptimally.
Land, and by this Henry George meant any natural
factor of production not created by human hands or minds,
is ours only to use, not to buy or sell as a commodity.
In the equally immortal words of Jefferson a century
earlier, “The earth belongs in usufruct to the
living; . . . [It is] given as a common stock for men to
labor and live on.”35 This passage likely needs a
bit of parsing for the modern reader. The word usufruct,
understood since Roman times, has almost passed from use
today. It means “the right to use the property of
another so long as its value is not diminished.”36
Note also that Jefferson regarded the earth as a
“common stock;” not allotted to individuals
with possessory titles. Only the phrase “to the
living” might be subject to challenge by
forward-looking environmentalists who, taking an idea
from Native American cultures, argue that “we do
not inherit the earth from our ancestors; we borrow it
from our children.” The presumption that real
property titles are acquired legitimately is a claim that
does not withstand scrutiny; rather all such titles owe
their origin ultimately to force or fraud.37
If we own the land sites that we occupy only
in usufruct, and the rent that derives from those sites
is due to community enterprise, it is not a large logical
leap to argue that the community’s recovery of that
rent should be the proper source of taxation. This is the
Georgist argument: that the recapture of land rent is the
proper – indeed the natural – source of
taxation.38 ... read the whole
commentary
|
To share this page with a friend:
right click, choose "send," and add your
comments.
|
|
Red links have not been
visited; .
Green links are pages you've seen
|
Essential Documents pertinent
to this theme:
|
|