War
How many wars have been fought — and how many
more will be fought if we continue on the course we're on
today — over land and other natural resources? We
hear the expression "our oil under their sand."
Corporations are seeking natural resources we've become
reliant on, and our military are brought in to help
insure that we will have a continued supply of the
world's resources. Meanwhile, other countries will assert
their equal right to those resources, and none of us seem
willing to consider to whom those resources rightly
belong, and who should receive payment for them, and what
new institutional structures might be necessary to
today's realities.
Does our assertion that all people are created equal
mean that we acknowledge the basic equality of all the
world's people with us? Do we acknowledge their equal
claim on the world's natural resources, and their claim
on clean air and clean water? How do we make that real
and secure, for everyone? Henry George's ideas provide an
excellent foundation — and a valuable alternative
to war.
Rev. A. C. Auchmuty: Gems from George, a themed
collection of excerpts from the writings of Henry
George (with links to sources)
CAPITAL, which is not in itself a distinguishable
element, but which it must always be kept in mind
consists of wealth applied to the aid of labor in further
production, is not a primary factor. There can be
production without it, and there must have been
production without it, or it could not in the first place
have appeared. It is a secondary and compound factor,
coming after and resulting from the union of labor and
land in the production of wealth. It is in essence labor
raised by a second union with land to a third or higher
power. But it is to civilized life so necessary and
important as to be rightfully accorded in political
economy the place of a third factor in production.
— The Science of Political Economy
unabridged: Book III, Chapter 17, The Production of
Wealth: The Third Factor of Production —
Capital • abridged:
Part III, Chapter 10: Order of the Three Factors of
Production
IT is to be observed that capital of itself can do
nothing. It is always a subsidiary, never an initiatory,
factor. The initiatory factor is always labor. That is to
say, in the production of wealth labor always uses
capital, is never used by capital. This is not merely
literally true, when by the term capital we mean the
thing capital. It is also true when we personify the term
and mean by it not the thing capital, but the men who are
possessed of capital. The capitalist pure and simple, the
man who merely controls capital, has in his hands the
power of assisting labor to produce. But purely as
capitalist he cannot exercise that power. It can be
exercised only by labor. To utilize it he must himself
exercise at least some of the functions of labor, or he
must put his capital, on some terms, at the use of those
who do. — The Science of Political Economy
unabridged: Book III, Chapter 17, The Production of
Wealth: The Third Factor of Production —
Capital • abridged:
Part III, Chapter 10: Order of the Three Factors of
Production
THUS we must exclude from the category of capital
everything that may be included either as land or labor.
Doing so, there remain only things which are neither land
nor labor, but which have resulted from the union of
these two original factors of production. Nothing can be
properly capital that does not consist of these —
that is to say, nothing can be capital that is not
wealth. —
Progress & Poverty
— Book I, Chapter 2: Wages and Capital: The Meaning
of the Terms
THUS, a government bond is not capital, nor yet is it the
representative of capital. The capital that was
once received for it by the government has been consumed
unproductively — blown away from the mouths of
cannon, used up in war ships, expended in keeping men
marching and drilling, killing and destroying.
The bond cannot represent capital that has been
destroyed. It does not represent capital at all. It is
simply a solemn declaration that the government will,
some time or other, take by taxation from the then
existing stock of the people, so much wealth, which it
will turn over to the holder of the bond; and that, in
the meanwhile, it will, from time to time, take, in the
same way, enough to make up to the holder the increase
which so much capital as it some day promises to give him
would yield him were it actually in his possession. The
immense sums which are thus taken from the produce of
every modern country to pay interest on public debts are
not the earnings or increase of capital — are not
really interest in the strict sense of the term, but are
taxes levied on the produce of labor and capital, leaving
so much less for wages and so much less for real
interest. —
Progress & Poverty
— Book III, Chapter 4: The Laws of Distribution: Of
Spurious Capital and of Profits Often Mistaken For
Interest
CAPITAL, as we have seen, consists of wealth used for
the procurement of more wealth, as distinguished from
wealth used for the direct satisfaction of desire; or, as
I think it may be defined, of wealth in the course of
exchange.
Capital, therefore, increases the power of labor to
produce wealth: (1) By enabling labor to apply itself in
more effective ways, as by digging up clams with a spade
instead of the hand, or moving a vessel by shoveling coal
into a furnace, instead of tugging at an oar. (2) By
enabling labor to avail itself of the reproductive forces
of nature, as to obtain corn by sowing it, or animals by
breeding them. (3) By permitting the division of labor,
and thus, on the one hand, increasing the efficiency of
the human factor of wealth, by the utilization of special
capabilities, the acquisition of skill, and the reduction
of waste; and, on the other, calling in the powers of the
natural factor at their highest, by taking advantage of
the diversities of soil, climate and situation, so as to
obtain each particular species of wealth where nature is
most favorable to its production.
Capital does not supply the materials which labor works
up into wealth, as is erroneously taught; the materials
of wealth are supplied by nature. But such materials
partially worked up and in the course of exchange are
capital. —
Progress & Poverty
— Book I, Chapter 5: Wages and Capital: The Real
Functions of Capital
... go to "Gems from
George"
Henry George:
The Increasing Importance of Social Questions (Chapter
1 of Social
Problems, 1883)
[09] And so come new dangers. The rude society
resembles the creatures that though cut into pieces will
live; the highly civilized society is like a highly
organized animal: a stab in a vital part, the suppression
of a single function, is death. A savage village may be
burned and its people driven off — but, used to
direct recourse to nature, they can maintain themselves.
Highly civilized man, however, accustomed to capital, to
machinery, to the minute division of labor, becomes
helpless when suddenly deprived of these and thrown upon
nature. Under the factory system, some sixty persons,
with the aid of much costly machinery, cooperate to the
making of a pair of shoes. But, of the sixty, not one
could make a whole shoe. This is the tendency in all
branches of production, even in agriculture. How many
farmers of the new generation can use the flail? How many
farmers' wives can now make a coat from the wool? Many of
our farmers do not even make their own butter or raise
their own vegetables! There is an enormous gain in
productive power from this division of labor, which
assigns to the individual the production of but a few of
the things, or even but a small part of one of the
things, he needs, and makes each dependent upon others
with whom he never comes in contact; but the social
organization becomes more sensitive. A primitive village
community may pursue the even tenor of its life without
feeling disasters which overtake other villages but a few
miles off; but in the closely knit civilization to which
we have attained, a war, a scarcity, a commercial crisis,
in one hemisphere produces powerful effects in the other,
while shocks and jars from which a primitive community
easily recovers would to a highly civilized community
mean wreck.
[10] It is startling to think how destructive in a
civilization like ours would be such fierce conflicts as
fill the history of the past. The wars of highly
civilized countries, since the opening of the era of
steam and machinery, have been duels of armies rather
than conflicts of peoples or classes. Our only glimpse of
what might happen, wore passion fully aroused, was in the
struggle of the Paris Commune. And, since 1870, to the
knowledge of petroleum has been added that of even more
destructive agents. The explosion of a little
nitro-glycerin under a few water-mains would make a great
city uninhabitable; the blowing up of a few railroad
bridges and tunnels would bring famine quicker than the
wall of circumvallation that Titus drew around Jerusalem;
the pumping of atmospheric air into the gas-mains, and
the application of a match, would tear up every street
and level every house. The Thirty Years' War set back
civilization in Germany; so fierce a war now would all
but destroy it. Not merely have destructive powers vastly
increased, but the whole social organization has become
vastly more delicate.
[11] In a simpler state master and man, neighbor and
neighbor, know each other, and there is that touch of the
elbow which, in times of danger, enables society to
rally. But present tendencies are to the loss of this. In
London, dwellers in one house do not know those in the
next; the tenants of adjoining rooms are utter strangers
to each other. Let civil conflict break or paralyze the
authority that preserves order and the vast population
would become a terror-stricken mob, without point of
rally or principle of cohesion, and your London would be
sacked and burned by an army of thieves. London is only
the greatest of great cities. What is true of London is
true of New York, and in the same measure true of the
many cities whose hundreds of thousands are steadily
growing toward millions. These vast aggregations of
humanity, where he who seeks isolation may find it more
truly than in the desert; where wealth and poverty touch
and jostle; where one revels and another starves within a
few feet of each other, yet separated by as great a gulf
as that fixed between Dives in Hell and Lazarus in
Abraham's bosom — they are centers and types of our
civilization. Let jar or shock dislocate the complex and
delicate organization, let the policeman's club be thrown
down or wrested from him, and the fountains of the great
deep are opened, and quicker than ever before chaos comes
again. Strong as it may seem, our civilization is
evolving destructive forces. Not desert and forest, but
city slums and country roadsides are nursing the
barbarians who may be to the new what Hun and Vandal were
to the old.
[12] Nor should we forget that in civilized man still
lurks the savage. The men who, in past times, oppressed
or revolted, who fought to the death in petty quarrels
and drunk fury with blood, who burned cities and rent
empires, were men essentially such as those we daily
meet. Social progress has accumulated knowledge, softened
manners, refined tastes and extended sympathies, but man
is yet capable of as blind a rage as when, clothed in
skins, he fought wild beasts with a flint. And present
tendencies, in some respects at least, threaten to kindle
passions that have so often before flamed in destructive
fury.
[19] The progress of civilization requires that more
and more intelligence be devoted to social affairs, and
this not the intelligence of the few, but that of the
many. We cannot safely leave politics to politicians, or
political economy to college professors. The people
themselves must think, because the people alone can
act.
[21] The intelligence required for the solving of
social problems is not a thing of the mere intellect. It
must be animated with the religious sentiment and warm
with sympathy for human suffering. It must stretch out
beyond self-interest, whether it be the self-interest of
the few or of the many. It must seek justice. For at the
bottom of every social problem we will find a social
wrong.
... read the entire essay
Mason Gaffney:
Rent Seeking and Global Conflict
National governments originate historically to
acquire, hold and police land. Other functions are
assumed later, but sovereignty over land is always the
first business. Private parties hold land from the
sovereign: every chain of title goes back to a grantor
who originally seized the land.
When economists today speak of "rent-seeking" they
usually are thinking not of basic land rent, but in
subtle and sophisticated terms, looking at dribs and
drabs of transfer rent derived from contracting
advantages. They develop abstract models for gaming
optimally with imperfect information, and so on. By
emphasizing the arcane while ignoring the basic they are
in danger of matching the proverbial expert who
fine-tunes all the details and elaborations as he forges
on to the grand disaster.
Indeed, we have had one such disaster. Viet Nam was
viewed by many as an economists' war, rationally planned
and led by the best and the brightest systems' analysts,
exemplified by the brilliant, energetic Secretary of
Defense. One should not be surprised at the post-Viet Nam
decline of interest in applying modern economic theory to
questions of global conflict.
We would be more useful to statesmen if we looked
first at rent-seeking in the grosser sense of
“land-grabbing,” where the whole bundle is at
stake. When William of Normandy conquered England the
prize was land rent, all of it. He and his retainers
dispossessed the local rent-collectors. It was simple,
gross, and basic, and much more consequential than the
trivial rent-seeking we model today. The bulk of the
natives may have been affected only marginally: they just
paid Lord B instead of Lord A. But it made all the
difference to Lords B and A, the ones who made basic
decisions about global conflict and cooperation.
Again, from the 17th century Europeans invaded North
America, dispossessed the natives and each other, until
today we meet here, overlooking beach and ocean, paying
our daily rent for a little slice of land which has been
won and kept by a long chain of wars.
The roof over our heads is different, it is the
product of capital formation. Someone saved from
income, and paid workers to construct the building. Its
present value is that less the obvious depreciation and
obsolescence, so it is rentable today mainly for its
appreciated site, to which therefore an economist or an
appraiser must impute most of the market value here.
But the site never was nor could be the product of
capital formation. It pre-existed man, who could only
acquire it by taking. It is fair to say that throughout most of history that is what warfare was
about, seizing and holding and policing land. This
is not to deny ancillary causes and issues of war, such
as disputing the pathway to Heaven, ethnic pride,
paranoia, acquisitive genes, and a leader's need to
divert people from domestic problems. Economists should
certainly make it their business to address the last, a
major source of global conflict. Neither is this to deny
that territorial expansion is often self-defeating,
economically. Many empires, probably most, cost more than
they return, a discovery that accounts for the well-being
of small nations like Sweden, Austria, Denmark and The
Netherlands, which gained by abandoning destiny and
empire. But we would miss the point to bury particulars
in aggregates. By disaggregating benefits and costs we
gain the key to understanding. The whole nation loses,
but certain parties gain, and it is they who promote and
sustain aggressive behavior.
Economists conventionally bury this point when they
submit that "national defense is a public good".
- "Defense" is a loaded word
which rationalizes as it describes. "Military spending"
is more neutral, and will be used here. It is worth
remembering that the German Schutz (as in
Schutz-Staffel) and Wehr (as in Wehrmacht) both
translate as "defense". Lebensraum is a more forthright
term, and explains much more about Nazi
aggressions.
- "Public good" says that all
gain equally. But that is not true even of pure defense
proper. What is defended behind the defense wall is
land previously seized. The Lords and Barons have much
at stake; the serfs and vagrants very little.
Rent is what is being defended, along
with, no doubt, traditional feelings of machismo and
some local folkways and mores.
Wages, as well as the return for capital formation,
ultimately need little defense because they are
economically functional. They are paid for real service
and sacrifices, and will command a return in almost any
viable system. Labor is also more migratory. "Fixed"
capital also migrates economically as capital recovery
funds are reinvested elsewhere. Land, in contrast, does
not migrate among nations. Nations are defined as areas
of land.
But it is outside the defense wall of the nation
proper that rent-seeking is most dynamic and
destabilizing. Military force (often in tandem with
finance) is used to project sovereignty into foreign
nations, and over no-man's-lands like the oceans, polar
regions, radio spectrum, and outer space.
Offshore rent-seekers are of two general kinds.
1. "Caciques." Cacique is a
generic term for local cooperating
rulers from the native population. It is more
neutral than Quisling, and most caciques are more
independent than he was. Imperial metropolitan powers
normally work through caciques. Turnover among
individual caciques is sometimes high, but they are
drawn from the matrix of the local landholding
oligarchy which is quite stable, often thanks to our
support.
We relieve the caciques of collecting
and/or paying taxes for their own military, which often
double as domestic police as well. The life of some
caciques is risky, but the rewards to caciques
and local landholders are often very high. The Sultan
of Brunei is the richest man in the world; the
extravagance of Ferdinand and Imelda Marcos is
legendary.
Unit land values in Tokyo have, in mid-boom.
exceeded those in New York and Chicago by a factor of
about 10. One reason (of several) for the difference is
that New York and Chicago pay taxes to defend Tokyo,
plus what the Japanese once called the Greater East
Asia Co-Prosperity Sphere. Roosevelt in 1941 stopped
Japan at Viet Nam, precipitating Pearl Harbor. But
Eisenhower said in 1959 we must defend Viet Nam to
protect the Japanese resource base.
2. Rent-seekers of the second kind are U.S. or
allied multinational interests, mostly
corporations. The cacique is expected to assign to
them, or be complaisant in their taking concessions and
resources like minerals, transportation routes,
communications, bank charters, plantations, etc.
Natives normally control more of the
traditional resources like farmland. Foreigners
specialize more in less visible, more novel and
sophisticated resources like
- undiscovered minerals (exploration
rights),
- navigation rights,
- radio spectrum,
- overflights,
- bank charters, etc.
Both these groups have the acutest incentive to
influence U.S. policies, and large discretionary funds at
hand. Therefore they tend to dominate U.S. statecraft.
The U.S. government is probably more vulnerable to such
foreign influence than most, because of our size and
weakly developed sense of honorable dedication to the
national interest. The English once terminated a dynasty,
the Stuarts, which was caught taking support from France;
but Americans hardly notice when retired Congressmen take
work lobbying for foreign sugar producers etc.
Self-evidently, rivalry to appropriate limited
rent-yielding resources must lead to conflict. It has to,
because land is not produced, nor stored up like capital
by saving. Modern economics glosses over this by
stressing that land, like other resources, is allocated
by the market. That may be, but distribution is something
else. Every land title in the world goes
back to a taking by force.
It will be objected that one can buy in peacefully
once a tenure is firmly established, with alienable
titles. There is certainly no intent to deny this. The
problem is that a successor-in-interest stands on no
firmer footing than the original. There
is no laundering: every landholder can consult his chain
of title and see how it originated.. Indeed, it has been
said that those who buy stolen property are the chief
cause of crime. Fencing itself is a crime.
However one may side on that question, it helps
account for the extreme alarm with which US statecraft
startles at any foreign country, however weak and
innocuous, which expropriates any such
successor-in-interest. Demonstration effects are
contagious and threatening. The defensiveness of the
insecure is a major cause of global conflict.
More destabilizing yet is the ambitious
rent-seeker offshore, who finds his biggest gains in the
riskiest ways, ways that unfortunately impose high risks
on the U.S. The biggest gains to rent-seekers come from
buying in on the ground floor, cheap, when tenures are
precarious or uncertain.
Then one invokes the U.S. armed forces and the
sanctions of ancillary statecraft to raise the value of
one's acquisition. The three main concerns are
- to firm up precarious tenures (as by supporting the
government that granted them);
- to hold down taxes (as by lending the U..S. armed
forces); and
- to avoid pure competition (as by giving
preferential access to the U.S. market, or Pentagon
procurers). ...
Read the whole article
Henry George: The Condition of Labor
— An Open Letter to Pope Leo XIII in response to
Rerum Novarum (1891)
... Nor do we hesitate to say that this way of
securing the equal right to the bounty of the Creator and
the exclusive right to the products of labor is the way
intended by God for raising public revenues. For we are
not atheists, who deny God; nor semi-atheists, who deny
that he has any concern in politics and legislation.
It is true as you say — a salutary truth too
often forgotten — that “man is older than the
state, and he holds the right of providing for the life
of his body prior to the formation of any state.”
Yet, as you too perceive, it is also true that the state
is in the divinely appointed order. For He who foresaw
all things and provided for all things, foresaw and
provided that with the increase of population and the
development of industry the organization of human society
into states or governments would become both expedient
and necessary.
No sooner does the state arise than, as we all know,
it needs revenues. This need for revenues is small at
first, while population is sparse, industry rude and the
functions of the state few and simple. But with growth of
population and advance of civilization the functions of
the state increase and larger and larger revenues are
needed.
Now, He that made the world and placed man in it, He
that pre-ordained civilization as the means whereby man
might rise to higher powers and become more and more
conscious of the works of his Creator, must have foreseen
this increasing need for state revenues and have made
provision for it. That is to say: The increasing need for
public revenues with social advance, being a natural,
God-ordained need, there must be a right way of raising
them — some way that we can truly say is the way
intended by God. It is clear that this right way of
raising public revenues must accord with the moral
law.
Hence:
It must not take from individuals what rightfully
belongs to individuals.
It must not give some an advantage over others, as by
increasing the prices of what some have to sell and
others must buy.
It must not lead men into temptation, by requiring
trivial oaths, by making it profitable to lie, to swear
falsely, to bribe or to take bribes.
It must not confuse the distinctions of right and
wrong, and weaken the sanctions of religion and the state
by creating crimes that are not sins, and punishing men
for doing what in itself they have an undoubted right to
do.
It must not repress industry. It must not check
commerce. It must not punish thrift. It must offer no
impediment to the largest production and the fairest
division of wealth.
Let me ask your Holiness to consider the taxes on the
processes and products of industry by which through the
civilized world public revenues are collected — the
octroi duties that surround Italian cities with barriers;
the monstrous customs duties that hamper intercourse
between so-called Christian states; the taxes on
occupations, on earnings, on investments, on the building
of houses, on the cultivation of fields, on industry and
thrift in all forms. Can these be the ways God has
intended that governments should raise the means they
need? Have any of them the characteristics indispensable
in any plan we can deem a right one?
All these taxes violate the moral law. They take by
force what belongs to the individual alone; they give to
the unscrupulous an advantage over the scrupulous; they
have the effect, nay are largely intended, to increase
the price of what some have to sell and others must buy;
they corrupt government; they make oaths a mockery; they
shackle commerce; they fine industry and thrift; they
lessen the wealth that men might enjoy, and enrich some
by impoverishing others.
Yet what most strikingly shows how opposed to
Christianity is this system of raising public revenues is
its influence on thought.
Christianity teaches us that all men are
brethren; that their true interests are harmonious, not
antagonistic. It gives us, as the golden rule of life,
that we should do to others as we would have others do to
us. But out of the system of taxing the products and
processes of labor, and out of its effects in increasing
the price of what some have to sell and others must buy,
has grown the theory of “protection,” which
denies this gospel, which holds Christ ignorant of
political economy and proclaims laws of national
well-being utterly at variance with his teaching. This
theory sanctifies national hatreds; it inculcates a
universal war of hostile tariffs; it teaches peoples that
their prosperity lies in imposing on the productions of
other peoples restrictions they do not wish imposed on
their own; and instead of the Christian doctrine of
man’s brotherhood it makes injury of foreigners a
civic virtue.
“By their fruits ye shall know them.” Can
anything more clearly show that to tax the products and
processes of industry is not the way God intended public
revenues to be raised?
But to consider what we propose — the raising of
public revenues by a single tax on the value of land
irrespective of improvements — is to see that in
all respects this does conform to the moral law.
Let me ask your Holiness to keep in mind that the
value we propose to tax, the value of land irrespective
of improvements, does not come from any exertion of labor
or investment of capital on or in it — the values
produced in this way being values of improvement which we
would exempt. The value of land irrespective of
improvement is the value that attaches to land by reason
of increasing population and social progress. This is a
value that always goes to the owner as owner, and never
does and never can go to the user; for if the user be a
different person from the owner he must always pay the
owner for it in rent or in purchase-money; while if the
user be also the owner, it is as owner, not as user, that
he receives it, and by selling or renting the land he
can, as owner, continue to receive it after he ceases to
be a user.
Thus, taxes on land irrespective of improvement cannot
lessen the rewards of industry, nor add to prices,* nor
in any way take from the individual what belongs to the
individual. They can take only the value that attaches to
land by the growth of the community, and which therefore
belongs to the community as a whole.
* As to this point it may be well to add
that all economists are agreed that taxes on land
values irrespective of improvement or use — or
what in the terminology of political economy is styled
rent, a term distinguished from the ordinary use of the
word rent by being applied solely to payments for the
use of land itself — must be paid by the owner
and cannot be shifted by him on the user. To explain in
another way the reason given in the text: Price is not
determined by the will of the seller or the will of the
buyer, but by the equation of demand and supply, and
therefore as to things constantly demanded and
constantly produced rests at a point determined by the
cost of production — whatever tends to increase
the cost of bringing fresh quantities of such articles
to the consumer increasing price by checking supply,
and whatever tends to reduce such cost decreasing price
by increasing supply. Thus taxes on wheat or tobacco or
cloth add to the price that the consumer must pay, and
thus the cheapening in the cost of producing steel
which improved processes have made in recent years has
greatly reduced the price of steel. But land has no
cost of production, since it is created by God, not
produced by man. Its price therefore is fixed
—
1 (monopoly rent), where land is held
in close monopoly, by what the owners can extract
from the users under penalty of deprivation and
consequently of starvation, and amounts to all that
common labor can earn on it beyond what is necessary
to life;
2 (economic rent proper), where there is no special
monopoly, by what the particular land will yield to
common labor over and above what may be had by like
expenditure and exertion on land having no special
advantage and for which no rent is paid; and,
3 (speculative rent, which is a species of monopoly
rent, telling particularly in selling price), by the
expectation of future increase of value from social
growth and improvement, which expectation causing
landowners to withhold land at present prices has the
same effect as combination.
Taxes on land values or economic rent
can therefore never be shifted by the landowner to the
land-user, since they in no wise increase the demand
for land or enable landowners to check supply by
withholding land from use. Where rent depends on mere
monopolization, a case I mention because rent may in
this way be demanded for the use of land even before
economic or natural rent arises, the taking by taxation
of what the landowners were able to extort from labor
could not enable them to extort any more, since
laborers, if not left enough to live on, will die. So,
in the case of economic rent proper, to take from the
landowners the premiums they receive, would in no way
increase the superiority of their land and the demand
for it. While, so far as price is affected by
speculative rent, to compel the landowners to pay taxes
on the value of land whether they were getting any
income from it or not, would make it more difficult for
them to withhold land from use; and to tax the full
value would not merely destroy the power but the desire
to do so.
To take land values for the state, abolishing all
taxes on the products of labor, would therefore leave to
the laborer the full produce of labor; to the individual
all that rightfully belongs to the individual. It would
impose no burden on industry, no check on commerce, no
punishment on thrift; it would secure the largest
production and the fairest distribution of wealth, by
leaving men free to produce and to exchange as they
please, without any artificial enhancement of prices; and
by taking for public purposes a value that cannot be
carried off, that cannot be hidden, that of all values is
most easily ascertained and most certainly and cheaply
collected, it would enormously lessen the number of
officials, dispense with oaths, do away with temptations
to bribery and evasion, and abolish man-made crimes in
themselves innocent.
But, further: That God has intended the state to
obtain the revenues it needs by the taxation of land
values is shown by the same order and degree of evidence
that shows that God has intended the milk of the mother
for the nourishment of the babe.
See how close is the analogy. In that primitive
condition ere the need for the state arises there are no
land values. The products of labor have value, but in the
sparsity of population no value as yet attaches to land
itself. But as increasing density of population and
increasing elaboration of industry necessitate the
organization of the state, with its need for revenues,
value begins to attach to land. As population still
increases and industry grows more elaborate, so the needs
for public revenues increase. And at the same time and
from the same causes land values increase. The connection
is invariable. The value of things produced by labor
tends to decline with social development, since the
larger scale of production and the improvement of
processes tend steadily to reduce their cost. But the
value of land on which population centers goes up and up.
Take Rome or Paris or London or New York or Melbourne.
Consider the enormous value of land in such cities as
compared with the value of land in sparsely settled parts
of the same countries. To what is this due? Is it not due
to the density and activity of the populations of those
cities — to the very causes that require great
public expenditure for streets, drains, public buildings,
and all the many things needed for the health,
convenience and safety of such great cities? See how with
the growth of such cities the one thing that steadily
increases in value is land; how the opening of roads, the
building of railways, the making of any public
improvement, adds to the value of land. Is it not clear
that here is a natural law — that is to say a
tendency willed by the Creator? Can it mean anything else
than that He who ordained the state with its needs has in
the values which attach to land provided the means to
meet those needs?
That it does mean this and nothing else is confirmed
if we look deeper still, and inquire not merely as to the
intent, but as to the purpose of the intent. If we do so
we may see in this natural law by which land values
increase with the growth of society not only such a
perfectly adapted provision for the needs of society as
gratifies our intellectual perceptions by showing us the
wisdom of the Creator, but a purpose with regard to the
individual that gratifies our moral perceptions by
opening to us a glimpse of his beneficence.
Consider: Here is a natural law by which as society
advances the one thing that increases in value is land
— a natural law by virtue of which all growth of
population, all advance of the arts, all general
improvements of whatever kind, add to a fund that both
the commands of justice and the dictates of expediency
prompt us to take for the common uses of society. Now,
since increase in the fund available for the common uses
of society is increase in the gain that goes equally to
each member of society, is it not clear that the law by
which land values increase with social advance while the
value of the products of labor does not increase, tends
with the advance of civilization to make the share that
goes equally to each member of society more and more
important as compared with what goes to him from his
individual earnings, and thus to make the advance of
civilization lessen relatively the differences that in a
ruder social state must exist between the strong and the
weak, the fortunate and the unfortunate? Does it not show
the purpose of the Creator to be that the advance of man
in civilization should be an advance not merely to larger
powers but to a greater and greater equality, instead of
what we, by our ignoring of his intent, are making it, an
advance toward a more and more monstrous inequality?
...
Your use, in so many passages of your Encyclical, of
the inclusive term “property” or
“private” property, of which in morals
nothing can be either affirmed or denied, makes your
meaning, if we take isolated sentences, in many places
ambiguous. But reading it as a whole, there can be no
doubt of your intention that private property in land
shall be understood when you speak merely of private
property. With this interpretation, I find that the
reasons you urge for private property in land are eight.
Let us consider them in order of presentation. You
urge:
1. That what is bought with rightful property is
rightful property. (RN, paragraph 5) ...
2. That private property in land proceeds from
man’s gift of reason. (RN, paragraphs 6-7.)
...
3. That private property in land deprives no one of the
use of land. (RN, paragraph 8.) ...
4. That Industry expended on land gives ownership in the
land itself. (RN, paragraphs 9-10.) ...
5. That private property in land has the support of the
common opinion of mankind, and has conduced to peace and
tranquillity, and that it is sanctioned by Divine Law.
(RN, paragraph 11.) ...
6. That fathers should provide for their children and
that private property in land is necessary to enable them
to do so. (RN, paragraphs 14-17.) ...
7. That the private ownership of land stimulates
industry, increases wealth, and attaches men to the soil
and to their country. (RN, paragraph 51.) ...
8. That the right to possess private property in land is
from nature, not from man; that the state has no right to
abolish it, and that to take the value of landownership
in taxation would be unjust and cruel to the private
owner. (RN, paragraph 51.) ...
5. That private property in land has the
support of the common opinion of mankind, and has
conduced to peace and tranquillity, and that it is
sanctioned by Divine Law. (11.)
Even were it true that the common opinion of mankind
has sanctioned private property in land, this would no
more prove its justice than the once universal practice
of the known world would have proved the justice of
slavery.
But it is not true. Examination will show that
wherever we can trace them the first perceptions of
mankind have always recognized the equality of right to
land, and that when individual possession became
necessary to secure the right of ownership in things
produced by labor some method of securing equality,
sufficient in the existing state of social development,
was adopted. Thus, among some peoples, land used for
cultivation was periodically divided, land used for
pasturage and wood being held in common. Among others,
every family was permitted to hold what land it needed
for a dwelling and for cultivation, but the moment that
such use and cultivation stopped any one else could step
in and take it on like tenure. Of the same nature were
the land laws of the Mosaic code. The land, first fairly
divided among the people, was made inalienable by the
provision of the jubilee, under which, if sold, it
reverted every fiftieth year to the children of its
original possessors.
Private property in land as we know it, the
attaching to land of the same right of ownership that
justly attaches to the products of labor, has never grown
up anywhere save by usurpation or force. Like slavery, it
is the result of war. It comes to us of the
modern world from your ancestors, the Romans, whose
civilization it corrupted and whose empire it
destroyed.
It made with the freer spirit of the northern peoples
the combination of the feudal system, in which, though
subordination was substituted for equality, there was
still a rough recognition of the principle of common
rights in land. A fief was a trust, and to enjoyment was
annexed some obligation. The sovereign, the
representative of the whole people, was the only owner of
land. Of him, immediately or mediately, held tenants,
whose possession involved duties or payments, which,
though rudely and imperfectly, embodied the idea that we
would carry out in the single tax, of taking land values
for public uses. The crown lands maintained the sovereign
and the civil list; the church lands defrayed the cost of
public worship and instruction, of the relief of the
sick, the destitute and the wayworn; while the military
tenures provided for public defense and bore the
costs of war. A fourth and very large portion of
the land remained in common, the people of the
neighborhood being free to pasture it, cut wood on it, or
put it to other common uses.
In this partial yet substantial recognition of
common rights to land is to be found the reason why, in a
time when the industrial arts were rude, wars frequent,
and the great discoveries and inventions of our time
unthought of, the condition of the laborer was devoid of
that grinding poverty which despite our marvelous
advances now exists. Speaking of England, the
highest authority on such subjects, the late Professor
Therold Rogers, declares that in the thirteenth century
there was no class so poor, so helpless, so pressed and
degraded as are millions of Englishmen in our boasted
nineteenth century; and that, save in times of actual
famine, there was no laborer so poor as to fear that his
wife and children might come to want even were he taken
from them. Dark and rude in many respects as they were,
these were the times when the cathedrals and churches and
religious houses whose ruins yet excite our admiration
were built; the times when England had no national debt,
no poor law, no standing army, no hereditary paupers, no
thousands and thousands of human beings rising in the
morning without knowing where they might lay their heads
at night.
With the decay of the feudal system, the system of
private property in land that had destroyed Rome was
extended. As to England, it may briefly be said that the
crown lands were for the most part given away to
favorites; that the church lands were parceled among his
courtiers by Henry VIII., and in Scotland grasped by the
nobles; that the military dues were finally remitted in
the seventeenth century, and taxation on consumption
substituted; and that by a process beginning with the
Tudors and extending to our own time all but a mere
fraction of the commons were inclosed by the greater
landowners; while the same private ownership of land was
extended over Ireland and the Scottish Highlands, partly
by the sword and partly by bribery of the chiefs. Even
the military dues, had they been commuted, not remitted,
would today have more than sufficed to pay all public
expenses without one penny of other taxation.
Of the New World, whose institutions but continue
those of Europe, it is only necessary to say that to the
parceling out of land in great tracts is due the
backwardness and turbulence of Spanish America; that to
the large plantations of the Southern States of the Union
was due the persistence of slavery there, and that the
more northern settlements showed the earlier English
feeling, land being fairly well divided and the attempts
to establish manorial estates coming to little or
nothing. In this lies the secret of the more vigorous
growth of the Northern States. But the idea that land was
to be treated as private property had been thoroughly
established in English thought before the colonial period
ended, and it has been so treated by the United States
and by the several States. And though land was at first
sold cheaply, and then given to actual settlers, it was
also sold in large quantities to speculators, given away
in great tracts for railroads and other purposes, until
now the public domain of the United States, which a
generation ago seemed illimitable, has practically gone.
And this, as the experience of other countries shows, is
the natural result in a growing community of making land
private property. When the possession of land means the
gain of unearned wealth, the strong and unscrupulous will
secure it. But when, as we propose, economic rent, the
“unearned increment of wealth,” is taken by
the state for the use of the community, then land will
pass into the hands of users and remain there, since no
matter how great its value, its possession will be
profitable only to users.
As to private property in land having conduced to the
peace and tranquillity of human life, it is not necessary
more than to allude to the notorious fact that the
struggle for land has been the prolific source of wars
and of lawsuits, while it is the poverty engendered by
private property in land that makes the prison and the
workhouse the unfailing attributes of what we call
Christian civilization.
Your Holiness intimates that the Divine Law gives its
sanction to the private ownership of land, quoting from
Deuteronomy, “Thou shalt not covet thy
neighbor’s wife, nor his house, nor his field, nor
his man-servant, nor his maid-servant, nor his ox, nor
his ass, nor anything which is his.”
If, as your Holiness conveys, this inclusion of the
words, “nor his field,” is to be taken as
sanctioning private property in land as it exists today,
then, but with far greater force, must the words,
“his man-servant, nor his maid-servant,” be
taken to sanction chattel slavery; for it is evident from
other provisions of the same code that these terms
referred both to bondsmen for a term of years and to
perpetual slaves. But the word “field”
involves the idea of use and improvement, to which the
right of possession and ownership does attach without
recognition of property in the land itself. And that this
reference to the “field” is not a sanction of
private property in land as it exists today is proved by
the fact that the Mosaic code expressly denied such
unqualified ownership in land, and with the declaration,
“the land also shall not be sold forever, because
it is mine, and you are strangers and sojourners with
me,” provided for its reversion every fiftieth
year; thus, in a way adapted to the primitive industrial
conditions of the time, securing to all of the chosen
people a foothold in the soil.
Nowhere in fact throughout the Scriptures can the
slightest justification be found for the attaching to
land of the same right of property that justly attaches
to the things produced by labor. Everywhere is it treated
as the free bounty of God, “the land which the Lord
thy God giveth thee.” ...
How true this is we may see in the facts of today. In
our own time invention and discovery have enormously
increased the productive power of labor, and at the same
time greatly reduced the cost of many things necessary to
the support of the laborer. Have these
improvements anywhere raised the earnings of the mere
laborer? Have not their benefits mainly gone to the
owners of land — enormously increased land
values?
I say mainly, for some part of the benefit has
gone to the cost of monstrous standing armies and warlike
preparations; to the payment of interest on
great public debts; and, largely disguised as interest on
fictitious capital, to the owners of monopolies other
than that of land. But improvements that would do away
with these wastes would not benefit labor; they would
simply increase the profits of landowners. Were
standing armies and all their incidents
abolished, were all monopolies other than that
of land done away with, were governments to become models
of economy, were the profits of speculators, of
middlemen, of all sorts of exchangers saved, were every
one to become so strictly honest that no policemen, no
courts, no prisons, no precautions against dishonesty
would be needed — the result would not differ from
that which has followed the increase of productive
power.
Nay, would not these very blessings bring starvation
to many of those who now manage to live? Is it
not true that if there were proposed today, what all
Christian men ought to pray for, the complete disbandment
of all the armies of Europe, the greatest fears would be
aroused for the consequences of throwing on the
labor-market so many unemployed laborers?
... read
the whole letter
Proving
Title
Years ago, a New Orleans lawyer sought an FHA loan
for a client. He was told the loan would be granted IF he
could prove satisfactory title to a parcel of property
being offered as collateral. No big deal; customary
request.
The title of the property dated back to 1803.
Instead of tracing title back 50 years, the customary
amount, the lawyer traced it all the way back to 1803.
This took him three months. ...
"For the edification of uninformed FHA
bureaucrats, the title to the land prior to U.S.
ownership was obtained from France, which had acquired it
by right of conquest from Spain. The land came into
possession of Spain by right of conquest made in the year
1492 by a sea captain named Christopher Columbus, who had
been granted the privilege of seeking a new route to
India by the Spanish monarch, Isabella. The good queen
Isabella, being a pious woman and almost as careful about
titles as the FHA, took the precaution of securing the
blessing of the Pope before she sold her jewels to
finance Columbus' expedition.
Now the Pope, as I'm sure you may know, is the emissary
of Jesus Christ, the Son of God, and God, it is commonly
accepted, created this world. Therefore, I believe it is
safe to presume that God also made that part of the world
called Louisiana. God, therefore, would be the owner of
origin and His origins date back to before the beginning
of time and of the world as we AND the FHA know it. I
hope to hell you find God's original claim to be
satisfactory. ... "
Rousseau
The first man who, having enclosed a piece of
ground, bethought himself of saying, “This is
mine”, and found people simple enough to believe
him, was the real founder of civil society.
From how many crimes, wars and murders, from how
many horrors and misfortunes, might not anyone have saved mankind by pulling up the
stakes, filling in the ditch, and crying to his fellows,
“BEWARE OF LISTENING TO THIS IMPOSTOR; YOU ARE
UNDONE IF YOU ONCE FORGET THAT THE FRUITS OF THE EARTH
BELONG TO US ALL, AND THE EARTH ITSELF TO
NOBODY.”
Any conception of justice may seem to be no more
than one person's opinion. And yet there are things that
we all know about justice. If I tell you that I stand
before you as justice, you know that across my face you
will find -- a blindfold. In my left hand I hold aloft --
a pair of scales. You know that in my right hand I have
-- a sword that I will use if necessary. And my gender is
female.
The blindfold, the scales, the sword,
and the feminine gender. These features of the traditional
symbol tell us much about justice. The blindfold might seem
out of place, since it prevents justice from either seeing
what the scales say or wielding the sword effectively. But
we know that the blindfold has a distinct and essential
meaning. The blindfold ensures that justice will not be
swayed by any visible characteristics of those who plead
before her. Justice is not concerned with whether you are
black or white, short or tall, beautiful or ugly. Every
person receives the same treatment from justice.
...
The scales have at least two possible
interpretations. The first interpretation is that the
disputants at the bar of justice each place their arguments
in one of the pans of the scales, and justice determines
who has the weightier arguments. Our language supports this
interpretation with references to the scales of justice
tipping in one direction or another. But there is different
use of the scales that is particularly relevant to
questions of social justice, as opposed to personal
disputes. The scales can be used to
achieve an equal division. Justice is done when the
contents of one pan of the scales are exactly balanced by
the contents of the other. This is the meaning of
the scales that I shall apply.
And then the sword. The sword
represents the fact that justice is prepared to use the
threat of force, and force itself, to see that her decrees
are carried out. In a world where men have so often used
weapons to achieve selfish dominance, the feminine gender
helps make credible the claim that the sword is used only
to achieve justice, and not to advance the selfish
interests of the person who wields it.
Thus if we know that justice is the
blindfolded woman with the scales and the sword, then we
know that justice is the principles of equality and
evenhandedness that command and prohibit the use of force
in resolving conflicts. ...
Consider what this tells us. It tells
us first that if we wish to claim that justice authorizes
the force we wish to use, or that justice forbids the force
that others wish to use against us, then we must be able to
show that our claim is consistent with equality and
evenhandedness. ...
One tradition in classical liberalism
concerning claims to land is that of the "homesteading libertarians," as exemplified by
Murray Rothbard, who say that there is really no need to be
concerned with Locke's proviso. Natural opportunities
belong to whoever first appropriates them, regardless of
whether opportunities of equal value are available to
others.[13]
The other tradition is that of the
"geoists," as inspired if not
exemplified by Henry George, who say that, whenever natural
opportunities are scarce, each person has an obligation to
ensure that the per capita value of the natural
opportunities that he leaves for others is as great as the
value of the natural opportunities that he claims for
himself.[14] Any excess in
one's claim generates an obligation to compensate those who
thereby have less. George actually proposed the nearly
equivalent idea, that all or nearly all of the rental value
of land should be collected in taxes, and all other taxes
should be abolished. The geoist position as I have
expressed it emphasizes the idea that, at least when value
generated by public services is not an issue, rights to
land are fundamentally rights of individuals, not rights of
governments.
There are two fundamental problems
with the position of homesteading libertarians on claims to
land. The first problem is the incongruity with historical
reality. Humans have emerged from an environment of
violence. Those who now have titles to land can trace those
titles back only so far, before they come to events where
fiat backed by violence determined title. And the persons
who were displaced at that time themselves had titles that
originated in violence. If there ever were humans who
acquired the use of land without forcibly displacing other
humans, we have no way of knowing who they were or who
their current descendants might be. There is, in practice,
no way of assigning land to the legitimate successors of
the persons who first claimed land. And to assign titles
based on any fraction of history is to reward the last land
seizures that are not rectified.
The second fundamental problem with
the position of the homesteading libertarians is that, even
if there were previously unsettled land to be allocated,
say a new continent emerging from the ocean, first grabbing
would make no sense as a criterion for allocating
land. ... Read
the entire article
Nic Tideman: The Case for Taxing
Land
I. Taxing Land as Ethics and
Efficiency
II. What is Land?
III. The simple efficiency argument for
taxing land
IV. Taxing Land is Better Than
Neutral
V. Measuring the Economic Gains from
Shifting Taxes to Land
VI. The Ethical Case for Taxing Land
VII. Answer to Arguments against Taxing
Land
There is a case for taxing land based on ethical
principles and a case for taxing land based on efficiency
principles. As a matter of logic, these two cases
are separate. Ethical conclusions follow from
ethical premises and efficiency conclusions from
efficiency principles. However, it is natural for
human minds to conflate the two cases. It is easier
to believe that something is good if one knows that it is
efficient, and it is easier to see that something is
efficient if one believes that it is good.
Therefore it is important for a discussion of land
taxation to address both question of efficiency and
questions of ethics.
This monograph will first address the efficiency case for taxing land, because that
is the less controversial case. The efficiency case
for taxing land has two main parts. ...
To estimate the magnitudes of the impacts that
additional taxes on land would have on an economy, one
must have a model of the economy. I report on
estimates of the magnitudes of impacts on the U.S.
economy of shifting taxes to land, based on a
mathematical model that is outlined in the
Appendix.
The ethical case for
taxing land is based on two ethical premises:
...
The ethical case for taxing land ends with a
discussion of the reasons why recognition of the equal
rights of all to land may be essential for world
peace.
After developing the efficiency argument and the
ethical argument for taxing land, I consider a variety of
counter-arguments that have been offered against taxing
land. For a given level of other taxes, a rise in
the rate at which land is taxed causes a fall in the
selling price of land. It is sometimes argued that
only modest taxes on land are therefore feasible, because
as the rate of taxation on land increases and the selling
price of land falls, market transactions become
increasingly less reliable as indicators of the value of
land. ...
Another basis on which it is argued that greatly
increased taxes on land are infeasible is that if land
values were to fall precipitously, the financial system
would collapse. ...
Apart from questions of feasibility, it is
sometimes argued that erosion of land values from taxing
land would harm economic efficiency, because it would
reduce opportunities for entrepreneurs to use land as
collateral for loans to finance their ideas.
...
.
Another ethical argument that is made against
taxing land is that the return to unusual ability is
“rent” just as the return to land is
rent. ...
But before developing any of these arguments, I
must discuss what land is. ...
The processes that humans employ to determine who
shall have exclusive use of natural opportunities are
complex. To some extent, opportunities are assigned
to those who first make use of them. However,
another important component of the
natural-opportunity-assignment process is the ability and
willingness to use deadly force to exclude others.
Americans from Europe undertook some negotiations with
the native American Indians, but primarily they
threatened to kill the Indians if they did not agree to
move into smaller territories. All over the world,
nations emerged when war-minded leaders imposed their
rule where they could. We have built a relatively
humane world on this violent foundation, but the origins
of the assignment of natural opportunities cannot be
characterized as just.
Nor would have been just (or efficient) to adhere
to a rule of initial assignment based on first use.
It would not be just because a person who arrives later
than another is not inherently less
deserving. (It would not be efficient because a
rule of assignment based on first use promotes
inefficient, excessive investment in being first.
Still, to motivate efficient discovery, it pays to
provide some reward for discoverers.) ...
Read the whole
article
Karl Williams: Social Justice In Australia:
INTRODUCTORY KIT
There's an amusing story of a Georgist who
challenged a land baron as to the baron's right to his
vast tracts. The baron knew the history of the estate of
his noble bloodlines, and told how one of his ancestors
had paid good money for the land, rather than gaining it
by some royal grant. To this the Georgist replied, "But
how did the previous owner obtain it?" Again the baron
explained how that person had also once paid good money
for it. Yet again and again, the Georgist persisted with,
"But how did that owner obtain it?" Finally, the baron
said, "He fought for it in battle, and won it". To which
the Georgist said, "Good! I'll fight you for it!"
Read the entire article
Karl Williams: Social Justice In Australia:
ADVANCED KIT
WAR -- WHO'S THE REAL
VILLAIN!
"But when the sky darkens, and
the prospect is war
Who's given a gun and then pushed to the fore?
Aye, and expected to die for the land of our birth
We who have never owned one handful of earth."
Anon.
Would Geonomics lead to an outbreak of
multi-ethnic tea parties all over the Balkans? We repeat,
Geonomics is not a panacea. Without it, though, there
will never be any real prosperity or social justice.
Similarly, Geonomics isn't the panacea for all conflict,
but without it there will always be incentives to wage
war.
THE TIMELESS CAUSE OF
CONFLICT
The issue is territorial conquest. If you examine
the causes of war, you won't be able to identify many for
which territorial conquest was not an important factor.
This is especially the case if you broaden the term
territory to include water (one of the things over which
scores of future wars will be fought, many say) and
minerals (including oil).
Wherever a society exists in which individuals or
groups can own the Earth outright and thereby profit
enormously, then there's going to be a great temptation
to seize a few of the best chunks. Of course, there'll be
some ostensible justification for this confiscation, such
as:
- Some silly nationalistic "principle", like
ethnic pride or vengeance
- Some historical justification, like "we had it
first" (selectively choosing how far back in history to
go)
- A pre-emptive move of forward self-defense in
the face of imminent (or beat-up) threats by a hostile
neighbour
One way or another, nearly all war is about
territory in the end. As humans are physical beings,
somehow stuck in time and three dimensions, this must be
ever so. If we are going to claim exclusive and eternal
possession of some of the physical environment where our
bodies - pretty much locked to our consciousnesses - want
to move, then it's no wonder that one may hear big, loud,
angry-sounding bumps sometimes.
WHAT MAKES LAND SO
SPECIAL
Land is limited, a minimum of it is essential for
survival, and its quality varies greatly. This presently
gives a big incentive to some
individuals/clans/tribes/ethnic groups/nations to grab
more than their fair share. And, seeing how generals or
demagogues in charge usually ensure that their own nests
are pretty well-feathered, the poor old plebs are often
led into a war from which they will gain little if
anything - as the poem at the head of the page well
illustrates.
So how would LVT change all this? Well, it
wouldn't change it all but it would, for starters,
eliminate or greatly reduce that particular incentive for
individual or group gain arising through the possibility
of claiming ownership of natural resources, including
land.
A CHANGE IN
CONSCIOUSNESS?
And here's a completely different tack: while
greed, malice and cynicism rule human hearts, no system
of government can hope to eliminate war. But, given
enough time, perhaps an enabling environment would
nurture more the virtuous than the vicious side of
humanity and eventually bring about peace on a personal
level - a sort of bottom-up approach. For instance, the
more people there are who understand the philosophy of
social justice (not to mention the potential prosperity)
that LVT confers, the less likely they are to believe and
follow some ranting populist playing the cheap
nationalist card to drag a bewildered population into yet
another war.
On that very point, Henry George also believed in
the innate goodness of humanity, and seemed to inspire it
among those who knew him. George was not naïve of
our human flaws, yet was convinced that our system of
land monopoly capitalism had degraded many of our higher
virtues, and herein lay great hope. As Helen Keller said
of George, "Who reads shall find in Henry George's
philosophy a rare beauty and power of inspiration, and a
splendid faith in the essential nobility of human
nature." Contrast this to the cynicism of Hitler, who
wrote in Mein Kampf "If you wish the sympathy of broad
masses, then you must tell them the crudest and most
stupid things."
If Hitler was right, humanity is irredeemable. If
George was right, the principles he enunciated and
elaborated could encourage humanity to such a level of
social development that few would feel the need to
respond to rabble-rousing warmongers. But whatever the
case, it cannot be denied that LVT would greatly reduce
the financial incentive to violently grab natural
resources. ... Read the
entire article
Jeff Smith: How Sharing Earth
Brought Peace
Since forever, humans have claimed and
counter-claimed every square inch of this planet.
Occasionally, these disputes have ended peacefully. What
has worked in other times and places might work again in
the Mideast. Delivering a double dividend, what settled
land disputes also developed moribund economies and
revived developed ones. Among others, New York, now
aiming to rebuild, has used this policy before. Because
it's growing popular among environmentalists, greens
could lead the US to geonomics.
... These cases
involved different classes, not different cultures. Yet
with a new twist the rent rebate that worked within
society may work between societies. The Koran urges
landlords to not gouge tenants but to consider land a
trust. In Israel, admonished to not own
land forever, since the land is Mine (Leviticus), the
National Trust leases all the land to the occupants.
These strictures could lead to geonomics.
Israel and Palestine
would establish a steward to collect land dues and disburse
rent dividends a la Alaska's oil dividend. Since
land is more valuable in Israel than in Palestine, Jews
would pay in more than Arabs, yet everyone would get back
the same. And since Israelis prosper, they drive up land
values; having Jews as co-owners developing land, raising
its value, fattening everyone's Citizens Dividend Arabs
might accept that. Profit does make for strange bedfellows.
Two archrivals, China and Taiwan, recently agreed to
explore for oil together.
While sharing rent may soothe
hurt feelings, collecting it stimulates
development. ...
Using geonomics, people have
turned some of the poorest lands into the richest
economies. Hong Kong is a barren rock owned by the
public. The city collects enough site-rent to keep taxes
on effort way down.
...
Where to draw a line in the sand
becomes a lot less contentious when land and oil are no
longer spoils of war and when neighbors do not endure
drastically different standards of living. Growing up, we
learn to not fight over toys but to take turns. Societies
need to learn this, too.
Early last century, Gifford Pinchot, first head of
the US Forest Service, said: "The earth belongs of right
to all its people and not to a minority, insignificant in
numbers but tremendous in wealth and power. The people
shall get their fair share of the benefit which comes
from the development of the country which belongs to us
all with equal opportunity for all and special privileges
for none." A man in a Republican administration could say
that then. We need to hear it again now.
Read the whole
article
Dave Wetzel: Justice or Injustice: The
Locational Benefit Levy
We all have our own personal interpretation of how
“justice” can be achieved.
Often “justice” is interpreted in a
very narrow legal sense and only in reference to the
judicial system, which has been designed to protect the
status quo. ...
Of course, all citizens (and subjects in the UK)
-- need to know exactly what are the legal boundaries
within which society operates.
But, supposing those original rules are unfair and
unjust. Then the legal framework, being used to
perpetuate an injustice -- does not make that injustice
moral and proper even if within the rules of
jurisprudence it is “legal.”
Obvious examples of this dislocation between
immoral laws and natural justice is
- South Africa's former policy of
apartheid;
- the USA's former segregated schools and
buses;
- discrimination based on race, religion,
disability or sex;
- slavery;
- the oppression of women;
- Victorian Britain's use of child labour and
colonialism.
All these policies were
“lawful” according to the legal framework of
their day but that veneer of legality did not make these
policies righteous and just.
Any society built on a basis of injustice will be
burdened down with its own predisposition towards
self-destruction. Even the most suppressed people will
one-day, demand justice, rise up and overthrow their
oppressors.
Human survival demands justice. Wherever slavery
or dictatorship has been installed -- eventually, justice
has triumphed and a more democratic and fairer system has
replaced it. It is safe to predict that wherever slavery
or dictatorship exists today -- it will be superseded by
a fairer and more just system.
Similarly, let's consider our
distribution of natural resources.
By definition, natural resources are not made by
human effort. Our planet offers every inhabitant a bounty
-- an amazing treasure chest of wealth that can supply
our needs for food, shelter and every aspect for our
survival.
Surely, “justice”
demands that this natural wealth should be equally
available to all and that nobody should starve, be
homeless or suffer poverty simply because they are
excluded from tapping in to this enormous wealth that
nature has provided. ...
If our whole economy, with the
private possession of land and other natural resources,
is built upon an injustice -- then can any of us really
be surprised that we continue to live on a planet where
wars predominate, intolerance is common, crime is rife
and where poverty and starvation is the norm for a huge
percentage of earth's population.
Is this inherited system really the best we can
do?
There must be a method for fairly utilising the
earth's natural resources.
Referring to the rebuilding of
Iraq in his recent speech to the American Congress, Tony
Blair stated “We promised Iraq democratic
Government. We will deliver it. We promised them the
chance to use their oil wealth to build prosperity for
all their citizens, not a corrupt elite. We will do
so”.
Thus, Tony Blair recognises the difference between
political justice in the form of a democratic Government
and economic justice in the form of sharing natural
resources.
We have not heard any dissenting voice from this
promise to share Iraq's natural oil wealth for all the
people of Iraq to enjoy the benefits. But if it is so obviously right and proper for the
Iraqi people to share their natural wealth – why is
it not the practice to do the same in all
nations?
No landowner can create land values. If this were
the case, then an entrepreurial landowner in the Scottish
Highlands would be able to create more value than an
indolent landowner in the City of London.
No, land values arise because of natural
advantages (eg fertility for agricultural land or
approximity to ports or harbours for commercial sites) or
because of the efforts of the whole community -- past and
present investment by both the public and private
sectors, and the activities of individuals all give rise
to land values. Why do we not advocate
the sharing of these land values, which are as much a
gift of nature and probably in most western economies are
worth much more than Iraqi oil? ...
The Location Benefit Levy is a simple way to start
addressing the world's last great injustice.
Read
the whole article
Weld Carter: An
Introduction to Henry George
What is the law of human
progress?
George saw ours alone among the civilizations of
the world as still progressing; all others had either
petrified or had vanished. And in our civilization he had
already detected alarming evidences of corruption and
decay. So he sought out the forces that create
civilization and the forces that destroy it.
He found the incentives to progress
to be the desires inherent in human nature, and the motor
of progress to be what he called mental power. But the
mental power that is available for progress is only what
remains after nonprogressive demands have been met. These
demands George listed as maintenance and
conflict.
In his isolated state, primitive
man's powers are required simply to maintain existence;
only as he begins to associate in communities and to enjoy
the resultant economies is mental power set free for higher
uses. Hence, association is the first essential of
progress:
And as the wasteful expenditure of
mental power in conflict becomes greater or less as the
moral law which accords to each an equality of rights is
ignored or is recognized, equality (or justice) is the
second essential of progress.
Thus association in equality is the
law of progress. Association frees mental power for
expenditure in improvement, and equality, or justice, or
freedom -- for the terms here signify the same thing, the
recognition of the moral law -- prevents the dissipation of
this power in fruitless struggles.
He concluded this phase of his
analysis of civilization in these words: "The law of human
progress, what is it but the moral law? Just as social
adjustments promote justice, just as they acknowledge the
equality of right between man and man, just as they insure
to each the perfect liberty which is bounded only by the
equal liberty of every other, must civilization advance.
Just as they fail in this, must advancing civilization come
to a halt and recede..."
However, as the primary relation of
man is to the earth, so must the primary social adjustment
concern the relation of man to the earth. Only that social
adjustment which affords all mankind equal access to nature
and which insures labor its full earnings will promote
justice, acknowledge equality of right between man and man,
and insure perfect liberty to each.
This, according to George, was what the single tax
would do. It was why he saw the single tax as not merely
a fiscal reform but as the basic reform without which no
other reform could, in the long run, avail. This is why
he said, "What is inexplicable, if we lose sight of man's
absolute and constant dependence upon land, is clear when
we recognize it." ... read the
whole article
Weld Carter: A
Clarion Call to Sanity, to Honesty, to Justice
This world of ours is currently threatened
with disaster of awesome magnitude on two fronts. The
first is the danger of nuclear warfare, most likely
occurring between the United States and the Soviet Union;
the second disaster, of even greater likelihood, is that
the currencies of all the major countries of the world
may soon be rendered worthless by inflation. Because the
possibility of nuclear war may be lessened dramatically
by the elimination of inflation, this article will
address this second horror which currently engulfs us
all.
This paper is predicated on the fact that there is one
reform basic to the extent that no other reform, in its
very nature, can possibly avail until this basic reform
is fully adopted and instituted. The whole tenet of this
paper is to demonstrate the verity of this statement.
The above appeal is based on the obvious fact that our
entire socio-economic order has become riddled with lies,
corruption and injustice. These claims, too, will be
widely verified.
There must come a yearning for sanity, for honesty,
for justice – and now – else we shall surely
perish from the earth. ... read the whole
essay
Judge Samuel Seabury: An Address delivered upon the
100th anniversary of the birth of Henry George
WE are met to celebrate the 100th anniversary of the
birth of Henry George. We meet, therefore, in a spirit of
joy and thanksgiving for the great life which he devoted
to the service of humanity. To very few of the children
of men is it given to act the part of a great teacher who
makes an outstanding contribution toward revealing the
basic principles to which human society must adhere if it
is to walk in the way which leads to freedom. This Henry
George did, and in so doing he expressed himself with a
clarity of thought and diction which has rarely been
surpassed. ...
Henry George's teachings involved more than the
prescription of specific remedies for particular evils.
The specific remedies which he proposed were means to an
end. The end was the philosophy of freedom as applied to
human relations. I do not say that the majority of the
people of the world have given acceptance to many of his
most important teachings. Indeed, in view of the world
tendency since his death to aggrandize the powers of the
political state and limit and subordinate the power of
the people, it is self-evident that in this environment
the principles of Henry George could not have won general
acceptance. Had they done so, the world would have made
greater progress toward the attainment of the goal of
human freedom and economic contentment which is still the
unrealized aspiration of humanity.
Moreover, many who have believed in the necessity for
basic social changes preferred to ignore the simple and
fundamental teachings of Henry George, and to adopt,
instead, the philosophy of Marx and Lenin. It is the wide
acceptance of the doctrines of these false prophets which
has contributed to making the economic condition of the
masses worse, has reduced their standard of living and
has made of Europe an armed camp. It is their disciples
who are now attempting to introduce here the political
and economic theories which in other countries have
culminated in the totalitarian state, together with the
host of iniquities which are inseparably connected with
it.
... The second principle to which I wish to refer is
Henry George's advocacy of freedom of trade among the
nations — not free trade introduced overnight, but
freedom of trade as an end toward which the nations
should move. When he wrote his great work on "Protection
or Free Trade," he demolished the protectionist argument
and in chapter after chapter he showed the absurdities to
which the protectionist principle led if carried to its
logical conclusion. But even he, penetrating as his
vision was, could not foresee that mankind was heading
for a world order of economic nationalism and isolation,
based upon the principle of protection carried to its
utmost extreme. And yet that it is precisely the doctrine
which is now currently accepted. If it becomes general,
it can serve only to sow the seeds of destruction of that
measure of civilization which we now have and force a
lowering of the standard of living throughout the
world.
There are two ways by which the people of one nation
can acquire the property or goods of the people of
another nation. These are by war and by trade. There are
no other methods. The present tendency among civilized
people to outlaw trade must drive the states which
prescribe such outlawry to acquire the property and goods
of other peoples by war. Early in man's struggle for
existence the resort to war was the common method
adopted. With the advancement of civilization men
resorted to trade as a practical substitute for war. The
masses of men wish to trade with one another. The action
of the states alone prevents them from so doing. In
prohibiting trade, the state gives an importance to
territorial boundaries which would not exist if freedom
of trade existed. In accentuating the importance of mere
boundary disputes, rather than assuring the right of
peoples to trade with one another, the nations put the
emphasis upon the precise issue which is, itself, one of
the most prolific causes of war.
All the great modern states are turning away from
freedom of trade, and indeed, from trade itself, and
forbidding their people the right to earn their own
livelihood and to associate freely with one another in
industry. In order to accomplish this end they are
compelled to regiment the lives of their people under
state bureaucracies and this can be accomplished only by
a despotic state. If the powers of the modern states are
to be augmented by conferring upon them the right to run
all industry, despotism is inevitable. A dictator may, by
reducing the standard of living and regimenting the
people, run all industry within the state over which he
rules, but a democracy, which, if it is to be true to
itself, must preserve individual initiative, can not do
so without transforming itself into a dictatorship. ...
read the whole
speech
Peter Barnes:
Capitalism 3.0 — Chapter 2: A Short History of
Capitalism (pages 15-32)
About ten thousand years ago, human agriculture and
permanent settlements arose, and with them came private
property. Rulers granted ownership of land to heads of
families (usually males). Often, military conquerors
distributed land to their lieutenants. Titles could then
be passed to heirs — typically, oldest sons got
everything. ...
read the whole chapter
Henry Ford
Talks About War and Your Future - 1942
interview
|
To share this page with a friend:
right click, choose "send," and add your
comments.
|
|
Red links have not been
visited; .
Green links are pages you've seen
|
Essential Documents pertinent
to this theme:
|
|