Inequality
"We hold these truths to be self-evident: that all men
are created equal..." How is it, that in a society
dedicated to such a proposition, we have such amazing
inequality of results and inequality of opportunity?
Income and wealth are both highly concentrated (though
not in precisely the same groups of people), and it is
difficult to reconcile that concentration with our
ideals.
Henry George sought
answers to the puzzle that confronted him in 1870s
America: why was it that, despite awesome increases in
technology, poverty was on the increase in America, and
why was it that poverty was largely an urban affair?
Since he made his observations and sought explanations,
our society has become far more urbanized, and technological progress
has spiraled upward and outward — and poverty has
become far more serious a problem, and concentration of
wealth and income has also increased precipitously.
If we want to understand why we have so much poverty,
we need to look beyond the au courant
explanations, and the "fences and small bandages" solutions
that we persist in applying.
Georgists do not seek equality of results; we do seek
genuine equality of opportunity, and we seek to end
systematic theft. We want to
create a society in which all of us have equal access to
natural opportunities, share in the natural resources our
soil and airwaves have to offer, and in which the social
surplus is shared among all of us equally. We see the
natural creation as legitimately common property, and
that which individuals create as legitimately private
property. We seek a society without privilege, a society
with no victims. And we know the first, most important
step for achieving that — something that most of
our greatgrandparents knew.
Henry George: Ode to
Liberty (1877 speech)
WE HONOR LIBERTY in name and in form. We set up
her statues and sound her praises. But we have not fully
trusted her. And with our growth so grow her demands. She
will have no half service! Liberty! it is a word to
conjure with, not to vex the ear in empty boastings. For
Liberty means Justice, and Justice is the natural law
— the law of health and symmetry and strength, of
fraternity and co-operation.
They who look upon Liberty as having
accomplished her mission when she has abolished
hereditary privileges and given men the ballot, who think
of her as having no further relations to the everyday
affairs of life, have not seen her real grandeur
— to them the poets who have sung of her must seem
rhapsodists, and her martyrs fools!
...
In our time, as in
times before, creep on the insidious forces that, producing
inequality, destroy Liberty. On the horizon the
clouds begin to lower. Liberty calls to us again. We must
follow her further; we must trust her fully. Either we must
wholly accept her or she will not stay. It
is not enough that men should vote; it is not enough that
they should be theoretically equal before the law. They
must have liberty to avail themselves of the opportunities
and means of life; they must stand on equal terms with
reference to the bounty of nature. Either this, or
Liberty withdraws her light! Either this, or darkness comes
on, and the very forces that progress has evolved turn to
powers that work destruction. This is the universal law.
This is the lesson of the centuries. Unless its foundations
be laid in justice the social structure cannot
stand.
Our primary social adjustment is
a denial of justice. In allowing one man to own the land
on which and from which other men must live, we have made
them his bondsmen in a degree which increases as material
progress goes on. This is the subtle alchemy that
in ways they do not realize is extracting from the masses
in every civilized country the fruits of their weary
toil; that is instituting a harder and more hopeless
slavery in place of that which has been destroyed; that
is bringing political despotism out of political freedom,
and must soon transmute democratic institutions into
anarchy....
read the whole speech
Fred Foldvary: Well being and being
well off
I see three ways in which one can define "well
off."
First, one is better or worse off
relative to the distribution of wealth or income in a
particular society. ...
Secondly, being well off can be
thought of as relative to the typical person in the
economy. ...
Third, one can define "well off" in
absolute terms. ...
Being absolutely well off
means,
- first, that one is able to rise substantially
above subsistence through peaceful and honest means,
whether from one's labor, from one's rightful share of
natural and contractual benefits, or from
gifts.
- Secondly, to be absolutely well off requires
complete liberty, so that the
only legal restriction is the prohibition of coercive
harm to others. Liberty includes security against attack,
either by government or by private persons, since one is
not really free if one is under substantial threats of
death and theft against which one is
helpless.
With liberty, one is free to establish
whatever relationships one wishes, so long as others are
also willing. With liberty and the ability to obtain
wealth, one can obtain assurance of future wealth both
because one is able to earn it and also because one is able
to store wealth and insure oneself against
risk.
My Dictionary of Free-Market Economics
defines "well-being" as "The amount and degree to which
individuals in an economy are able to pursue and attain
their ends." The only requirement for absolute well
being, for someone who is mentally and physically able to
produce wealth, is liberty. With liberty, one can
obtain wealth, friends, and future security, express
oneself as one pleases, and enjoy life in accord with one's
values and lifestyle preference.
Being absolutely well off does not
involve any particular level of wealth beyond subsistence,
since this depends on personal preference. An artist may
prefer to live at subsistence and devote her time to art,
and that person is absolutely well off because she is
pursuing happiness in her own way. As with relative well
being, one can be well off in the absolute sense without
being happy, as for example a person who has much wealth
but has lost love or has a serious illness.
What is required for
there to be complete liberty? There must be a basic
law such that any act that does not invade the domain of
others is not prohibited or taxed. In liberty, there are
only prohibitions if there are victims who are coercively
harmed, and there is restitution for damages to others. In
liberty, people have equal rights and no special legal
privileges. In a free society, nobody starves, because one
is able to save for the future, because on obtains one's
equal share of natural and civic benefits, and because the
sympathy of society will not let people starve.
The economic policy of liberty has
four rules:
- To the creator belongs the
creation.
- The profit of nature's creation belongs
equally to all.
- The benefit of what is created by government
belongs to all the people in its
jurisdiction.
- When the initial distribution is just, the
outcomes of free exchange are just and should not be
hampered. Read the whole
article
Peter Barnes:
Capitalism 3.0 — Chapter 5: Reinventing the Commons
(pages 65-78)
Thus far I’ve argued that Capitalism 2.0 —
or surplus capitalism — has three tragic flaws: it
devours nature, widens inequality, and fails to make us
happier in the end. It behaves this way because
it’s programmed to do so. It must make thneeds,
reward property owners disproportionately, and distract
us from truer paths to happiness because its algorithms
direct it to do so. Neither enlightened managers nor the
occasional zealous regulator can make it behave much
differently.
In this part of the book I advance a solution. The
essence of it is to fix capitalism’s operating
system by adding a commons sector to balance the
corporate sector. The new sector would supply virtuous
feedback loops and proxies for unrepresented
stakeholders: future generations, pollutees, and nonhuman
species. And would offset the corporate sector’s
negative externalities with positive externalities of
comparable magnitude. If the corporate sector devours
nature, the commons sector would protect it. If the
corporate sector widens inequality, the commons sector
would reduce it. If the corporate sector turns us into
self-obsessed consumers, the commons sector would
reconnect us to nature, community, and culture. All this
would happen automatically once the commons sector is set
up. The result would be a balanced economy that gives us
the best of both sectors and the worst of neither. ...
read the whole chapter
Peter Barnes:
Capitalism 3.0 — Chapter 7: Universal Birthrights
(pages 101-116)
The Idea of Birthrights
John Locke’s response to royalty’s claim
of divine right was the idea of everyone’s inherent
right to life, liberty, and
property. Thomas Jefferson, in drafting
America’s Declaration of Independence, changed
Locke’s trinity to life, liberty, and
the pursuit of happiness. These, Jefferson
and his collaborators agreed, are gifts from the creator
that can’t be taken away. Put slightly differently,
they’re universal
birthrights.
The Constitution and its amendments added meat to
these elegant bones. They guaranteed such birthrights as
free speech, due process, habeas corpus, speedy public
trials, and secure homes and property. Wisely, the Ninth
Amendment affirmed that “the enumeration in the
Constitution, of certain rights, shall not be construed
to deny or disparage others retained by the
people.” In that spirit, others have since been
added.
If we were to analyze the expansion of American
birthrights, we’d see a series of waves. The first
wave consisted of rights against the state. The second
included rights against unequal treatment based on race,
nationality, gender, or sexual orientation. The third
wave — which, historically speaking, is just
beginning — consists of rights not against
things, but for things — free public
education, collective bargaining for wages, security in
old age. They can be thought of as rights necessary for
the pursuit of happiness.
What makes this latest wave of birthrights strengthen
community is their universality. If some Americans could
enjoy free public education while others couldn’t,
the resulting inequities would divide rather than unite
us as a nation. The universality of these rights puts
everyone in the same boat. It spreads risk,
responsibility, opportunity, and reward across race,
gender, economic classes, and generations. It makes us a
nation rather than a collection of isolated
individuals.
Universality is also what distinguishes the commons
sector from the corporate sector. The starting condition
for the corporate sector, as we’ve seen, is that
the top 5 percent owns more shares than everyone else.
The starting condition for the commons sector, by
contrast, is one person, one share.
The standard argument against third wave universal
birthrights is that, while they might be nice in theory,
in practice they are too expensive. They impose an
unbearable burden on “the economy” —
that is, on the winners in unfettered markets. Much
better, therefore, to let everyone — including poor
children and the sick — fend for themselves. In
fact, the opposite is often true: universal birthrights,
as we’ll see, can be cheaper and more efficient
than individual acquisition. Moreover, they are always
fairer.
How far we might go down the path of extending
universal birthrights is anyone’s guess, but
we’re now at the point where, economically
speaking, we can afford to go farther. Without great
difficulty, we could add three birthrights to our
economic operating system: one would pay everyone a
regular dividend, the second would give every child a
start-up stake, and the third would reduce and share
medical costs. Whether we add these birthrights or not
isn’t a matter of economic ability, but of attitude
and politics.
Why attitude? Americans suffer from a number of
confusions. We think it’s “wrong” to
give people “something for nothing,” despite
the fact that corporations take common wealth for nothing
all the time. We believe the poor are poor and the rich
are rich because they deserve to be, but don’t
consider that millions of Americans work two or three
jobs and still can’t make ends meet. Plus, we think
tinkering with the “natural” distribution of
income is “socialism,” or “big
government,” or some other manifestation of evil,
despite the fact that our current distribution of income
isn’t “natural” at all, but rigged from
the get-go by maldistributed property.
The late John Rawls, one of America’s leading
philosophers, distinguished between
pre distribution of property
and re distribution of income.
Under income re distribution, money is taken from
“winners” and transferred to
“losers.” Understandably, this isn’t
popular with winners, who tend to control government and
the media. Under property pre
distribution, by contrast, the playing field is leveled
by spreading property ownership before income is
generated. After that, there’s no need for income
redistribution; property itself distributes income to
all. According to Rawls, while income re distribution
creates dependency, property predistribution
empowers.
But how can we spread property ownership without
taking property from some and giving it to others? The
answer lies in the commons — wealth that already
belongs to everyone. By propertizing (without
privatizing) some of that wealth, we can make everyone a
property owner.
What’s interesting is that, for purely
ecological reasons, we need to
propertize (without privatizing) some natural wealth now.
This twenty-first century necessity means we have a
chance to save the planet, and as a bonus, add a
universal birthright. ...
read the whole chapter
Henry George: The Condition of Labor
— An Open Letter to Pope Leo XIII in response to
Rerum Novarum (1891)
Nor do we hesitate to say that this way of securing
the equal right to the bounty of the Creator and the
exclusive right to the products of labor is the way
intended by God for raising public revenues. For we are
not atheists, who deny God; nor semi-atheists, who deny
that he has any concern in politics and legislation.
It is true as you say — a salutary truth too
often forgotten — that “man is older than the
state, and he holds the right of providing for the life
of his body prior to the formation of any state.”
Yet, as you too perceive, it is also true that the state
is in the divinely appointed order. For He who foresaw
all things and provided for all things, foresaw and
provided that with the increase of population and the
development of industry the organization of human society
into states or governments would become both expedient
and necessary.
No sooner does the state arise than, as we all know,
it needs revenues. This need for revenues is small at
first, while population is sparse, industry rude and the
functions of the state few and simple. But with growth of
population and advance of civilization the functions of
the state increase and larger and larger revenues are
needed.
Now, He that made the world and placed man in it, He
that pre-ordained civilization as the means whereby man
might rise to higher powers and become more and more
conscious of the works of his Creator, must have foreseen
this increasing need for state revenues and have made
provision for it. That is to say: The increasing need for
public revenues with social advance, being a natural,
God-ordained need, there must be a right way of raising
them — some way that we can truly say is the way
intended by God. It is clear that this right way of
raising public revenues must accord with the moral
law.
Hence:
It must not take from individuals what rightfully
belongs to individuals.
It must not give some an advantage over others, as by
increasing the prices of what some have to sell and
others must buy.
It must not lead men into temptation, by requiring
trivial oaths, by making it profitable to lie, to swear
falsely, to bribe or to take bribes.
It must not confuse the distinctions of right and
wrong, and weaken the sanctions of religion and the state
by creating crimes that are not sins, and punishing men
for doing what in itself they have an undoubted right to
do.
It must not repress industry. It must not check
commerce. It must not punish thrift. It must offer no
impediment to the largest production and the fairest
division of wealth.
Let me ask your Holiness to consider the taxes on the
processes and products of industry by which through the
civilized world public revenues are collected — the
octroi duties that surround Italian cities with barriers;
the monstrous customs duties that hamper intercourse
between so-called Christian states; the taxes on
occupations, on earnings, on investments, on the building
of houses, on the cultivation of fields, on industry and
thrift in all forms. Can these be the ways God has
intended that governments should raise the means they
need? Have any of them the characteristics indispensable
in any plan we can deem a right one?
All these taxes violate the moral law. They take by
force what belongs to the individual alone; they give to
the unscrupulous an advantage over the scrupulous; they
have the effect, nay are largely intended, to increase
the price of what some have to sell and others must buy;
they corrupt government; they make oaths a mockery; they
shackle commerce; they fine industry and thrift; they
lessen the wealth that men might enjoy, and enrich some
by impoverishing others.
Yet what most strikingly shows how opposed to
Christianity is this system of raising public revenues is
its influence on thought.
Christianity teaches us that all men are brethren;
that their true interests are harmonious, not
antagonistic. It gives us, as the golden rule of life,
that we should do to others as we would have others do to
us. But out of the system of taxing the products and
processes of labor, and out of its effects in increasing
the price of what some have to sell and others must buy,
has grown the theory of “protection,” which
denies this gospel, which holds Christ ignorant of
political economy and proclaims laws of national
well-being utterly at variance with his teaching. This
theory sanctifies national hatreds; it inculcates a
universal war of hostile tariffs; it teaches peoples that
their prosperity lies in imposing on the productions of
other peoples restrictions they do not wish imposed on
their own; and instead of the Christian doctrine of
man’s brotherhood it makes injury of foreigners a
civic virtue.
“By their fruits ye shall know them.” Can
anything more clearly show that to tax the products and
processes of industry is not the way God intended public
revenues to be raised?
But to consider what we propose — the raising of
public revenues by a single tax on the value of land
irrespective of improvements — is to see that in
all respects this does conform to the moral law.
Let me ask your Holiness to keep in mind that the
value we propose to tax, the value of land irrespective
of improvements, does not come from any exertion of labor
or investment of capital on or in it — the values
produced in this way being values of improvement which we
would exempt. The value of land irrespective of
improvement is the value that attaches to land by reason
of increasing population and social progress. This is a
value that always goes to the owner as owner, and never
does and never can go to the user; for if the user be a
different person from the owner he must always pay the
owner for it in rent or in purchase-money; while if the
user be also the owner, it is as owner, not as user, that
he receives it, and by selling or renting the land he
can, as owner, continue to receive it after he ceases to
be a user.
Thus, taxes on land irrespective of improvement cannot
lessen the rewards of industry, nor add to prices,* nor
in any way take from the individual what belongs to the
individual. They can take only the value that attaches to
land by the growth of the community, and which therefore
belongs to the community as a whole.
* As to this point it may be well to add
that all economists are agreed that taxes on land
values irrespective of improvement or use — or
what in the terminology of political economy is styled
rent, a term distinguished from the ordinary use of the
word rent by being applied solely to payments for the
use of land itself — must be paid by the owner
and cannot be shifted by him on the user. To explain in
another way the reason given in the text: Price is not
determined by the will of the seller or the will of the
buyer, but by the equation of demand and supply, and
therefore as to things constantly demanded and
constantly produced rests at a point determined by the
cost of production — whatever tends to increase
the cost of bringing fresh quantities of such articles
to the consumer increasing price by checking supply,
and whatever tends to reduce such cost decreasing price
by increasing supply. Thus taxes on wheat or tobacco or
cloth add to the price that the consumer must pay, and
thus the cheapening in the cost of producing steel
which improved processes have made in recent years has
greatly reduced the price of steel. But land has no
cost of production, since it is created by God, not
produced by man. Its price therefore is fixed
—
1 (monopoly rent), where land is held
in close monopoly, by what the owners can extract
from the users under penalty of deprivation and
consequently of starvation, and amounts to all that
common labor can earn on it beyond what is necessary
to life;
2 (economic rent proper), where there is no special
monopoly, by what the particular land will yield to
common labor over and above what may be had by like
expenditure and exertion on land having no special
advantage and for which no rent is paid; and,
3 (speculative rent, which is a species of monopoly
rent, telling particularly in selling price), by the
expectation of future increase of value from social
growth and improvement, which expectation causing
landowners to withhold land at present prices has the
same effect as combination.
Taxes on land values or economic rent
can therefore never be shifted by the landowner to the
land-user, since they in no wise increase the demand
for land or enable landowners to check supply by
withholding land from use. Where rent depends on mere
monopolization, a case I mention because rent may in
this way be demanded for the use of land even before
economic or natural rent arises, the taking by taxation
of what the landowners were able to extort from labor
could not enable them to extort any more, since
laborers, if not left enough to live on, will die. So,
in the case of economic rent proper, to take from the
landowners the premiums they receive, would in no way
increase the superiority of their land and the demand
for it. While, so far as price is affected by
speculative rent, to compel the landowners to pay taxes
on the value of land whether they were getting any
income from it or not, would make it more difficult for
them to withhold land from use; and to tax the full
value would not merely destroy the power but the desire
to do so.
To take land values for the state, abolishing all
taxes on the products of labor, would therefore leave to
the laborer the full produce of labor; to the individual
all that rightfully belongs to the individual. It would
impose no burden on industry, no check on commerce, no
punishment on thrift; it would secure the largest
production and the fairest distribution of wealth, by
leaving men free to produce and to exchange as they
please, without any artificial enhancement of prices; and
by taking for public purposes a value that cannot be
carried off, that cannot be hidden, that of all values is
most easily ascertained and most certainly and cheaply
collected, it would enormously lessen the number of
officials, dispense with oaths, do away with temptations
to bribery and evasion, and abolish man-made crimes in
themselves innocent.
But, further: That God has intended the state to
obtain the revenues it needs by the taxation of land
values is shown by the same order and degree of evidence
that shows that God has intended the milk of the mother
for the nourishment of the babe.
See how close is the analogy. In that primitive
condition ere the need for the state arises there are no
land values. The products of labor have value, but in the
sparsity of population no value as yet attaches to land
itself. But as increasing density of population and
increasing elaboration of industry necessitate the
organization of the state, with its need for revenues,
value begins to attach to land. As population still
increases and industry grows more elaborate, so the needs
for public revenues increase. And at the same time and
from the same causes land values increase. The connection
is invariable. The value of things produced by labor
tends to decline with social development, since the
larger scale of production and the improvement of
processes tend steadily to reduce their cost. But the
value of land on which population centers goes up and up.
Take Rome or Paris or London or New York or Melbourne.
Consider the enormous value of land in such cities as
compared with the value of land in sparsely settled parts
of the same countries. To what is this due? Is it not due
to the density and activity of the populations of those
cities — to the very causes that require great
public expenditure for streets, drains, public buildings,
and all the many things needed for the health,
convenience and safety of such great cities? See how with
the growth of such cities the one thing that steadily
increases in value is land; how the opening of roads, the
building of railways, the making of any public
improvement, adds to the value of land. Is it not clear
that here is a natural law — that is to say a
tendency willed by the Creator? Can it mean anything else
than that He who ordained the state with its needs has in
the values which attach to land provided the means to
meet those needs?
That it does mean this and nothing else is confirmed
if we look deeper still, and inquire not merely as to the
intent, but as to the purpose of the intent. If we do so
we may see in this natural law by which land values
increase with the growth of society not only such a
perfectly adapted provision for the needs of society as
gratifies our intellectual perceptions by showing us the
wisdom of the Creator, but a purpose with regard to the
individual that gratifies our moral perceptions by
opening to us a glimpse of his beneficence.
Consider: Here is a natural law by which as society
advances the one thing that increases in value is land
— a natural law by virtue of which all growth of
population, all advance of the arts, all general
improvements of whatever kind, add to a fund that both
the commands of justice and the dictates of expediency
prompt us to take for the common uses of society. Now,
since increase in the fund available for the common uses
of society is increase in the gain that goes equally to
each member of society, is it not clear that the law by
which land values increase with social advance while the
value of the products of labor does not increase, tends
with the advance of civilization to make the share that
goes equally to each member of society more and more
important as compared with what goes to him from his
individual earnings, and thus to make the advance of
civilization lessen relatively the differences that in a
ruder social state must exist between the strong and the
weak, the fortunate and the unfortunate? Does it
not show the purpose of the Creator to be that the
advance of man in civilization should be an advance not
merely to larger powers but to a greater and greater
equality, instead of what we, by our ignoring of his
intent, are making it, an advance toward a more and more
monstrous inequality? ...
That the value attaching to land with social growth is
intended for social needs is shown by the final proof.
God is indeed a jealous God in the sense that nothing but
injury and disaster can attend the effort of men to do
things other than in the way he has intended; in the
sense that where the blessings he proffers to men are
refused or misused they turn to evils that scourge us.
And just as for the mother to withhold the provision that
fills her breast with the birth of the child is to
endanger physical health, so for society to refuse to
take for social uses the provision intended for them is
to breed social disease.
For refusal to take for public purposes the increasing
values that attach to land with social growth is to
necessitate the getting of public revenues by taxes that
lessen production, distort distribution and corrupt
society. It is to leave some to take what justly
belongs to all; it is to forego the only means
by which it is possible in an advanced civilization to
combine the security of possession that is necessary to
improvement with the equality of natural opportunity that
is the most important of all natural rights. It
is thus at the basis of all social life to set up an
unjust inequality between man and man, compelling some to
pay others for the privilege of living, for the chance of
working, for the advantages of civilization, for the
gifts of their God. But it is even more than
this. The very robbery that the masses of men
thus suffer gives rise in advancing communities to a new
robbery. For the value that with the increase of
population and social advance attaches to land being
suffered to go to individuals who have secured ownership
of the land, it prompts to a forestalling of and
speculation in land wherever there is any prospect of
advancing population or of coming improvement, thus
producing an artificial scarcity of the natural elements
of life and labor, and a strangulation of production that
shows itself in recurring spasms of industrial depression
as disastrous to the world as destructive wars. It is
this that is driving men from the old countries to the
new countries, only to bring there the same curses. It is
this that causes our material advance not merely to fail
to improve the condition of the mere worker, but to make
the condition of large classes positively worse. It is
this that in our richest Christian countries is giving us
a large population whose lives are harder, more hopeless,
more degraded than those of the veriest savages. It is
this that leads so many men to think that God is a
bungler and is constantly bringing more people into his
world than he has made provision for; or that there is no
God, and that belief in him is a superstition which the
facts of life and the advance of science are
dispelling.
... read
the whole letter
|
To share this page with a friend:
right click, choose "send," and add your
comments.
|
|
Red links have not been
visited; .
Green links are pages you've seen
|
Essential Documents pertinent
to this theme:
|
|