Theft
Lead us not into temptation ... don't let us
be tempted to take from our neighbor — poor or rich
— that which is rightly his: that which he created
through his labor — that from which he earns his
living. Similarly, don't let us be tempted to allow
individuals or corporations to privatize that which is
rightly the property of the commons: the value of the
land and the natural creation, and the value of the
social surplus.
When we straighten out our incentives, and stop
allowing some of us to steal from others, a lot of our
most serious social, economic and justice problems will
evaporate.
As to what constitutes robbery,
it is, we will both agree, the taking or withholding from
another of that which rightfully belongs to him. That
which rightfully belongs to him, be it observed, not that
which legally belongs to him. ...
The repetition of a wrong may dull the
moral sense, but will not make it right. A robbery is no
less a robbery the thousand millionth time it is
committed than it was the first time.
— Henry George, Property in
Land Seems to me that a “right” is
something everyone should have, like life, liberty, free
speech, rewards of working and saving. A privilege is
something A can only have by depriving B et al. Those
with privileges have sought to expand the meaning of
“right” to include their privileges. —
Mason Gaffney (correspondence, May, 2006)
A house and the lot on which it stands are alike
property, as being the subject of ownership, and are
alike classed by the lawyers as real estate. Yet in
nature and relations they differ widely.
-
The one is produced by human labor, and belongs
to the class in political economy styled
wealth.
-
The other is a part of nature, and belongs to
the class in political economy styled land.
The essential character of the one class of things
is that they embody labor, are brought into being by
human exertion, their existence or nonexistence, their
increase or diminution, depending on man. The essential
character of the other class of things is that they do
not embody labor, and exist irrespective of human
exertion and irrespective of man; they are the field or
environment in which man finds himself; the storehouse
from which his needs must be supplied, the raw material
upon which and the forces with which alone his labor
can act.
The moment this distinction is realized, that moment
is it seen that the sanction which natural justice
gives to one species of property is denied to the
other.
For as labor cannot produce without the use of land,
the denial of the equal right to the use of land is
necessarily the denial of the right of labor to its own
produce. If one man can command the land upon which
others must labor, he can appropriate the produce of
their labor as the price of his permission to labor.
The fundamental law of nature, that her enjoyment by
man shall be consequent upon his exertion, is thus
violated. The one receives without producing; the
others produce without receiving. The one is unjustly
enriched; the others are robbed. ... read the whole
chapter
But great as they thus appear, the advantages of a
transference of all public burdens to a tax upon the
value of land cannot be fully appreciated until we
consider the effect upon the distribution of wealth.
Tracing out the cause of the unequal distribution of
wealth which appears in all civilized countries, with a
constant tendency to greater and greater inequality as
material progress goes on, we have found it in the fact
that, as civilization advances, the ownership of land,
now in private hands, gives a greater and greater power
of appropriating the wealth produced by labor and
capital.
Thus, to relieve labor and capital from all taxation,
direct and indirect, and to throw the burden upon rent,
would be, as far as it went, to counteract this tendency
to inequality, and, if it went so far as to take in
taxation the whole of rent, the cause of inequality would
be totally destroyed. Rent, instead of causing
inequality, as now, would then promote equality. Labor
and capital would then receive the whole produce, minus
that portion taken by the state in the taxation of land
values, which, being applied to public purposes, would be
equally distributed in public benefits.
That is to say, the wealth produced in every community
would be divided into two portions.
- One part would be distributed in wages and interest
between individual producers, according to the part
each had taken in the work of production;
- the other part would go to the community as a
whole, to be distributed in public benefits to all its
members.
In this all would share equally — the weak with
the strong, young children and decrepit old men, the
maimed, the halt, and the blind, as well as the vigorous.
And justly so — for while one part represents the
result of individual effort in production, the other
represents the increased power with which the community
as a whole aids the individual.
Thus, as material progress tends to increase rent,
were rent taken by the community for common purposes the
very cause which now tends to produce inequality as
material progress goes on would then tend to produce
greater and greater equality.
Who can say to what infinite powers the
wealth-producing capacity of labor may not be raised by
social adjustments which will give to the producers of
wealth their fair proportion of its advantages and
enjoyments! With present processes the gain would be
simply incalculable, but just as wages are high, so do
the invention and utilization of improved processes and
machinery go on with greater rapidity and ease.
But I shall not deny, and do not wish to lose sight of
the fact, that while thus preventing waste and thus
adding to the efficiency of labor, the equalization in
the distribution of wealth that would result from the
simple plan of taxation that I propose, must lessen the
intensity with which wealth is pursued. It seems to me
that in a condition of society in which no one need fear
poverty, no one would desire great wealth — at
least, no one would take the trouble to strive and to
strain for it as men do now. For, certainly, the
spectacle of men who have only a few years to live,
slaving away their time for the sake of dying rich, is in
itself so unnatural and absurd, that in a state of
society where the abolition of the fear of want had
dissipated the envious admiration with which the masses
of men now regard the possession of great riches, whoever
would toil to acquire more than he cared to use would be
looked upon as we would now look on a man who would
thatch his head with half a dozen hats.
And though this incentive to production be withdrawn,
can we not spare it? Whatever may have been its office in
an earlier stage of development, it is not needed now.
The dangers that menace our civilization do not come from
the weakness of the springs of production. What it
suffers from, and what, if a remedy be not applied, it
must die from, is unequal distribution!
Nor would the removal of this incentive, regarded only
from the standpoint of production, be an unmixed loss.
For, that the aggregate of production is greatly reduced
by the greed with which riches are pursued, is one of the
most obtrusive facts of modern society. While, were this
insane desire to get rich at any cost lessened, mental
activities now devoted to scraping together riches would
be translated into far higher spheres of usefulness. ...
read the whole chapter
Henry George: The Condition of Labor
— An Open Letter to Pope Leo XIII in response to
Rerum Novarum (1891)
As to the right of ownership, we hold: That
—
Being created individuals, with individual wants and
powers, men are individually entitled (subject of course
to the moral obligations that arise from such relations
as that of the family) to the use of their own powers and
the enjoyment of the results. There thus arises, anterior
to human law, and deriving its validity from the law of
God, a right of private ownership in things produced by
labor — a right that the possessor may transfer,
but of which to deprive him without his will is
theft.
This right of property, originating in the right of
the individual to himself, is the only full and complete
right of property. It attaches to things produced by
labor, but cannot attach to things created by God.
Thus, if a man take a fish from the ocean he acquires
a right of property in that fish, which exclusive right
he may transfer by sale or gift. But he cannot obtain a
similar right of property in the ocean, so that he may
sell it or give it or forbid others to use it.
Or, if he set up a windmill he acquires a right of
property in the things such use of wind enables him to
produce. But he cannot claim a right of property in the
wind itself, so that he may sell it or forbid others to
use it.
Or, if he cultivate grain he acquires a right of
property in the grain his labor brings forth. But he
cannot obtain a similar right of property in the sun
which ripened it or the soil on which it grew. For these
things are of the continuing gifts of God to all
generations of men, which all may use, but none may claim
as his alone.
To attach to things created by God the same right of
private ownership that justly attaches to things produced
by labor is to impair and deny the true rights of
property. For a man who out of the proceeds of his labor
is obliged to pay another man for the use of ocean or air
or sunshine or soil, all of which are to men involved in
the single term land, is in this deprived of his rightful
property and thus robbed. ...
Thus Cain and Abel, were there only two men on earth,
might by agreement divide the earth between them. Under
this compact each might claim exclusive right to his
share as against the other. But neither could rightfully
continue such claim against the next man born. For since
no one comes into the world without God’s
permission, his presence attests his equal right to the
use of God’s bounty. For them to refuse him
any use of the earth which they had divided between them
would therefore be for them to commit murder. And for
them to refuse him any use of the earth, unless by
laboring for them or by giving them part of the products
of his labor he bought it of them, would be for them to
commit theft. ...
God’s laws do not change. Though their
applications may alter with altering conditions, the same
principles of right and wrong that hold when men are few
and industry is rude also hold amid teeming populations
and complex industries. In our cities of millions and our
states of scores of millions, in a civilization where the
division of labor has gone so far that large numbers are
hardly conscious that they are land-users, it still
remains true that we are all land animals and can live
only on land, and that land is God’s bounty to all,
of which no one can be deprived without being murdered,
and for which no one can be compelled to pay another
without being robbed. But even in a state of society
where the elaboration of industry and the increase of
permanent improvements have made the need for private
possession of land wide-spread, there is no difficulty in
conforming individual possession with the equal right to
land. For as soon as any piece of land will yield to the
possessor a larger return than is had by similar labor on
other land a value attaches to it which is shown when it
is sold or rented. Thus, the value of the land itself,
irrespective of the value of any improvements in or on
it, always indicates the precise value of the benefit to
which all are entitled in its use, as distinguished from
the value which, as producer or successor of a producer,
belongs to the possessor in individual right.
To combine the advantages of private possession with
the justice of common ownership it is only necessary
therefore to take for common uses what value attaches to
land irrespective of any exertion of labor on it. The
principle is the same as in the case referred to, where a
human father leaves equally to his children things not
susceptible of specific division or common use. In that
case such things would be sold or rented and the value
equally applied.
It is on this common-sense principle that we, who term
ourselves single-tax men, would have the community
act.
We do not propose to assert equal rights to land by
keeping land common, letting any one use any part of it
at any time. We do not propose the task, impossible in
the present state of society, of dividing land in equal
shares; still less the yet more impossible task of
keeping it so divided.
We propose — leaving land in the private
possession of individuals, with full liberty on their
part to give, sell or bequeath it — simply to levy
on it for public uses a tax that shall equal the annual
value of the land itself, irrespective of the use made of
it or the improvements on it. And since this
would provide amply for the need of public revenues, we
would accompany this tax on land values with the repeal
of all taxes now levied on the products and processes of
industry — which taxes, since they take from the
earnings of labor, we hold to be infringements of the
right of property.
This we propose, not as a cunning device of human
ingenuity, but as a conforming of human regulations to
the will of God.
God cannot contradict himself nor impose on his
creatures laws that clash.
If it be God’s command to men that they should
not steal — that is to say, that they should
respect the right of property which each one has in the
fruits of his labor;
And if he be also the Father of all men, who in his
common bounty has intended all to have equal
opportunities for sharing;
Then, in any possible stage of civilization, however
elaborate, there must be some way in which the exclusive
right to the products of industry may be reconciled with
the equal right to land.
If the Almighty be consistent with himself, it cannot
be, as say those socialists referred to by you, that in
order to secure the equal participation of men in the
opportunities of life and labor we must ignore the right
of private property. Nor yet can it be, as you yourself
in the Encyclical seem to argue, that to secure the right
of private property we must ignore the equality of right
in the opportunities of life and labor. To say the one
thing or the other is equally to deny the harmony of
God’s laws.
But, the private possession of land, subject to the
payment to the community of the value of any special
advantage thus given to the individual, satisfies both
laws, securing to all equal participation in the bounty
of the Creator and to each the full ownership of the
products of his labor. ...
Nor do we hesitate to say that this way of securing
the equal right to the bounty of the Creator and the
exclusive right to the products of labor is the way
intended by God for raising public revenues. For we are
not atheists, who deny God; nor semi-atheists, who deny
that he has any concern in politics and legislation.
It is true as you say — a salutary truth too
often forgotten — that “man is older than the
state, and he holds the right of providing for the life
of his body prior to the formation of any state.”
Yet, as you too perceive, it is also true that the state
is in the divinely appointed order. For He who foresaw
all things and provided for all things, foresaw and
provided that with the increase of population and the
development of industry the organization of human society
into states or governments would become both expedient
and necessary.
No sooner does the state arise than, as we all know,
it needs revenues. This need for revenues is small at
first, while population is sparse, industry rude and the
functions of the state few and simple. But with growth of
population and advance of civilization the functions of
the state increase and larger and larger revenues are
needed.
Now, He that made the world and placed man in it, He
that pre-ordained civilization as the means whereby man
might rise to higher powers and become more and more
conscious of the works of his Creator, must have foreseen
this increasing need for state revenues and have made
provision for it. That is to say: The increasing need for
public revenues with social advance, being a natural,
God-ordained need, there must be a right way of raising
them — some way that we can truly say is the way
intended by God. It is clear that this right way of
raising public revenues must accord with the moral
law.
Hence:
It must not take from individuals what rightfully
belongs to individuals.
It must not give some an advantage over others, as by
increasing the prices of what some have to sell and
others must buy.
It must not lead men into temptation, by requiring
trivial oaths, by making it profitable to lie, to swear
falsely, to bribe or to take bribes.
It must not confuse the distinctions of right and
wrong, and weaken the sanctions of religion and the state
by creating crimes that are not sins, and punishing men
for doing what in itself they have an undoubted right to
do.
It must not repress industry. It must not check
commerce. It must not punish thrift. It must offer no
impediment to the largest production and the fairest
division of wealth.
Let me ask your Holiness to consider the taxes on the
processes and products of industry by which through the
civilized world public revenues are collected — the
octroi duties that surround Italian cities with barriers;
the monstrous customs duties that hamper intercourse
between so-called Christian states; the taxes on
occupations, on earnings, on investments, on the building
of houses, on the cultivation of fields, on industry and
thrift in all forms. Can these be the ways God has
intended that governments should raise the means they
need? Have any of them the characteristics indispensable
in any plan we can deem a right one?
All these taxes violate the moral law. They take by
force what belongs to the individual alone; they give to
the unscrupulous an advantage over the scrupulous; they
have the effect, nay are largely intended, to increase
the price of what some have to sell and others must buy;
they corrupt government; they make oaths a mockery; they
shackle commerce; they fine industry and thrift; they
lessen the wealth that men might enjoy, and enrich some
by impoverishing others.
Yet what most strikingly shows how opposed to
Christianity is this system of raising public revenues is
its influence on thought.
Christianity teaches us that all men are brethren;
that their true interests are harmonious, not
antagonistic. It gives us, as the golden rule of life,
that we should do to others as we would have others do to
us. But out of the system of taxing the products and
processes of labor, and out of its effects in increasing
the price of what some have to sell and others must buy,
has grown the theory of “protection,” which
denies this gospel, which holds Christ ignorant of
political economy and proclaims laws of national
well-being utterly at variance with his teaching. This
theory sanctifies national hatreds; it inculcates a
universal war of hostile tariffs; it teaches peoples that
their prosperity lies in imposing on the productions of
other peoples restrictions they do not wish imposed on
their own; and instead of the Christian doctrine of
man’s brotherhood it makes injury of foreigners a
civic virtue.
“By their fruits ye shall know them.” Can
anything more clearly show that to tax the products and
processes of industry is not the way God intended public
revenues to be raised?
But to consider what we propose — the raising of
public revenues by a single tax on the value of land
irrespective of improvements — is to see that in
all respects this does conform to the moral law.
Let me ask your Holiness to keep in mind that the
value we propose to tax, the value of land irrespective
of improvements, does not come from any exertion of labor
or investment of capital on or in it — the values
produced in this way being values of improvement which we
would exempt. The value of land irrespective of
improvement is the value that attaches to land by reason
of increasing population and social progress. This is a
value that always goes to the owner as owner, and never
does and never can go to the user; for if the user be a
different person from the owner he must always pay the
owner for it in rent or in purchase-money; while if the
user be also the owner, it is as owner, not as user, that
he receives it, and by selling or renting the land he
can, as owner, continue to receive it after he ceases to
be a user.
Thus, taxes on land irrespective of improvement cannot
lessen the rewards of industry, nor add to prices,* nor
in any way take from the individual what belongs to the
individual. They can take only the value that attaches to
land by the growth of the community, and which therefore
belongs to the community as a whole.
* As to this point it may be well to add
that all economists are agreed that taxes on land
values irrespective of improvement or use — or
what in the terminology of political economy is styled
rent, a term distinguished from the ordinary use of the
word rent by being applied solely to payments for the
use of land itself — must be paid by the owner
and cannot be shifted by him on the user. To explain in
another way the reason given in the text: Price is not
determined by the will of the seller or the will of the
buyer, but by the equation of demand and supply, and
therefore as to things constantly demanded and
constantly produced rests at a point determined by the
cost of production — whatever tends to increase
the cost of bringing fresh quantities of such articles
to the consumer increasing price by checking supply,
and whatever tends to reduce such cost decreasing price
by increasing supply. Thus taxes on wheat or tobacco or
cloth add to the price that the consumer must pay, and
thus the cheapening in the cost of producing steel
which improved processes have made in recent years has
greatly reduced the price of steel. But land has no
cost of production, since it is created by God, not
produced by man. Its price therefore is fixed
—
1 (monopoly rent), where land is held
in close monopoly, by what the owners can extract
from the users under penalty of deprivation and
consequently of starvation, and amounts to all that
common labor can earn on it beyond what is necessary
to life;
2 (economic rent proper), where there is no special
monopoly, by what the particular land will yield to
common labor over and above what may be had by like
expenditure and exertion on land having no special
advantage and for which no rent is paid; and,
3 (speculative rent, which is a species of monopoly
rent, telling particularly in selling price), by the
expectation of future increase of value from social
growth and improvement, which expectation causing
landowners to withhold land at present prices has the
same effect as combination.
Taxes on land values or economic rent
can therefore never be shifted by the landowner to the
land-user, since they in no wise increase the demand
for land or enable landowners to check supply by
withholding land from use. Where rent depends on mere
monopolization, a case I mention because rent may in
this way be demanded for the use of land even before
economic or natural rent arises, the taking by taxation
of what the landowners were able to extort from labor
could not enable them to extort any more, since
laborers, if not left enough to live on, will die. So,
in the case of economic rent proper, to take from the
landowners the premiums they receive, would in no way
increase the superiority of their land and the demand
for it. While, so far as price is affected by
speculative rent, to compel the landowners to pay taxes
on the value of land whether they were getting any
income from it or not, would make it more difficult for
them to withhold land from use; and to tax the full
value would not merely destroy the power but the desire
to do so.
To take land values for the state, abolishing all
taxes on the products of labor, would therefore leave to
the laborer the full produce of labor; to the individual
all that rightfully belongs to the individual. It would
impose no burden on industry, no check on commerce, no
punishment on thrift; it would secure the largest
production and the fairest distribution of wealth, by
leaving men free to produce and to exchange as they
please, without any artificial enhancement of prices; and
by taking for public purposes a value that cannot be
carried off, that cannot be hidden, that of all values is
most easily ascertained and most certainly and cheaply
collected, it would enormously lessen the number of
officials, dispense with oaths, do away with temptations
to bribery and evasion, and abolish man-made crimes in
themselves innocent.
But, further: That God has intended the state to
obtain the revenues it needs by the taxation of land
values is shown by the same order and degree of evidence
that shows that God has intended the milk of the mother
for the nourishment of the babe.
See how close is the analogy. In that primitive
condition ere the need for the state arises there are no
land values. The products of labor have value, but in the
sparsity of population no value as yet attaches to land
itself. But as increasing density of population and
increasing elaboration of industry necessitate the
organization of the state, with its need for revenues,
value begins to attach to land. As population still
increases and industry grows more elaborate, so the needs
for public revenues increase. And at the same time and
from the same causes land values increase. The connection
is invariable. The value of things produced by labor
tends to decline with social development, since the
larger scale of production and the improvement of
processes tend steadily to reduce their cost. But the
value of land on which population centers goes up and up.
Take Rome or Paris or London or New York or Melbourne.
Consider the enormous value of land in such cities as
compared with the value of land in sparsely settled parts
of the same countries. To what is this due? Is it not due
to the density and activity of the populations of those
cities — to the very causes that require great
public expenditure for streets, drains, public buildings,
and all the many things needed for the health,
convenience and safety of such great cities? See how with
the growth of such cities the one thing that steadily
increases in value is land; how the opening of roads, the
building of railways, the making of any public
improvement, adds to the value of land. Is it not clear
that here is a natural law — that is to say a
tendency willed by the Creator? Can it mean anything else
than that He who ordained the state with its needs has in
the values which attach to land provided the means to
meet those needs? ...
That the value attaching to land with social growth is
intended for social needs is shown by the final proof.
God is indeed a jealous God in the sense that nothing but
injury and disaster can attend the effort of men to do
things other than in the way he has intended; in the
sense that where the blessings he proffers to men are
refused or misused they turn to evils that scourge us.
And just as for the mother to withhold the provision that
fills her breast with the birth of the child is to
endanger physical health, so for society to refuse to
take for social uses the provision intended for them is
to breed social disease.
For refusal to take for public purposes the increasing
values that attach to land with social growth is to
necessitate the getting of public revenues by taxes that
lessen production, distort distribution and corrupt
society. It is to leave some to take what justly belongs
to all; it is to forego the only means by which it is
possible in an advanced civilization to combine the
security of possession that is necessary to improvement
with the equality of natural opportunity that is the most
important of all natural rights. It is thus at the basis
of all social life to set up an unjust inequality between
man and man, compelling some to pay others for the
privilege of living, for the chance of working, for the
advantages of civilization, for the gifts of their God.
But it is even more than this. The very robbery
that the masses of men thus suffer gives rise in
advancing communities to a new robbery. For the value
that with the increase of population and social advance
attaches to land being suffered to go to individuals who
have secured ownership of the land, it prompts to a
forestalling of and speculation in land wherever there is
any prospect of advancing population or of coming
improvement, thus producing an artificial scarcity of the
natural elements of life and labor, and a strangulation
of production that shows itself in recurring spasms of
industrial depression as disastrous to the world as
destructive wars. It is this that is driving men
from the old countries to the new countries, only to
bring there the same curses. It is this that causes our
material advance not merely to fail to improve the
condition of the mere worker, but to make the condition
of large classes positively worse. It is this that in our
richest Christian countries is giving us a large
population whose lives are harder, more hopeless, more
degraded than those of the veriest savages. It is this
that leads so many men to think that God is a bungler and
is constantly bringing more people into his world than he
has made provision for; or that there is no God, and that
belief in him is a superstition which the facts of life
and the advance of science are dispelling. ...
Thus, that any species of property is permitted by the
state does not of itself give it moral sanction. The
state has often made things property that are not justly
property, but involve violence and robbery. For instance,
the things of religion, the dignity and authority of
offices of the church, the power of administering her
sacraments and controlling her temporalities, have often
by profligate princes been given as salable property to
courtiers and concubines. At this very day in England an
atheist or a heathen may buy in open market, and hold as
legal property, to be sold, given or bequeathed as he
pleases, the power of appointing to the cure of souls,
and the value of these legal rights of presentation is
said to be no less than £17,000,000.
Or again: Slaves were universally treated as property
by the customs and laws of the classical nations, and
were so acknowledged in Europe long after the acceptance
of Christianity. At the beginning of this century there
was no Christian nation that did not, in her colonies at
least, recognize property in slaves, and slaveships
crossed the seas under Christian flags. In the United
States, little more than thirty years ago, to buy a man
gave the same legal ownership as to buy a horse, and in
Mohammedan countries law and custom yet make the slave
the property of his captor or purchaser.
Yet your Holiness, one of the glories of whose
pontificate is the attempt to break up slavery in its
last strongholds, will not contend that the moral
sanction that attaches to property in things produced by
labor can, or ever could, apply to property in
slaves.
Your use, in so many passages of your Encyclical, of
the inclusive term “property” or
“private” property, of which in morals
nothing can be either affirmed or denied, makes your
meaning, if we take isolated sentences, in many places
ambiguous. But reading it as a whole, there can be no
doubt of your intention that private property in land
shall be understood when you speak merely of private
property. With this interpretation, I find that the
reasons you urge for private property in land are eight.
Let us consider them in order of presentation. You
urge:
1. That what is bought with rightful property is
rightful property. (RN, paragraph 5) ...
2. That private property in land proceeds from
man’s gift of reason. (RN, paragraphs 6-7.)
...
3. That private property in land deprives no one of the
use of land. (RN, paragraph 8.) ...
4. That Industry expended on land gives ownership in
the land itself. (RN, paragraphs 9-10.) ...
5. That private property in land has the support of the
common opinion of mankind, and has conduced to peace
and tranquillity, and that it is sanctioned by Divine
Law. (RN, paragraph 11.) ...
6. That fathers should provide for their children and
that private property in land is necessary to enable
them to do so. (RN, paragraphs 14-17.) ...
7. That the private ownership of land stimulates
industry, increases wealth, and attaches men to the
soil and to their country. (RN, paragraph 51.)
...
8. That the right to possess private property in land
is from nature, not from man; that the state has no
right to abolish it, and that to take the value of
landownership in taxation would be unjust and cruel to
the private owner. (RN, paragraph 51.) ...
4. That Industry expended on land gives
ownership in the land itself. (9-10.)
Your Holiness next contends that industry expended on
land gives a right to ownership of the land, and that the
improvement of land creates benefits indistinguishable
and inseparable from the land itself.
This contention, if valid, could only justify the
ownership of land by those who expend industry on it. It
would not justify private property in land as it exists.
On the contrary, it would justify a gigantic no-rent
declaration that would take land from those who now
legally own it, the landlords, and turn it over to the
tenants and laborers. And if it also be that improvements
cannot be distinguished and separated from the land
itself, how could the landlords claim consideration even
for improvements they had made?
But your Holiness cannot mean what your words imply.
What you really mean, I take it, is that the original
justification and title of landownership is in the
expenditure of labor on it. But neither can this justify
private property in land as it exists. For is it not all
but universally true that existing land titles do not
come from use, but from force or fraud?
Take Italy! Is it not true that the greater part of
the land of Italy is held by those who so far from ever
having expended industry on it have been mere
appropriators of the industry of those who have? Is this
not also true of Great Britain and of other countries?
Even in the United States, where the forces of
concentration have not yet had time fully to operate and
there has been some attempt to give land to users, it is
probably true today that the greater part of the land is
held by those who neither use it nor propose to use it
themselves, but merely hold it to compel others to pay
them for permission to use it.
And if industry give ownership to land what are the
limits of this ownership? If a man may acquire the
ownership of several square miles of land by grazing
sheep on it, does this give to him and his heirs the
ownership of the same land when it is found to contain
rich mines, or when by the growth of population and the
progress of society it is needed for farming, for
gardening, for the close occupation of a great city? Is
it on the rights given by the industry of those who first
used it for grazing cows or growing potatoes that you
would found the title to the land now covered by the city
of New York and having a value of thousands of millions
of dollars?
But your contention is not valid. Industry expended on
land gives ownership in the fruits of that industry, but
not in the land itself, just as industry expended on the
ocean would give a right of ownership to the fish taken
by it, but not a right of ownership in the ocean. Nor yet
is it true that private ownership of land is necessary to
secure the fruits of labor on land; nor does the
improvement of land create benefits indistinguishable and
inseparable from the land itself. That secure possession
is necessary to the use and improvement of land I have
already explained, but that ownership is not necessary is
shown by the fact that in all civilized countries land
owned by one person is cultivated and improved by other
persons. Most of the cultivated land in the British
Islands, as in Italy and other countries, is cultivated
not by owners but by tenants. And so the costliest
buildings are erected by those who are not owners of the
land, but who have from the owner a mere right of
possession for a time on condition of certain payments.
Nearly the whole of London has been built in this way,
and in New York, Chicago, Denver, San Francisco, Sydney
and Melbourne, as well as in continental cities, the
owners of many of the largest edifices will be found to
be different persons from the owners of the ground. So
far from the value of improvements being inseparable from
the value of land, it is in individual transactions
constantly separated. For instance, one-half of the land
on which the immense Grand Pacific Hotel in Chicago
stands was recently separately sold, and in Ceylon it is
a not infrequent occurrence for one person to own a
fruit-tree and another to own the ground in which it is
implanted.
There is, indeed, no improvement of land, whether it
be clearing, plowing, manuring, cultivating, the digging
of cellars, the opening of wells or the building of
houses, that so long as its usefulness continues does not
have a value clearly distinguishable from the value of
the land. For land having such improvements will always
sell or rent for more than similar land without them.
If, therefore, the state levy a tax equal to what the
land irrespective of improvement would bring, it will
take the benefits of mere ownership, but will leave the
full benefits of use and improvement, which the
prevailing system does not do. And since the holder, who
would still in form continue to be the owner, could at
any time give or sell both possession and improvements,
subject to future assessment by the state on the value of
the land alone, he will be perfectly free to retain or
dispose of the full amount of property that the exertion
of his labor or the investment of his capital has
attached to or stored up in the land.
Thus, what we propose would secure, as it is
impossible in any other way to secure, what you properly
say is just and right — ”that the results of
labor should belong to him who has labored.” But
private property in land — to allow the holder
without adequate payment to the state to take for himself
the benefit of the value that attaches to land with
social growth and improvement — does take the
results of labor from him who has labored, does turn over
the fruits of one man’s labor to be enjoyed by
another. For labor, as the active factor, is the producer
of all wealth. Mere ownership produces nothing. A man
might own a world, but so sure is the decree that
“by the sweat of thy brow shalt thou eat
bread,” that without labor he could not get a meal
or provide himself a garment. Hence, when the owners of
land, by virtue of their ownership and without laboring
themselves, get the products of labor in abundance, these
things must come from the labor of others, must be the
fruits of others’ sweat, taken from those who have
a right to them and enjoyed by those who have no right to
them.
The only utility of private ownership of land as
distinguished from possession is the evil utility of
giving to the owner products of labor he does not earn.
For until land will yield to its owner some return beyond
that of the labor and capital he expends on it —
that is to say, until by sale or rental he can without
expenditure of labor obtain from it products of labor,
ownership amounts to no more than security of possession,
and has no value. Its importance and value begin only
when, either in the present or prospectively, it will
yield a revenue — that is to say, will enable the
owner as owner to obtain products of labor without
exertion on his part, and thus to enjoy the results of
others’ labor.
What largely keeps men from realizing the robbery
involved in private property in land is that in the most
striking cases the robbery is not of individuals, but of
the community. For, as I have before explained, it is
impossible for rent in the economic sense — that
value which attaches to land by reason of social growth
and improvement — to go to the user. It can go only
to the owner or to the community. Thus those who pay
enormous rents for the use of land in such centers as
London or New York are not individually injured.
Individually they get a return for what they pay, and
must feel that they have no better right to the use of
such peculiarly advantageous localities without paying
for it than have thousands of others. And so, not
thinking or not caring for the interests of the
community, they make no objection to the system.
It recently came to light in New York that a man
having no title whatever had been for years collecting
rents on a piece of land that the growth of the city had
made very valuable. Those who paid these rents had never
stopped to ask whether he had any right to them. They
felt that they had no right to land that so many others
would like to have, without paying for it, and did not
think of, or did not care for, the rights of all.
6. That fathers should provide for their
children and that private property in land is necessary
to enable them to do so. (14-17.)
With all that your Holiness has to say of the
sacredness of the family relation we are in full accord.
But how the obligation of the father to the child can
justify private property in land we cannot see. You
reason that private property in land is necessary to the
discharge of the duty of the father, and is therefore
requisite and just, because —
It is a most sacred law of nature that a father must
provide food and all necessaries for those whom he has
begotten; and, similarly, nature dictates that a
man’s children, who carry on, as it were, and
continue his own personality, should be provided by him
with all that is needful to enable them honorably to keep
themselves from want and misery in the uncertainties of
this mortal life. Now, in no other way can a father
effect this except by the ownership of profitable
property, which he can transmit to his children by
inheritance. (14.)
Thanks to Him who has bound the generations of men
together by a provision that brings the tenderest love to
greet our entrance into the world and soothes our exit
with filial piety, it is both the duty and the joy of the
father to care for the child till its powers mature, and
afterwards in the natural order it becomes the duty and
privilege of the child to be the stay of the parent. This
is the natural reason for that relation of marriage, the
groundwork of the sweetest, tenderest and purest of human
joys, which the Catholic Church has guarded with such
unremitting vigilance.
We do, for a few years, need the providence of our
fathers after the flesh. But how small, how transient,
how narrow is this need, as compared with our constant
need for the providence of Him in whom we live, move and
have our being — Our Father who art in Heaven! It
is to him, “the giver of every good and perfect
gift,” and not to our fathers after the flesh, that
Christ taught us to pray, “Give us this day our
daily bread.” And how true it is that it is through
him that the generations of men exist! Let the mean
temperature of the earth rise or fall a few degrees, an
amount as nothing compared with differences produced in
our laboratories, and mankind would disappear as ice
disappears under a tropical sun, would fall as the leaves
fall at the touch of frost. Or, let for two or three
seasons the earth refuse her increase, and how many of
our millions would remain alive?
The duty of fathers to transmit to their children
profitable property that will enable them to keep
themselves from want and misery in the uncertainties of
this mortal life! What is not possible cannot be a duty.
And how is it possible for fathers to do that? Your
Holiness has not considered how mankind really lives from
hand to mouth, getting each day its daily bread; how
little one generation does or can leave another. It is
doubtful if the wealth of the civilized world all told
amounts to anything like as much as one year’s
labor, while it is certain that if labor were to stop and
men had to rely on existing accumulation, it would be
only a few days ere in the richest countries pestilence
and famine would stalk.
The profitable property your Holiness refers to, is
private property in land. Now profitable land, as all
economists will agree, is land superior to the land that
the ordinary man can get. It is land that will yield an
income to the owner as owner, and therefore that will
permit the owner to appropriate the products of labor
without doing labor, its profitableness to the individual
involving the robbery of other individuals. It is
therefore possible only for some fathers to leave their
children profitable land. What therefore your Holiness
practically declares is, that it is the duty of all
fathers to struggle to leave their children what only the
few peculiarly strong, lucky or unscrupulous can leave;
and that, a something that involves the robbery of others
— their deprivation of the material gifts of
God.
This anti-Christian doctrine has been long in practice
throughout the Christian world. What are its results?
Are they not the very evils set forth in your
Encyclical? Are they not, so far from enabling men to
keep themselves from want and misery in the uncertainties
of this mortal life, to condemn the great masses of men
to want and misery that the natural conditions of our
mortal life do not entail; to want and misery deeper and
more wide-spread than exist among heathen savages? Under
the régime of private property in land and in the
richest countries not five per cent of fathers are able
at their death to leave anything substantial to their
children, and probably a large majority do not leave
enough to bury them! Some few children are left by their
fathers richer than it is good for them to be, but the
vast majority not only are left nothing by their fathers,
but by the system that makes land private property are
deprived of the bounty of their Heavenly Father; are
compelled to sue others for permission to live and to
work, and to toil all their lives for a pittance that
often does not enable them to escape starvation and
pauperism.
What your Holiness is actually, though of course
inadvertently, urging, is that earthly fathers should
assume the functions of the Heavenly Father. It is not
the business of one generation to provide the succeeding
generation “with all that is needful to enable them
honorably to keep themselves from want and misery.”
That is God’s business. We no more create our
children than we create our fathers. It is God who is the
Creator of each succeeding generation as fully as of the
one that preceded it. And, to recall your own words (7),
“Nature [God], therefore, owes to man a storehouse
that shall never fail, the daily supply of his daily
wants. And this he finds only in the inexhaustible
fertility of the earth.” What you are now assuming
is, that it is the duty of men to provide for the wants
of their children by appropriating this storehouse and
depriving other men’s children of the unfailing
supply that God has provided for all.
The duty of the father to the child — the duty
possible to all fathers! Is it not so to conduct himself,
so to nurture and teach it, that it shall come to manhood
with a sound body, well-developed mind, habits of virtue,
piety and industry, and in a state of society that shall
give it and all others free access to the bounty of God,
the providence of the All-Father?
In doing this the father would be doing more to secure
his children from want and misery than is possible now to
the richest of fathers — as much more as the
providence of God surpasses that of man. For the justice
of God laughs at the efforts of men to circumvent it, and
the subtle law that binds humanity together poisons the
rich in the sufferings of the poor. Even the few who are
able in the general struggle to leave their children
wealth that they fondly think will keep them from want
and misery in the uncertainties of this mortal life
— do they succeed? Does experience show that it is
a benefit to a child to place him above his fellows and
enable him to think God’s law of labor is not for
him? Is not such wealth oftener a curse than a blessing,
and does not its expectation often destroy filial love
and bring dissensions and heartburnings into families?
And how far and how long are even the richest and
strongest able to exempt their children from the common
lot? Nothing is more certain than that the blood of the
masters of the world flows today in lazzaroni and that
the descendants of kings and princes tenant slums and
workhouses.
But in the state of society we strive for, where the
monopoly and waste of God’s bounty would be done
away with and the fruits of labor would go to the
laborer, it would be within the ability of all to make
more than a comfortable living with reasonable labor. And
for those who might be crippled or incapacitated, or
deprived of their natural protectors and breadwinners,
the most ample provision could be made out of that great
and increasing fund with which God in his law of rent has
provided society — not as a matter of niggardly and
degrading alms, but as a matter of right, as the
assurance which in a Christian state society owes to all
its members.
Thus it is that the duty of the father, the obligation
to the child, instead of giving any support to private
property in land, utterly condemns it, urging us by the
most powerful considerations to abolish it in the simple
and efficacious way of the single tax.
This duty of the father, this obligation to children,
is not confined to those who have actually children of
their own, but rests on all of us who have come to the
powers and responsibilities of manhood.
For did not Christ set a little child in the midst of
the disciples, saying to them that the angels of such
little ones always behold the face of his Father; saying
to them that it were better for a man to hang a millstone
about his neck and plunge into the uttermost depths of
the sea than to injure such a little one?
And what today is the result of private property in
land in the richest of so-called Christian countries? Is
it not that young people fear to marry; that married
people fear to have children; that children are driven
out of life from sheer want of proper nourishment and
care, or compelled to toil when they ought to be at
school or at play; that great numbers of those who attain
maturity enter it with under-nourished bodies,
overstrained nerves, undeveloped minds — under
conditions that foredoom them, not merely to suffering,
but to crime; that fit them in advance for the prison and
the brothel?
If your Holiness will consider these things we are
confident that instead of defending private property in
land you will condemn it with anathema! ...
8. That the right to possess private property
in land is from nature, not from man; that the state has
no right to abolish it, and that to take the value of
landownership in taxation would be unjust and cruel to
the private owner. (51.)
This, like much else that your Holiness says, is
masked in the use of the indefinite terms “private
property” and “private owner” — a
want of precision in the use of words that has doubtless
aided in the confusion of your own thought. But the
context leaves no doubt that by private property you mean
private property in land, and by private owner, the
private owner of land.
The contention, thus made, that private property in
land is from nature, not from man, has no other basis
than the confounding of ownership with possession and the
ascription to property in land of what belongs to its
contradictory, property in the proceeds of labor. You do
not attempt to show for it any other basis, nor has any
one else ever attempted to do so. That private property
in the products of labor is from nature is clear, for
nature gives such things to labor and to labor alone. Of
every article of this kind, we know that it came into
being as nature’s response to the exertion of an
individual man or of individual men — given by
nature directly and exclusively to him or to them. Thus
there inheres in such things a right of private property,
which originates from and goes back to the source of
ownership, the maker of the thing. This right is anterior
to the state and superior to its enactments, so that, as
we hold, it is a violation of natural right and an
injustice to the private owner for the state to tax the
processes and products of labor. They do not belong to
Caesar. They are things that God, of whom nature is but
an expression, gives to those who apply for them in the
way he has appointed — by labor.
But who will dare trace the individual ownership of
land to any grant from the Maker of land? What does
nature give to such ownership? how does she in any way
recognize it? Will any one show from difference of form
or feature, of stature or complexion, from dissection of
their bodies or analysis of their powers and needs, that
one man was intended by nature to own land and another to
live on it as his tenant? That which derives its
existence from man and passes away like him, which is
indeed but the evanescent expression of his labor, man
may hold and transfer as the exclusive property of the
individual; but how can such individual ownership attach
to land, which existed before man was, and which
continues to exist while the generations of men come and
go — the unfailing storehouse that the Creator
gives to man for “the daily supply of his daily
wants”?
Clearly, the private ownership of land is from the state,
not from nature. Thus, not merely can no objection be
made on the score of morals when it is proposed that the
state shall abolish it altogether, but insomuch as it is
a violation of natural right, its existence involving a
gross injustice on the part of the state, an
“impious violation of the benevolent intention of
the Creator,” it is a moral duty that the state so
abolish it.
So far from there being anything unjust in taking the
full value of landownership for the use of the community,
the real injustice is in leaving it in private hands
— an injustice that amounts to robbery and
murder.
And when your Holiness shall see this I have no fear
that you will listen for one moment to the impudent plea
that before the community can take what God intended it
to take — before men who have been disinherited of
their natural rights can be restored to them, the present
owners of land shall first be compensated.
For not only will you see that the single tax will
directly and largely benefit small landowners, whose
interests as laborers and capitalists are much greater
than their interests as landowners, and that though the
great landowners — or rather the propertied class
in general among whom the profits of landownership are
really divided through mortgages, rent-charges, etc.
— would relatively lose, they too would be absolute
gainers in the increased prosperity and improved morals;
but more quickly, more strongly, more peremptorily than
from any calculation of gains or losses would your duty
as a man, your faith as a Christian, forbid you to listen
for one moment to any such paltering with right and
wrong.
Where the state takes some land for public uses it is
only just that those whose land is taken should be
compensated, otherwise some landowners would be treated
more harshly than others. But where, by a measure
affecting all alike, rent is appropriated for the benefit
of all, there can be no claim to compensation.
Compensation in such case would be a continuance of the
same in another form — the giving to landowners in
the shape of interest of what they before got as rent.
Your Holiness knows that justice and injustice are not
thus to be juggled with, and when you fully realize that
land is really the storehouse that God owes to all his
children, you will no more listen to any demand for
compensation for restoring it to them than Moses would
have listened to a demand that Pharaoh should be
compensated before letting the children of Israel go.
Compensated for what? For giving up what has been
unjustly taken? The demand of landowners for compensation
is not that. We do not seek to spoil the Egyptians. We do
not ask that what has been unjustly taken from laborers
shall be restored. We are willing that bygones should be
bygones and to leave dead wrongs to bury their dead. We
propose to let those who by the past appropriation of
land values have taken the fruits of labor to retain what
they have thus got. We merely propose that for the future
such robbery of labor shall cease — that for the
future, not for the past, landholders shall pay to the
community the rent that to the community is justly due.
...
You assume that the labor question is a question
between wage-workers and their employers. But working for
wages is not the primary or exclusive occupation of
labor. Primarily men work for themselves without the
intervention of an employer. And the primary source of
wages is in the earnings of labor, the man who works for
himself and consumes his own products receiving his wages
in the fruits of his labor. Are not fishermen, boatmen,
cab-drivers, peddlers, working farmers — all, in
short, of the many workers who get their wages directly
by the sale of their services or products without the
medium of an employer, as much laborers as those who work
for the specific wages of an employer? In your
consideration of remedies you do not seem even to have
thought of them. Yet in reality the laborers who work for
themselves are the first to be considered, since what men
will be willing to accept from employers depends
manifestly on what they can get by working for
themselves.
You assume that all employers are rich men, who might
raise wages much higher were they not so grasping. But is
it not the fact that the great majority of employers are
in reality as much pressed by competition as their
workmen, many of them constantly on the verge of failure?
Such employers could not possibly raise the wages they
pay, however they might wish to, unless all others were
compelled to do so.
You assume that there are in the natural order two
classes, the rich and the poor, and that laborers
naturally belong to the poor.
It is true as you say that there are differences in
capacity, in diligence, in health and in strength, that
may produce differences in fortune. These, however, are
not the differences that divide men into rich and poor.
The natural differences in powers and aptitudes are
certainly not greater than are natural differences in
stature. But while it is only by selecting giants and
dwarfs that we can find men twice as tall as others, yet
in the difference between rich and poor that exists today
we find some men richer than other men by the
thousandfold and the millionfold.
Nowhere do these differences between wealth
and poverty coincide with differences in individual
powers and aptitudes. The real difference between rich
and poor is the difference between those who hold the
tollgates and those who pay toll; between
tribute-receivers and tribute-yielders.
In what way does nature justify such a difference? In
the numberless varieties of animated nature we find some
species that are evidently intended to live on other
species. But their relations are always marked by
unmistakable differences in size, shape or organs. To man
has been given dominion over all the other living things
that tenant the earth. But is not this mastery indicated
even in externals, so that no one can fail on sight to
distinguish between a man and one of the inferior
animals? Our American apologists for slavery used to
contend that the black skin and woolly hair of the negro
indicated the intent of nature that the black should
serve the white; but the difference that you assume to be
natural is between men of the same race. What difference
does nature show between such men as would indicate her
intent that one should live idly yet be rich, and the
other should work hard yet be poor? If I could bring you
from the United States a man who has $200,000,000, and
one who is glad to work for a few dollars a week, and
place them side by side in your antechamber, would you be
able to tell which was which, even were you to call in
the most skilled anatomist? Is it not clear that God in
no way countenances or condones the division of rich and
poor that exists today, or in any way permits it, except
as having given them free will he permits men to choose
either good or evil, and to avoid heaven if they prefer
hell. For is it not clear that the division of
men into the classes rich and poor has invariably its
origin in force and fraud; invariably involves violation
of the moral law; and is really a division into those who
get the profits of robbery and those who are robbed;
those who hold in exclusive possession what God made for
all, and those who are deprived of his bounty?
Did not Christ in all his utterances and parables show
that the gross difference between rich and poor is
opposed to God’s law? Would he have condemned the
rich so strongly as he did, if the class distinction
between rich and poor did not involve injustice —
was not opposed to God’s intent?
It seems to us that your Holiness misses its real
significance in intimating that Christ, in becoming the
son of a carpenter and himself working as a carpenter,
showed merely that “there is nothing to be ashamed
of in seeking one’s bread by labor.” To say
that is almost like saying that by not robbing people he
showed that there is nothing to be ashamed of in honesty.
If you will consider how true in any large view is the
classification of all men into working-men, beggar-men
and thieves, you will see that it was morally impossible
that Christ during his stay on earth should have been
anything else than a working-man, since he who came to
fulfil the law must by deed as well as word obey
God’s law of labor.
See how fully and how beautifully Christ’s life
on earth illustrated this law. Entering our earthly life
in the weakness of infancy, as it is appointed that all
should enter it, he lovingly took what in the natural
order is lovingly rendered, the sustenance, secured by
labor, that one generation owes to its immediate
successors. Arrived at maturity, he earned his own
subsistence by that common labor in which the majority of
men must and do earn it. Then passing to a higher —
to the very highest — sphere of labor, he earned
his subsistence by the teaching of moral and spiritual
truths, receiving its material wages in the
love-offerings of grateful hearers, and not refusing the
costly spikenard with which Mary anointed his feet. So,
when he chose his disciples, he did not go to landowners
or other monopolists who live on the labor of others, but
to common laboring-men. And when he called them to a
higher sphere of labor and sent them out to teach moral
and spiritual truths, he told them to take, without
condescension on the one hand or sense of degradation on
the other, the loving return for such labor, saying to
them that “the laborer is worthy of his
hire,” thus showing, what we hold, that all labor
does not consist in what is called manual labor, but that
whoever helps to add to the material, intellectual, moral
or spiritual fullness of life is also a laborer.*
* Nor should it be forgotten that the
investigator, the philosopher, the teacher, the artist,
the poet, the priest, though not engaged in the
production of wealth, are not only engaged in the
production of utilities and satisfactions to which the
production of wealth is only a means, but by acquiring
and diffusing knowledge, stimulating mental powers and
elevating the moral sense, may greatly increase the
ability to produce wealth. For man does not live by
bread alone. . . . He who by any exertion of mind or
body adds to the aggregate of enjoyable wealth,
increases the sum of human knowledge, or gives to human
life higher elevation or greater fullness — he
is, in the large meaning of the words, a
“producer,” a “working-man,” a
“laborer,” and is honestly earning honest
wages. But he who without doing aught to make mankind
richer, wiser, better, happier, lives on the toil of
others — he, no matter by what name of honor he
may be called, or how lustily the priests of Mammon may
swing their censers before him, is in the last analysis
but a beggar-man or a thief. — Protection or
Free Trade, pp. 74-75.
In assuming that laborers, even ordinary manual
laborers, are naturally poor, you ignore the fact that
labor is the producer of wealth, and attribute to the
natural law of the Creator an injustice that comes from
man’s impious violation of his benevolent
intention. In the rudest stage of the arts it is
possible, where justice prevails, for all well men to
earn a living. With the labor-saving appliances of our
time, it should be possible for all to earn much more.
And so, in saying that poverty is no disgrace, you convey
an unreasonable implication. For poverty ought to be a
disgrace, since in a condition of social justice, it
would, where unsought from religious motives or unimposed
by unavoidable misfortune, imply recklessness or
laziness. ... read the whole
letter
Henry George: The
Wages of Labor
Thus Cain and Abel, were there only two men on
earth, might by agreement divide the earth between them.
Under this compact each might claim exclusive right to
his share as against the other. But neither could
rightfully continue such claim against the next child
born. For since no one comes into the world without God's
permission, his presence attests his equal right to the
use of God’s bounty. For them to refuse him any use
of the earth which they had divided between them would
therefore be for them to commit murder. And for them to
refuse him any use of the earth, unless by laboring for
them or by giving them part of the products of his labor
he bought It of them, would be for them to commit theft.
...
read the whole article
Henry George: Thou
Shalt Not Steal (1887 speech)
"Thou shalt not steal." That means, of course,
that we ourselves must not steal. But does it not also
mean that we must not suffer anybody else to steal if we
can help it?
"Thou shalt not steal." Does it not also mean:
"Thou shalt not suffer thyself or anybody else to be
stolen from?" If it does, then we, all of us, rich and
poor alike, are responsible for this social crime that
produces poverty. Not merely the people who monopolize
the land — they are not to blame above anyone else,
but we who permit them to monopolize land are also
parties to the theft.
The Christianity that ignores this social
responsibility has really forgotten the teachings of
Christ. Where He in the Gospels speaks
of the judgment, the question which is put to the people
is never, "Did you praise me?" "Did you pray to me?" "Did
you believe this or did you believe that?" It is only
this: "What did you do to relieve distress; to abolish
poverty?" To those who are condemned, the Judge is
represented as saying: "I was ahungered and ye gave me no
meat, I was athirst and ye gave me no drink, I was sick
and in prison and ye visited me not." Then they say,
"Lord, Lord, when did we fail to do these things to
thee?" The answer is: "Inasmuch as ye failed to do it to
the least of these, so also did ye fail to do it unto me;
depart into the place prepared for the devil and his
angels."
On the other hand, what is said to the blessed is:
"I was ahungered and ye gave me meat, I was thirsty and
ye gave me drink, I was naked and ye clothed me, I was
sick and in prison and ye visited me." And when they say:
"Lord, Lord, when did we do these things to thee?"
The answer is: "Inasmuch as ye have done
it unto the least of these my brethren, ye have done it
unto me."
Here is the essential spirit of
Christianity. The essence of its teaching is not "Provide
for your own body and save your own soul!" but "Do what
you can to make this world a better world for
all!" It was a protest against the doctrine of
"each for himself and the devil takes the hindermost!" It
was the proclamation of a common fatherhood of God and a
common brotherhood and sisterhood of men and women. This
was why the rich and powerful, the high priests and the
rulers persecuted Christianity with fire and sword.
It was not religion (what in so many of
our churches today is called religion) that pagan Rome
sought to tear out — it was the doctrine of the
equality of human rights!
Now imagine, when we men and women of today go
before that awful bar, that there we should behold the
spirits of those who in our time under this accursed
social system were driven into crime; of those who were
starved in body and mind; of those little children who,
in this city of New York, are being sent out of the world
by thousands when they have scarcely entered it —
because they do not get food enough, nor air enough;
because they are crowded together in these tenement
districts under conditions in which all diseases rage and
destroy.
Supposing we are confronted with those souls, what
will it avail us to say that we individually were not
responsible for their earthly conditions? What, in the
spirit of the parable of Matthew, would be the reply from
the Judgment seat? Would it not be: "I provided for them
all. The earth that I made was broad enough to give them
room. The materials that are placed in it were abundant
enough for all their needs. Did you or did you not lift
up your voice against the wrong that robbed them of their
fair share in the provision made for all?"
"Thou shalt not steal!" It is theft, it is robbery
that is producing poverty and disease and vice and crime
among us. It is by virtue of laws that we uphold; and
those who do not raise their voices against that crime,
they are accessories. The standard has now been raised,
the cross of the new crusade at last is lifted. Some of
us, aye, many of us, have sworn in our hearts that we
will never rest as long as we have life and strength
until we expose and abolish that wrong. We have declared
war upon it. Those who are not with us, let us count them
against us. For us there will be no faltering, no
compromise, no turning back until the end. ...
read
the whole article
Henry George: In
Liverpool: The Financial Reform Meeting at the Liverpool
Rotunda (1889)
He began as a protectionist. As he moved on he saw
that liberty meant something more than simply the
abolition of chattel slavery. He saw that liberty also
meant, not merely the right to freely labor for oneself,
but the right to freely exchange one's production, and,
from a protectionist, William Lloyd Garrison became a
free trader. (Cheers)
And now, when the first is gone, the second comes
forward, to take one further step to realize that for
perfect freedom there must also be freedom in the use of
natural opportunities. (Hear, hear, and cheers)
We have come . . . to the same point by converging
lines. Why is freedom of trade good? Simply that trade
— exchange — is but a mode of production.
Therefore, to secure full free trade we must also secure
freedom to the natural opportunities of production.
(Hear, hear) Our production—what is it? We produce
from what? From land. All human production consists but
in working up the raw materials that we find in nature
— consists simply in changing in place, or in form,
that matter which we call land. To free production there
must be no monopoly of the natural element. Even in our
methods we agree primarily on this essential point
— that everyone ought to be free to exert his
labor, to retain or to exchange its fruits, unhampered by
restrictions, unvexed by the tax gatherer. (Hear, hear) .
. .
Chattel slavery, thank God, is abolished at last.
Nowhere, where the American flag flies, can one man be
bought, or sold, or held by another. (Cheers) But a great
struggle still lies before us now. Chattel slavery is
gone; industrial slavery remains. The effort, the aim of
the abolitionists of this time is to abolish industrial
slavery. (Cheers)
The free trade movement in England was a necessary
step in this direction. The men who took part in it did
more than they knew. Striking at restrictions in the form
of protection, aiming at emancipating trade by reducing
tariffs to a minimum for revenue only, they aroused a
spirit that yet goes further. There sits, in the person
of my friend, Mr. Briggs [Thomas Briggs], one of the men
of that time, one of the men who, not stopping, has
always aimed a a larger freedom, one of the men who today
hails what we in the United States call the single tax
movement, as the natural outcome and successor of the
movement which Richard Cobden led.39 (A voice: "Three
cheers for Mr. Briggs," and cheers) ...
The People who say that such terrible things would
follow the institution of the single tax are simply like
the people who had predicted terrible things to follow
the building of railroads and the abolition of chattel
slavery. Why I remember, and Mr. Garrison well remembers,
the day when in the United States all the arguments that
are used in this country against the single tax were used
against the abolition of chattel slavery, even down to
the "poor widow argument."
We used to be told — I was only a boy then
— we used to be told, when William Lloyd Garrison,
father of this man, was the best denounced man on two
continents, that it might be well if we could find the
people who originally brought these slaves from Africa,
to make them give them up. "But," it was urged, "these
negroes are owned by people who paid their money for
them. (Laughter) Would you take away from a man without
any compensation the property that he bought?" (Laughter)
Then we used to be told, as you are told now, about that
hard working mechanic. "Here is a hard working laboring
man. He has toiled early and late, and he has bought a
slave to help him. Are you going to take a man's slave
without compensation and rob him of the products of his
labor?" (Laughter) So they say today of the English
mechanic, or English laborer, who has bought himself a
little bit of land. And then we used to be told: "Here is
a man who worked hard and saved his money, and he
invested in half-a-dozen slaves. He died, and those
slaves are the only means of subsistence the widow has to
support his orphan children. Would you emancipate those
slaves, and let that poor widow and those little orphans
starve to death?" (Laughter)
Slavery and Slavery
It is the old, old story! And no wonder, for property
in land is just as absurd! just as monstrous as property
in human beings. (Hear, hear, and cheers) What difference
does it make whether you enslave a man by making his
flesh and blood the property of another, or whether you
enslave him by making the property of another that
element on which and from which he must live if he is to
live at all? (A voice: "None whatever!" and cheers)
Why, in those old days slave ships used to set out
from this town of Liverpool for the coast of Africa to
buy slaves. They did not bring them to Liverpool; they
took them over to America. Why? Because you people were
so good, and the Englishmen who had got to the other side
of the Atlantic, and had settled there, were so bad? Not
at all. I will tell you why the Liverpool ships carried
slaves to America and did not bring them back to England.
Because in America population was sparse and land was
plentiful. Therefore to rob a man of his labor —
and that is what the slaveowner wanted the slave for
— you had got to catch and hold the man. That is
the reason the slaves went to America. The reason they
did not come here, the reason they were not carried over
to Ireland was that here population was relatively dense,
land was relatively scarce and could easily be
monopolized, and to get out of the laborer all that his
labor could furnish, save only wages enough to keep him
alive even the slaveowner had to give this — it was
only necessary to own land.
What is the difference, economically speaking, between
the slaves of South Carolina, Missouri, Mississippi, and
Georgia and the free peasantry of Ireland or the
agricultural laborer of England? (Cheers) Go to one of
those slave states in the slave days, and there you would
find a planter, the owner of five hundred slaves, living
in elegant luxury, without doing a stroke of work, having
a fine mansion, horses, [and a] carriage — all the
things that work produces, but doing none of it himself.
The people who did the work were living in negro huts, on
coarse food; they were clothed in coarse raiment. If they
ran away, he had the privilege of chasing them back,
tying them up and whipping them and making them work.
Come to this side of the Atlantic, in a place where
you saw the same state of development. There you found
also five hundred people living in little cabins, eating
coarse food, clothed in coarse raiment, working hard, yet
getting only enough of the things that work produces to
keep them in good times, when bad times came having to
appeal to the world for charity. But you found among
those little cabins, too, the lordly mansion of the man
who did no work. (Hear, hear, and groans)
You found the mansion; you did not often find the man.
(Laughter and cheers) As a general rule he was off in
London, or in Paris, enjoying himself on the fruits of
their labor. (Hear, hear) He had no legal right to make
them work for him. Oh! no. If they ran away he could not
put bloodhounds on their track and bring them back and
whip them; but he had, in hunger, in starvation, a ban
dog40 more swift, more keen, more sure than the
bloodhound of the south. (Cheers)
The slaveowner of the south — the owner of men
— had to make those men work for him. He went to
all that trouble. The landlord of Ireland did not have to
make men work for him. He owned the land, and without
land men cannot work; and so men would come to him
— equal children of the Creator, equal citizens of
Great Britain — would come to him, with their hats
in their hands, and beg to be allowed to live on his
land, to be allowed to work and to give to him all the
produce of their work, except enough to merely keep them
alive, and thank him for the privilege. . . . read the whole speech
Rev. A. C. Auchmuty: Gems from George, a themed
collection of excerpts from the writings of Henry
George (with links to sources)
THE term Labor includes all human exertion in the
production of wealth, whatever its mode. In common
parlance we often speak of brain labor and hand labor as
though they were entirely distinct kinds of exertion, and
labor is often spoken of as though it involved only
muscular exertion. But in reality any form of labor, that
is to say, any form of human exertion in the production
of wealth above that which cattle may be applied to
doing, requires the human brain as truly as the human
hand, and would be impossible without the exercise of
mental faculties on the part of the laborer. Labor in
fact is only physical in external form. In its origin it
is mental or on strict analysis spiritual. —
The Science of Political Economy
unabridged: Book III, Chapter 16: The Production of
Wealth, The Second Factor of Production — Labor
• abridged:
Part III, Chapter 10: Order of the Three Factors of
Production
IT seems to us that your Holiness misses its real
significance in intimating that Christ in becoming the
son of a carpenter and Himself working as a carpenter
showed merely that "there is nothing to be ashamed of in
seeking one's bread by labor." To say that is almost like
saying that by not robbing people He showed that there is
nothing to be ashamed of in honesty. If you will consider
how true in any large view is the classification of all
men into working-men, beggar-men and thieves, you will
see that it was morally impossible that Christ during His
stay on earth should have been anything else than a
working-man, since He who came to fulfill the law must by
deed as well as word obey God's law of labor.
See how fully and how beautifully Christ's life on earth
illustrated this law. Entering our earthly life in the
weakness of infancy, as it is appointed that all should
enter it, He lovingly took what in the natural order is
lovingly rendered, the sustenance, secured by labor, that
one generation owes to its immediate successors. Arrived
at maturity, He earned His own subsistence by that common
labor in which the majority of men must and do earn it.
Then passing to a higher — to the very
highest-sphere of labor. He earned His subsistence by the
teaching of moral and spiritual truths, receiving its
material wages in the love offerings of grateful hearers,
and not refusing the costly spikenard with which Mary
anointed his feet. So, when He chose His disciples, He
did not go to land-owners or other monopolists who live
on the labor of others but to common laboring men. And
when He called them to a higher sphere of labor and sent
them out to teach moral and spiritual truths He told them
to take, without condescension on the one hand, or sense
of degradation on the other, the loving return for such
labor, saying to them that the "laborer is worthy of his
hire," thus showing, what we hold, that all labor does
not consist in what is called manual labor, but that
whoever helps to add to the material, intellectual,
moral, or spiritual fulness of life is also a laborer. -
The Condition
of Labor
NOR should it be forgotten that the investigator, the
philosopher, the teacher, the artist, the poet, the
priest, though not engaged in the production of wealth,
are not only engaged in the production of utilities and
satisfactions to which the production of wealth is only a
means, but by acquiring and diffusing knowledge,
stimulating mental powers and elevating the moral sense,
may greatly increase the ability to produce wealth. For
man does not live by bread alone. He is not an engine, in
which so much fuel gives so much power. On a capstan bar
or a topsail halyard a good song tells like muscle, and a
"Marseillaise" or a "Battle Hymn of the Republic" counts
for bayonets. A hearty laugh, a noble thought, a
perception of harmony, may add to the power of dealing
even with material things.
He who by any exertion of mind or body adds to the
aggregate of enjoyable wealth, increases the sum of human
knowledge or gives to human life higher elevation or
greater fulness — he is, in the large meaning of
the words, a "producer," a "working-man," a "laborer,"
and is honestly earning honest wages. But he who without
doing aught to make mankind richer, wiser, better,
happier, lives on the toil of others — he, no
matter by what name of honor he may be I called, or how
lustily the priests of Mammon may swing their censers
before him, is in the last analysis but a beggarman or a
thief. — Protection or Free Trade, Chapter
7
econlib
THE poverty to which in advancing civilization great
masses of men are condemned, is not the freedom from
distraction and temptation which sages have sought and
philosophers have praised: it is a degrading and
embruting slavery, that cramps the higher nature, dulls
the finer feelings, and drives men by its pain to acts
which the brutes would refuse. It is into this helpless,
hopeless poverty, that crushes manhood and destroys
womanhood, that robs even childhood of its innocence and
joy, that the working classes are being driven by a force
which acts upon them like a resistless and unpitying
machine. The Boston collar manufacturer who pays his
girls two cents an hour may commiserate their condition,
but he, as they, is governed by the law of competition,
and cannot pay more and carry on his business, for
exchange is not governed by sentiment. And so, through
all intermediate gradations, up to those who receive the
earnings of labor without return, in the rent of land, it
is the inexorable laws of supply and demand, a power with
which the individual can no more quarrel or dispute than
with the winds and the tides, that seem to press down the
lower classes into the slavery of want.
But, in reality, the cause is that which always has, and
always must result in slavery — the monopolization
by some of what nature has designed for all. . . .
Private ownership of land is the nether millstone.
Material progress is the upper millstone. Between them;
with an increasing pressure, the working classes are
being ground. —
Progress & Poverty —
Book VII, Chapter 2, Justice of the Remedy: Enslavement
of laborers the ultimate result of private property in
land
IT is not in the relations of capital and labor; it is
not in the pressure of population against subsistence
that an explanation of the unequal development of our
civilization is to be found. The great cause of
inequality in the distribution of wealth is inequality in
the ownership of land. The ownership of land is the great
fundamental fact which ultimately determines the social,
the political and, consequently, the intellectual and
moral condition of a people. And it must be so. For land
is the habitation of man, the storehouse upon which he
must draw for all his needs, the material to which his
labor must be applied for the supply of all his desires;
for even the products of the sea cannot be taken, the
light of the sun enjoyed, or any of the forces of nature
utilized, without the use of land or its products. On the
land we are born, from it we live, to it we return again
— children of the soil as truly as is the blade of
grass or the flower of the field. —
Progress & Poverty
— Book V, Chapter 2: The Problem Solved: The
persistence of poverty amid advancing wealth
THERE is nothing strange or inexplicable in the phenomena
that are now perplexing the world. It is not that
material progress is not in itself a good, it is not that
nature has called into being children for whom she has
failed to provide; it is not that the Creator has left on
natural laws a taint of injustice at which even the human
mind revolts, that material progress brings such bitter
fruits. That amid our highest civilization men faint and
die with want is not due to the niggardliness of nature,
but to the injustice of man. Vice and misery, poverty and
pauperism, are not the legitimate results of increase of
population and industrial development; they only follow
increase of population and industrial development because
land is treated as private property — they are the
direct and necessary results of the violation of the
supreme law of justice, involved in giving to some men
the exclusive possession of that which nature provides
for all men. —
Progress & Poverty
— Book VII, Chapter 1, Justice of the Remedy:
Injustice of private property in land ... go to "Gems from
George"
Charles B. Fillebrown: A Catechism of Natural
Taxation, from Principles of Natural Taxation
(1917)
Q22. What is privilege?
A. Strictly defined, privilege is, according to the
Century Dictionary, "a special and exclusive power
conferred by law on particular persons or classes of
persons and ordinarily in derogation of the common
right."
Q23. What is today the popular conception of
privilege?
A. That it is the law-given power of one man to profit at
another man's expense.
Q24. What are the principal forms of
privilege?
A. The appropriation by individuals, or by public service
corporations, of the net rent of land created by the
growth and activity of the community without payment for
the same. Also, the less important privileges connected
with patents, tariff, and the currency.
Q25. Where in does privilege differ from
capital?
A. Capital is a material thing, a product of labor,
stored-up wages; an instrument of production paid for in
human labor, and destined to wear out. Capital is the
natural ally of labor, and is harmless except as allied
to privilege. Privilege is none of these, but is an
intangible statutory power, an unpaid-for and perpetual
lien upon the future labor of this and succeeding
generations. Capital is paid for and ephemeral. Privilege
is unpaid for and eternal. A man accumulated in his
profession $5,000 capital, which he invested in land in
Canada. Ten years later he sold the same land for
$200,000. Here is an instance of $5,000 capital allied
with $195,000 privilege. This illustrates that privilege
and not capital is the real enemy of labor.
Q26. How may franchises be treated?
A. Franchise privileges may be abated, or gradually
abolished by lower rates, or by taxation, or by both, in
the interest of the community.
Q27. Why should privilege be especially
taxed?
A. Because such payment is fairly due from grantee to the
grantor of privilege and also because a tax upon
privilege can never be a burden upon industry or
commerce, nor can it ever operate to reduce the wages of
labor or increase prices to the consumer.
Q28. How are landlords privileged?
A. Because, in so far as their land tax is an "old" tax,
it is a burdenless tax, and because their buildings' tax
is shifted upon their tenants; most landlords who let
land and also the tenement houses and business blocks
thereon avoid all share in the tax burden.
Q29. How does privilege affect the distribution of
wealth?
A. Wealth as produced is now distributed substantially in
but two channels, privilege and wages. The abolition of
privilege would leave but the one proper channel, viz.,
wages of capital, hand, and brain. ... read the whole
article
Lindy Davies: Land and Justice
We were talking about the tendency for landowners to
use land as an investment — a sensible thing to do
— not to use it now if they don't need to, but to
think in terms of enjoying its increase in value over
time. We even identified that as the key to the problem
of poverty. But — good heavens, what can we do
about that? Isn't that just how the economy works? Isn't
the private ownership of land a basic part of a modern
economy? How can we do without such an important
institution?
Or in other words — won't the poor always be
with us?
Not necessarily. It has been plain, since very
earliest days of civil society, that the private
ownership of land leads to exploitation and great
extremes of wealth and poverty. And, since the time of
the Book of Leviticus, we have had a pretty good idea of
what to do about it. In that book were recorded the words
"The land shall not be sold for ever, for the land is
Mine, for ye are strangers and sojourners with me."
This ideal was codified into a remarkable three-stage
program for economic justice and social harmony: the land
laws of Leviticus. The stages were:
1. The Sabbath. Every seventh day
was the Lord's day; people were enjoined to keep it
holy and refrain from work. Now, we were told in Sunday
school that this was all about going to church, but, as
so often happens, our teachers missed the deeper
significance. Kids who try to get out of, say, taking
out the garbage on the Sabbath realized that the
prohibition was really against gainful work; folks were
still allowed to weed the garden and stuff.
What the Sabbath did was to force people to focus on
things that had meaning beyond striving and striving to
get ahead. Indeed, if one did work on the Sabbath,
while one's neighbors did not, one could become
wealthier, at their expense — which was why the
Sabbath was a very big deal: one of the ten
commandments.
2. The Sabbatical. Every seventh year,
the fields were to lie fallow — thus recognizing
the right of the earth itself to be protected against
depletion and misuse. And, in the sabbatical year,
debts were to be forgiven. A debt that could not be
paid off after six years was well on the way to
becoming a usurious burden, a guaranteed flow from the
labors of one into the coffers of another. The
canceling of debts in the seventh year was designed to
ensure that nobody got too far ahead, or too far
behind.
3. The Jubilee. Even seven times seven
years (actually, every 50th year), each family could
return to its original allotment, or heritage, of land
— even if it had been sold in the meantime. Under
biblical law, then, land could not be sold for ever
— never for more than a single generation.
Now it is interesting to note that the economic vision
presented in the bible is not a precursor of communism.
Two of the ten commandments explicitly support the
institution of private property, and the prophets
consistently railed against landlords and rulers who
robbed the people of the fruits of their labor. The laws
of Leviticus, which Jesus said he "came not to destroy
but to fulfill," envisioned a community in which everyone
was secure in his own home and property, "beneath his
vine and fig tree".
(Incidentally, the quote on the American Liberty Bell,
from Leviticus, chapter 25, was a direct reference to
these principles : "Proclaim liberty throughout the land
and to all the people thereof." It was a reference to the
Jubilee, and the freedom it provided was from debt and
servitude.)
The division is clear: there is to be a sacred right
of private property in the things that are made by
people. But people were not to own the things that were
made by God. The 7th commandment sums up both principles
in 4 words: Thou shalt not steal.
Modern society has looked away from these principles,
calling them quaint, naive, inapplicable to the
complexities of our time — yet, modern society
finds itself mired in chronic economic and social
problems for which it can find no solutions — and
which threaten to pull down all the advances of
civilization into a dark age — occasioned by some
combination of war, financial implosion or ecological
collapse.
If there is any way out of this dark future, it can
only come by way of solving the problem of land and
justice.
Fortunately, there exists a plan for that.
This plan takes the shape of a "fiscal reform",
because it applies a definition of the relationship
between the individual and the society that is consistent
with both economic efficiency and moral law. It calls for
us to respect the right of labor to create and to save
wealth, and we acknowledge that the value of land is
created not by its “owners”, but by the
entire community.
Therefore, we will abolish all taxes on income,
products and sales — and collect the full rental
value of land and other natural resources for public
revenue. ... read the whole
speech
Bill Batt: The
Compatibility of Georgist Economics and Ecological
Economics
In the Georgist view, this economic
rent is the public’s birthright,47 and the failure to collect it and
to use it to pay for the general costs of government
services is a moral as well as a public policy lapse.
Georgists regard the private
confiscation of public wealth as mistaken policy if not
actually an immoral transgression — in a word,
theft! He himself was an advocate of the public
owning and protecting “the commons” and what
is today often called “natural capital.”
Studies have shown that if economic rent were collected
in full as well as other appropriate revenues such as
user fees and green taxes, the total income would likely
be enough to pay not only the costs of all government
services but provide a citizens’ dividend of
significant amounts as well.48 Statistical data is difficult to
compile, but what studies have been attempted to date
indicate that economic rent in all its forms and from all
its sources comprises approximately a third of the
economy as it is currently calculated.49 Arrangements such as these are to
the followers of Henry George a far more efficient and
moral system of public finance. ... read the whole
article
Weld Carter: An
Introduction to Henry George
The Ethics of Taxation
It was but a short step from the ethics of property to
the ethics of taxation. George's position here was that
as labor and capital rightfully and unconditionally own
what they produce, no one can rightfully appropriate any
of their earnings; nor can the State. On the other hand,
land value is always a socially created value, never the
result of action by the owner of the land. Therefore this
is a value that must be taken by society; otherwise,
those who comprise the social whole are deprived of what
is rightfully theirs. Furthermore, to charge the owner
for this value, in the form of taxation, is only to
collect from him the precise value of the benefit he
receives from society.
As to the justice of taxes on
products, George spoke of "...all taxes now levied on the
products and processes of industry -- which taxes, since
they take from the earnings of labor, we hold to be
infringements of the right of property."
Of the justice of
taxes on land values, he said, "Adam Smith speaks of
incomes as 'enjoyed under the protection of the state'; and
this is the ground upon which the equal taxation of all
species of property is commonly insisted upon -- that it is
equally protected by the state. The basis of this idea is
evidently that the enjoyment of property is made possible
by the state -- that there is a value created and
maintained by the community, which is justly called upon to
meet community expenses. Now of what values is this true?
Only of the value of land. This is a value that does not
arise until a community is formed, and that, unlike other
values, grows with the growth of the community. It exists
only as the community exists. Scatter again the largest
community, and land, now so valuable, would have no value
at all. With every increase of population the value of land
rises; with every decrease it falls. ...
"The tax upon land values is,
therefore, the most just and equal of all taxes. It falls
only upon those who receive from society a peculiar and
valuable benefit, and upon them in proportion to the
benefit they receive. It is the taking by the community,
for the use of the community, that value which is the
creation of the community. It is the application the common
property to common uses." ...read the
whole article
Robert H. Browne: Abraham Lincoln and the
Men of His Time
“Christ knew better than we that 'No man having
put his hand to the plow and looking back is fit for the
kingdom of God;' nor is many man doing his duty who
shrinks and is faithless to his fellow-men. Now a word
more about Abolitionists and new ideas in Government,
whatever they may be: We are all called Abolitionists now
who desire any restriction of slavery or believe that the
system is wrong, as I have declared for years. We are
called so, not to help out a peaceful solution, but in
derision, to abase us, and enable the defamers to make
successful combinations against us. I never was much
annoyed by these, less now than ever. I favor the best
plan to restrict the extension of slavery peacefully, and
fully believe that we must reach some plan that will do
it, and provide for some method of final extinction of
the evil, before we can have permanent peace on the
subject. On other questions there is ample room for
reform when the time comes; but now it would be folly to
think that we could undertake more than we have on hand.
But when slavery is over with and settled, men
should never rest content while oppressions, wrongs, and
iniquities are in force against them.
“The land, the earth that God gave to
man for his home, his sustenance, and support, should
never be the possession of any man, corporation, society,
or unfriendly Government, any more than the air or the
water, if as much. An individual company or enterprise
requiring land should hold no more in their own right
than is needed for their home and sustenance, and never
more than they have in actual use in the prudent
management of their legitimate business, and this much
should not be permitted when it creates an exclusive
monopoly. All that is not so used should be held for the
free use of every family to make homesteads, and to hold
them as long as they are so occupied.
“A reform like this will be worked out
some time in the future. The idle talk of foolish men,
that is so common now, on 'Abolitionists, agitators, and
disturbers of the peace,' will find its way against it,
with whatever force it may possess, and as strongly
promoted and carried on as it can be by land monopolists,
grasping landlords, and the titled and untitled senseless
enemies of mankind everywhere.” ...
read extended
excerpts
|
To share this page with a friend:
right click, choose "send," and add your
comments.
|
|
Red links have not been
visited; .
Green links are pages you've seen
|
Essential Documents pertinent
to this theme:
|
|