Tollgates and Tollpayers
Henry George: The Condition of
Labor — An Open Letter to Pope Leo XIII in response
to Rerum Novarum (1891)
You assume that the labor question is a question
between wage-workers and their employers. But working for
wages is not the primary or exclusive occupation of
labor. Primarily men work for themselves without the
intervention of an employer. And the primary source of
wages is in the earnings of labor, the man who works for
himself and consumes his own products receiving his wages
in the fruits of his labor. Are not fishermen, boatmen,
cab-drivers, peddlers, working farmers — all, in
short, of the many workers who get their wages directly
by the sale of their services or products without the
medium of an employer, as much laborers as those who work
for the specific wages of an employer? In your
consideration of remedies you do not seem even to have
thought of them. Yet in reality the laborers who work for
themselves are the first to be considered, since what men
will be willing to accept from employers depends
manifestly on what they can get by working for
themselves.
You assume that all employers are rich men, who might
raise wages much higher were they not so grasping. But is
it not the fact that the great majority of employers are
in reality as much pressed by competition as their
workmen, many of them constantly on the verge of failure?
Such employers could not possibly raise the wages they
pay, however they might wish to, unless all others were
compelled to do so.
You assume that there are in the natural order two
classes, the rich and the poor, and that laborers
naturally belong to the poor.
It is true as you say that there are differences in
capacity, in diligence, in health and in strength, that
may produce differences in fortune. These, however, are
not the differences that divide men into rich and poor.
The natural differences in powers and aptitudes are
certainly not greater than are natural differences in
stature. But while it is only by selecting giants and
dwarfs that we can find men twice as tall as others, yet
in the difference between rich and poor that exists today
we find some men richer than other men by the
thousandfold and the millionfold.
Nowhere do these differences between wealth
and poverty coincide with differences in individual
powers and aptitudes. The real difference between rich
and poor is the difference between those who hold the
tollgates and those who pay toll; between
tribute-receivers and tribute-yielders.
In what way does nature justify such a difference? In
the numberless varieties of animated nature we find some
species that are evidently intended to live on other
species. But their relations are always marked by
unmistakable differences in size, shape or organs. To man
has been given dominion over all the other living things
that tenant the earth. But is not this mastery indicated
even in externals, so that no one can fail on sight to
distinguish between a man and one of the inferior
animals? Our American apologists for slavery used
to contend that the black skin and woolly hair of the
negro indicated the intent of nature that the black
should serve the white; but the difference that you
assume to be natural is between men of the same race.
What difference does nature show between such men as
would indicate her intent that one should live idly yet
be rich, and the other should work hard yet be
poor? If I could bring you from the United
States a man who has $200,000,000, and one who is glad to
work for a few dollars a week, and place them side by
side in your antechamber, would you be able to tell which
was which, even were you to call in the most skilled
anatomist? Is it not clear that God in no way
countenances or condones the division of rich and poor
that exists today, or in any way permits it, except as
having given them free will he permits men to choose
either good or evil, and to avoid heaven if they prefer
hell. For is it not clear that the division of
men into the classes rich and poor has invariably its
origin in force and fraud; invariably involves violation
of the moral law; and is really a division into those who
get the profits of robbery and those who are robbed;
those who hold in exclusive possession what God made for
all, and those who are deprived of his bounty?
Did not Christ in all his utterances and parables show
that the gross difference between rich and poor is
opposed to God’s law? Would he have condemned the
rich so strongly as he did, if the class distinction
between rich and poor did not involve injustice —
was not opposed to God’s intent?
...
If when in speaking of the practical measures your
Holiness proposes, I did not note the moral injunctions
that the Encyclical contains, it is not because we do not
think morality practical. On the contrary it seems to us
that in the teachings of morality is to be found the
highest practicality, and that the question, What is
wise? may always safely be subordinated to the question,
What is right? But your Holiness in the Encyclical
expressly deprives the moral truths you state of all real
bearing on the condition of labor, just as the American
people, by their legalization of chattel slavery, used to
deprive of all practical meaning the declaration they
deem their fundamental charter, and were accustomed to
read solemnly on every national anniversary. That
declaration asserts that “We hold these truths to
be self-evident — that all men are created equal;
that they are endowed by their Creator with certain
unalienable rights; that among these are life, liberty,
and the pursuit of happiness.” But what did this
truth mean on the lips of men who asserted that one man
was the rightful property of another man who had bought
him; who asserted that the slave was robbing the master
in running away, and that the man or the woman who helped
the fugitive to escape, or even gave him a cup of cold
water in Christ’s name, was an accessory to theft,
on whose head the penalties of the state should be
visited?
Consider the moral teachings of the Encyclical:
- You tell us that God owes to man an
inexhaustible storehouse which he finds only in the
land. Yet you support a system that denies to the great
majority of men all right of recourse to this
storehouse.
- You tell us that the necessity of labor is
a consequence of original sin. Yet you support a system
that exempts a privileged class from the necessity for
labor and enables them to shift their share and much
more than their share of labor on others.
- You tell us that God has not created us for
the perishable and transitory things of earth, but has
given us this world as a place of exile and not as our
true country. Yet you tell us that some of the exiles
have the exclusive right of ownership in this place of
common exile, so that they may compel their
fellow-exiles to pay them for sojourning here, and that
this exclusive ownership they may transfer to other
exiles yet to come, with the same right of excluding
their fellows.
- You tell us that virtue is the common
inheritance of all; that all men are children of God
the common Father; that all have the same last end;
that all are redeemed by Jesus Christ; that the
blessings of nature and the gifts of grace belong in
common to all, and that to all except the unworthy is
promised the inheritance of the Kingdom of Heaven! Yet
in all this and through all this you insist as a moral
duty on the maintenance of a system that makes the
reservoir of all God’s material bounties and
blessings to man the exclusive property of a few of
their number — you give us equal rights in
heaven, but deny us equal rights on
earth!
It was said of a famous decision of the Supreme Court
of the United States made just before the civil war, in a
fugitive-slave case, that “it gave the law to the
North and the nigger to the South.” It is thus that
your Encyclical gives the gospel to laborers and the
earth to the landlords. Is it really to be wondered at
that there are those who sneeringly say, “The
priests are ready enough to give the poor an equal share
in all that is out of sight, but they take precious good
care that the rich shall keep a tight grip on all that is
within sight”? ... read the whole
letter
Rev. A. C. Auchmuty: Gems
from George, a themed collection of excerpts from the
writings of Henry George (with links to sources)
IF we are all here by the equal permission of the
Creator, we are all here with an equal title to the
enjoyment of His bounty — with an equal right to
the use of all that nature so impartially offers. This is
a right which is natural and inalienable; it is a right
which vests in every human being as he enters the world,
and which, during his continuance in the world, can be
limited only by the equal rights of others. There is in
nature no such thing as a fee simple in land. There is on
earth no power which can rightfully make a grant of
exclusive ownership in land. If all existing men were to
unite to grant away their equal rights, they could not
grant away the right of those who follow them. For what
are we but tenants for a day? Have we made the earth that
we should determine the rights of those who after us
shall tenant it in their turn? The Almighty, who created
the earth for man and man for the earth, has entailed it
upon all the generations of the children of men by a
decree written upon the constitution of all things
— a decree which no human action can bar and no
prescription determine, Let the parchments be ever so
many, or possession ever so long, natural justice can
recognize no right in one man to the possession and
enjoyment of land that is not equally the right of all
his fellows. —
Progress & Poverty
— Book VII, Chapter 1, Justice of the Remedy:
Injustice of private property in land
HAS the first comer at a banquet the right to turn
back all the chairs and claim that none of the other
guests shall partake of the food provided, except as they
make terms with him? Does the first man who presents a
ticket at the door of a theater and passes in, acquire by
his priority the right to shut the doors and have the
performance go on for him alone? Does the first passenger
who enters a railroad car obtain the right to scatter his
baggage over all the seats and compel the passengers who
come in after him to stand up?
The cases are perfectly analogous. We arrive and we
depart, guests at a banquet continually spread,
spectators and participants in an entertainment where
there is room for all who come; passengers from station
to station, on an orb that whirls through space —
our rights to take and possess cannot be exclusive; they
must be bounded everywhere by the equal rights of others.
Just as the passenger in a railroad car may spread
himself and his baggage over as many seats as he pleases,
until other passengers come in, so may a settler take and
use as much land as he chooses, until it is needed by
others — a fact which is shown by the land
acquiring a value — when his right must be
curtailed by the equal rights of the others, and no
priority of appropriation can give a right which will bar
these equal rights of others. —
Progress & Poverty
— Book VII, Chapter 1, Justice of the Remedy:
Injustice of private property in land ...
GREAT as John Stuart Mill was and pure as he was
— warm heart and noble mind — he yet never
saw the true harmony of economic laws, nor realized how
from this one great fundamental wrong flow want and
misery, and vice and shame. Else he could never have
written this sentence: "The land of Ireland, the land of
every country, belongs to the people of that country. The
individuals called landowners have no right in morality
and justice to anything but the rent, or compensation for
its salable value."
In the name of the Prophet — figs! If the land of
any country belong to the people of that country, what
right, in morality and justice, have the individuals
called landowners to the rent? If the land belong to the
people, why in the name of morality and justice should
the people pay its salable value for their own?
Herbert Spencer says: "Had we to deal with the parties
who originally robbed the human race of its heritage, we
might make short work of the matter?" Why not make short
work of the matter anyhow? For this robbery is not like
the robbery of a horse or a sum of money, that ceases
with the act. It is a fresh and continuous robbery, that
goes on every day and every hour. It is not from the
produce of the past that rent is drawn; it is from the
produce of the present. It is a toll levied upon labor
constantly and continuously. Every blow of the hammer,
every stroke of the pick, every thrust of the shuttle,
every throb of the steam engine pay it tribute. It levies
upon the earnings of the men who, deep underground, risk
their lives, and of those who over white surges hang to
reeling masts; it claims the just reward of the
capitalist and the fruits of the inventor's patient
effort; it takes little children from play and from
school, and compels them to work before their bones are
hard or their muscles are firm; it robs the shivering of
warmth; the hungry, of food; the sick, of medicine; the
anxious, of peace. It debases, and embrutes, and
embitters. —
Progress & Poverty
— Book VII, Chapter 3, Justice of the Remedy: Claim
of Landowners to Compensation ...
go to "Gems from George"
Arthur J. Ogilvy: A Colonist's Plea
for Land Nationalization (about 1890)
If I sell goods or perform work for another, then no
matter how high I may charge for the goods or the work, I
am rendering goods for goods, service for service,
earnings for earnings. What I offer is my labour, or the
fruits of it, and as the public are free to get the same
goods or services elsewhere if my terms don't suit, or to
go without them, the fact of their accepting my terms
shows that the thing I offer is, under the circumstances,
worth the money.
But in the case of this unearned increment on land there
is no pretence of any exchange. I offer for it neither
labour nor the produce of labour. All I do is to place my
hand on a certain portion of the earth's surface, and
say, "No one shall use this without paying me for the
mere permission to use it." I am rendering no more
service in return for this extra pound, either to the
purchaser or to society, than if I had acquired exclusive
title to the air, and charged people for permission to
breathe. And if, instead of selling my land for an
additional pound, I let it at a proportionately
additional rent the principle would be the same.
The increase of value in my land has arisen from the
execution of public works and increase of population,
causing an increased demand for the land; in other words,
it has arisen from the national progress; and I, so far
from aiding in this progress have actually hindered it,
by keeping my property locked up and so forcing on
intending producers to inferior or less accessible lands;
and by holding so much land back have helped to make land
so much scarcer, and, therefore, so much dearer, and so
have helped to increase the tribute which industry has to
pay to monopoly for the mere privilege of exerting
itself. ...
Whether the value of land and the value of the
improvements can be separated or not, they are quite
distinct elements, just as in a glass of grog, the brandy
is brandy and the water water, each with its own
distinctive properties and effects, notwithstanding their
indistinguishable com-mixture; and he therefore who lets
land levies blackmail upon industry by charging for
something which represents no service at all, none the
less that at the same time he charges for something else
that does represent service.
No doubt there are many other things besides land in
which a monopoly of the article will enable the possessor
to levy something resembling blackmail; but there are
points of difference that distinguish them all from the
pure and simple appropriation of land monopoly.
...
But it ought to be clear by this time that if all
existing landlords were swept away and all the land in
use confirmed absolutely upon the occupiers, things would
be no better than they are now.
For the evil that weighs upon society, hindering
progress, forcing down earnings, and making life to all
who have to live by work a struggle for existence is the
monopoly of the land; and whether it is A or B who
monopolises it, is of no consequence to anybody but A and
B.
Wherever one man is allowed to acquire more land than he
can use by his own labour for the purpose of preventing
other people from using it by their labour except for his
profit, that man is master of the situation, and the
class of which he is the representative has the world at
its feet. And whether the monopolist turns his monopoly
to account as an occupying owner by working the labourers
for his profit directly, or as a nonoccupier by selling
to somebody else (called a tenant) for a yearly payment
(called rent) the privilege of working them, is a
difference not worth talking about. ...
I have employed my land not as an instrument of
production, but as a means of extortion. I have bought
it, not to use but to prevent other people from using it
without my purchased leave; not to earn anything by it
but to obtain the power of demanding the earnings of
others.
Suppose certain parties, knowing that a road would
shortly be made into a particular region, bought from
Government the privilege of placing bars across the road
(when made) and forbidding anybody to pass until he had
paid toll; toll not (as under the old State tolls) to pay
for the maintenance of the road, but toll for the mere
permission to pass along the road. Every one would
recognise that this toll was pure blackmail and not
earnings, and the obstructors mere parasites licensed to
prey upon the public. But where is the difference between
blocking the road and blocking the land that the roads
lead to? Where is the difference between levying
blackmail on the transport of goods and levying it on
their production?
But it will be said, "It was with real earnings that I
bought the right to demand this payment."
True. But the point is that whether I bought it or stole
it, the thing I have bought or stolen is the privilege of
levying blackmail upon industry; of demanding something
and giving nothing in return; of laying my hand on the
earth's surface and saying to all and sundry, "Give me of
the produce of your labour, or be off with you; so much a
year if I choose to let it; so much in a lump sum if I
prefer to sell it." Whichever of the two forms the demand
assumes it is called by political economists "rent," and
by that name I shall henceforth call it, because that is
the accepted name, and because there is no other compact
and handy term by which to express it; but it is not to
be confounded with rent in the legal and commercial
sense, which includes interest on the cost of
improvements. The rent I shall mean is economic rent
only; the price charged for the mere use of the land as
such, either without any improvements or apart from them:
I shall mean "ground rent" in short.
... read the whole
paper.
|
To share this page with a friend:
right click, choose "send," and add your
comments.
|
|
Red links have not been
visited; .
Green links are pages you've seen
|
Essential Documents pertinent
to this theme:
essential_documents
|
|