Refining Capitalism
Henry George:
Concentrations of Wealth Harm
America(excerpt
from Social
Problems)
(1883)
Capital is a good; the capitalist
is a helper, if he is not also a monopolist. We can
safely let any one get as rich as he can if he will not
despoil others in doing so.
There are deep wrongs in the present
constitution of society, but they are not wrongs inherent
in the constitution of man nor in those social laws which
are as truly the laws of the Creator as are the laws of the
physical universe. They are wrongs resulting from bad
adjustments which it is within our power to amend. The
ideal social state is not that in which each gets an equal
amount of wealth, but in which each gets in proportion to
his contribution to the general stock. And in such a social
state there would not be less incentive to exertion than
now; there would be far more incentive. Men will be more
industrious and more moral, better workmen and better
citizens, if each takes his earnings and carries them home
to his family, than where they put their earnings in a
"pot" and gamble for them until some have far more than
they could have earned, and others have little or
nothing. ...
Read the entire
article Dan Sullivan: Are you a Real Libertarian, or a
ROYAL Libertarian?
The red, red herring
Royal libertarians are fond of confusing the
classical liberal concept of common land ownership,
particularly as espoused by land value tax advocate Henry
George, with socialism. Yet socialists have always been
contemptuous of George and of the distinction between
land monopoly and capital monopolies. However, Frank
Chodorov and Albert J. Nock (the original editors of
The Freeman) were both advocates of George's
economic remedies as well as lovers of individual
liberty.
The only reformer abroad in the world in my
time who interested me in the least was Henry George,
because his project did not contemplate prescription,
but, on the contrary, would reduce it to almost zero. He
was the only one of the lot who believed in freedom, or
(as far as I could see) had any approximation to an
intelligent idea of what freedom is, and of the economic
prerequisites to attaining it....One is immensely tickled
to see how things are coming out nowadays with reference
to his doctrine, for George was in fact the best
friend the capitalist ever had. He built up the
most complete and most impregnable defense of the rights
of capital that was ever constructed, and if the
capitalists of his day had had sense enough to dig in
behind it, their successors would not now be squirming
under the merciless exactions which collectivism is
laying on them, and which George would have no scruples
whatever about describing as sheer highwaymanry.
—Albert J. Nock "Thoughts on Utopia" ...
Read
the whole piece
Louis Post: Outlines
of Louis F. Post's Lectures, with Illustrative Notes and
Charts (1894) — Appendix: FAQ
Q38. Is there no danger that under the single tax
scheming men of great intellect would be able to take
advantage of their less intelligent brethren, and by the
competitive system corral everything as they do
now?
A. If they did, it would not be by the competitive
system, but because the competitive system was still
imperfectly developed. Competition is freedom, and such a
thing as you suggest could not be done where freedom
prevailed. I believe that the single tax would perfect
competition. If it did, and at any rate to the extent
that it did, every one would get what he earned. ...
read the book
Robert V. Andelson Henry George and the
Reconstruction of Capitalism
Land monopoly is the great monkey-wrench which
is caught in the works of the free enterprise system, and
which prevents the proper meshing of its gears; it is the
hidden cancer that is eating out the heart of
Capitalism. Early in this century, a great statesman
described its virulent effects in the following
words:
While the land is what is called
"ripening"for the unearned increment of its owner, the
merchant going to his office and the artisan going to his
work must detour or pay a fare to avoid it. The people
lose their chance of using the land, the city and state
lose the taxes which would have accrued if the natural
development had taken place, and all the while the land
monopolist has only to sit still and watch complacently
his property multiplying in value, sometimes many fold,
without either effort or contribution on his
part.
This evil process strikes at every
form of industrial activity. The municipality, wishing
for broader streets, better houses, more healthy, decent,
scientifically planned towns, is made to pay more to get
them in proportion as it has exerted itself to make past
improvements. The more it has improved the town, the more
it will have to pay for any land it may now wish to
acquire for further improvements.
The manufacturer proposing to start
a new industry, proposing to erect a great factory
offering employment to thousands of hands, is made to pay
such a price for his land that the purchase price hangs
around the neck of his whole business, hampering his
competitive power in every market, clogging him far more
than any foreign tariff in his export competition, and
the land price strikes down through the profits of the
manufacturer on to the wages of the workman.
No matter where you look or what
examples you select, you will see that every form of
enterprise, every step in material progress, is only
undertaken after the land monopolist has skimmed the
cream off for himself, and everywhere today the man or
the public body that wishes to put land to its highest
use is forced to pay a preliminary fine in land values to
the man who is putting it to an inferior use, and in some
cases to no use at all. All comes back to the land value,
and its owner is able to levy toll upon all other forms
of wealth and every form of industry.
Those were the words of Winston Churchill. And
if you will examine the history of the major American
depressions, you will find that virtually every one of them
was preceded by a period of intense land speculation which
had an inflationary effect upon the whole economy. In 1836,
in 1857, in 1873, in 1893, and in 1929 -- in every
instance, the big crash was precipitated by the bursting of
the land bubble. Read the
whole article
Albert Jay Nock — Henry George: Unorthodox
American
Progress and Poverty is the first and only
thorough, complete, scientific inquiry ever made into the
fundamental cause of industrial depressions and
involuntary poverty. The ablest minds of the century
attacked and condemned it — Professor Huxley, the
Duke of Argyll, Goldwin Smith, Leo XIII, Frederic
Harrison, John Bright, Joseph Chamberlain. Nevertheless,
in a preface to the definitive edition, George said what
very few authors of a technical work have ever been able
to say, that he had not met with a single criticism or
objection that was not fully anticipated and answered in
the book itself. For years he debated its basic positions
with any one who cared to try, and was never worsted.
... It is interesting, too, now that successive
depressions are bearing harder and harder on the
capitalist, precisely as George predicted, to observe
that George and his associate anti-monopolists of forty
years ago are turning out to be the best friends that the
capitalist ever had. Standing staunchly for the rights of
capital, as against collectivist proposals to confiscate
interest as well as rent, George formulated a defense of
those rights that is irrefragable. ...read the whole article
Frank Stilwell and Kirrily Jordan: The Political Economy of Land:
Putting Henry George in His Place
Land is the most basic of all economic resources,
fundamental to the form that economic development takes.
Its use for agricultural purposes is integral to the
production of the means of our subsistence. Its use in an
urban context is crucial in shaping how effectively
cities function and who gets the principal benefits from
urban economic growth. Its ownership is a major
determinant of the degree of economic inequality: surges
of land prices, such as have occurred in Australian
cities during the last decade, cause major
redistributions of wealth. In both an urban and rural
context the use of land – and nature more generally
– is central to the possibility of ecological
sustainability. Contemporary social concerns about
problems of housing affordability and environmental
quality necessarily focus our attention on ‘the
land question.’
These considerations indicate the need for a coherent
political economic analysis of land in capitalist
society. Indeed, the analysis of land was central in an
earlier era of political economic analysis. The role of
land in relation to economic production, income
distribution and economic growth was a major concern for
classical political economists, such as Smith, Ricardo
and Malthus. But the intervening years have seen land
slide into a more peripheral status within economic
analysis. Political economists working in the Marxian
tradition have tended to focus primarily on the
capital-labour relation as the key to understanding the
capitalist economy. Neo-classical economists typically
treat land, if they acknowledge it at all, as a
‘factor of production’ equivalent to labour
or capital, thereby obscuring its distinctive features
and differences. Keynesian and post-Keynesian economists
have also given little attention to land because
typically their analyses focus more on consumption,
saving, investment and other economic aggregates.
However, there is an alternative current of political
economic thought for which ‘the land
question’ is central. This is the tradition based
on the ideas of Henry George. This article seeks a
balanced assessment of the usefulness of George’s
ideas in the modern context. It outlines how insights
derived from Georgist thinking can help in dealing with
contemporary economic, social and environmental problems,
while noting deficiencies and additional concerns.
Following a general summary of Georgist ideas and policy
proposals, six themes are addressed:
- the moral issue,
- wealth inequality,
- housing affordability,
- environmental concerns,
- urban development and
- economic cycles.
In each case it is argued that Georgist insights
provide a valuable but incomplete basis for analysis and
policy.
Economic Cycles
Georgists have also frequently claimed to be able to
explain and ameliorate, even resolve, the cyclical
character of the capitalist economy. George argued that a
higher uniform land tax could reduce the severity of
booms and busts in the housing market by reducing the
speculative investment in land. This would produce more
stable economic conditions throughout the economy,
removing the boom-bust cycle to which capitalism is
otherwise prone. It is an argument that has contemporary
Australian relevance because the boom-bust character of
the urban property market is clearly a significant factor
in overall cyclical economic instability. An earlier
article on Australian land price trends by Kavanagh
(2001) has illustrated this connection, demonstrating
that, while the property market is more volatile than the
economy as a whole, there has been a clear temporal
connection between the two patterns of cyclical behaviour
over the last half century. Property booms and busts have
typically coincided with swings in overall national
economic performance. The policy implication is that, by
smoothing out cycles in the housing market, a uniform
land tax could help to avoid periodic crises in
capitalist economies more generally. ...
Georgists have also frequently claimed to be able to
explain and ameliorate, even resolve, the cyclical
character of the capitalist economy. George argued that a
higher uniform land tax could reduce the severity of
booms and busts in the housing market by reducing the
speculative investment in land. This would produce more
stable economic conditions throughout the economy,
removing the boom-bust cycle to which capitalism is
otherwise prone. It is an argument that has contemporary
Australian relevance because the boom-bust character of
the urban property market is clearly a significant factor
in overall cyclical economic instability. An earlier
article on Australian land price trends by Kavanagh
(2001) has illustrated this connection, demonstrating
that, while the property market is more volatile than the
economy as a whole, there has been a clear temporal
connection between the two patterns of cyclical behaviour
over the last half century. Property booms and busts have
typically coincided with swings in overall national
economic performance. The policy implication is that, by
smoothing out cycles in the housing market, a uniform
land tax could help to avoid periodic crises in
capitalist economies more generally.
However, the argument needs to be kept in perspective.
Periodic economic recessions cannot be solely attributed
to speculation in land.
Inadequate levels of aggregate demand, problems of
overproduction, and problems of instability in financial
markets are among other causes of interruptions to the
process of capital accumulation. Land tax cannot feasibly
claim to redress all the systemic contradictions and
malfunctions of a capitalist economy. Additional
counter-cyclical policies are necessary. These include
macroeconomic stabilisers, such as monetary and fiscal
policies, that can contribute to reducing the cyclical
tendency to which the economy is otherwise prone, along
with incomes policy and the more radically
interventionist ‘socialisation of investment’
that Keynes (1936: 378) advocated. So here, too, land tax
seems to have the status of a necessary but not
sufficient condition for progressive economic reform. ...
read the whole
article
Peter Barnes:
Capitalism 3.0: Preface (pages ix.-xvi)
In retrospect, I realized the question I’d been
asking since early adulthood was: Is capitalism a
brilliant solution to the problem of scarcity, or is it
itself modernity’s central problem? The question
has many layers, but explorations of each layer led me to
the same verdict. Although capitalism started as a
brilliant solution, it has become the central problem of
our day. It was right for its time, but times have
changed.
When capitalism started, nature was abundant and
capital was scarce; it thus made sense to reward capital
above all else. Today we’re awash in capital and
literally running out of nature. We’re also losing
many social arrangements that bind us together as
communities and enrich our lives in nonmonetary ways.
This doesn’t mean capitalism is doomed or useless,
but it does mean we have to modify it. We have to adapt
it to the twenty-first century rather than the
eighteenth. ...
read the whole chapter
Peter Barnes:
Capitalism 3.0 — Chapter 1: Time to Upgrade (pages
3-14)
Can we imagine, design, and install an upgraded
operating system that fixes these flaws? This may seem a
far-fetched dream. But consider that something comparable
happened before, in 1935, with the enactment of Social
Security.
Like the changes I’m suggesting here, Social
Security is an intergenerational compact, engraved into
our economic operating system. It was imagined, designed,
and installed early in the twentieth century in response
to what was then a looming crisis: the impoverishment of
millions too old to work. The basic contract was, and
remains, simple: active workers collectively support
retired workers, and in return are supported in old age
by the next generation of workers. For seventy years,
this contract has been administered without scandal or
waste by a trust fund that has never missed a payment.
Thanks to this operating system upgrade, extreme old-age
poverty, once rampant, is largely a thing of the
past.
What we need now is a comparable system upgrade, this
time to fix capitalism’s disregard for nature,
future generations, and the nonelderly poor. ...
read the whole chapter
Peter Barnes:
Capitalism 3.0 — Chapter 2: A Short History of
Capitalism (pages 15-32)
Before we consider how to upgrade our economic
operating system, it’s worth contemplating how it
came to be. Two parallel threads emerge: the decline of
the commons and the ascent of private corporations.
...
Why isn’t economic growth making us
happier? There are many possibilities, and
they’re additive rather than exclusive.
- One is that, once material needs are met,
happiness is based on comparative rather than absolute
conditions. If your neighbors have bigger
houses than you do, the fact that yours is smaller
diminishes your happiness, even though your house by
itself meets your needs. In the same way, more income
wouldn’t make you happier if other people got
even more. That’s why an affluent country can get
richer without its citizens getting happier.
- A second reason is that surplus capitalism
foments anxiety. Millions live one paycheck,
or one illness, away from disaster. When disaster
strikes, the safety nets beneath them are thin. And
everyone sees jobs vanishing as capital scours the
planet for cheap labor.
- Another reason is that surplus capitalism
speeds up life and creates great stress.
Humans didn’t evolve to multitask, sit in traffic
jams, or work, shop, and pay bills 24/7. We need rest,
relaxation, and time for companionship and creativity.
Surplus capitalism can’t give us enough of those
things.
- Similarly, its nonstop marketing message
— you’re no good without Brand X —
breeds the opposites of gratitude and contentment, two
widely acknowledged precursors of happiness.
According to the Union of Concerned Scientists, the
average American encounters about three thousand such
messages each day. No wonder we experience envy, greed,
and dissatisfaction. ...
read the whole chapter
Peter Barnes:
Capitalism 3.0 — Chapter 7: Universal Birthrights
(pages 101-116)
The perennially popular board game Monopoly is a
reasonable simulacrum of capitalism. At the beginning of
the game, players move around a commons and try to
privatize as much as they can. The player who privatizes
the most invariably wins.
But Monopoly has two features currently lacking in
American capitalism: all players start with the same
amount of capital, and all receive $200 each time they
circle the board. Absent these features, the game would
lack fairness and excitement, and few would choose to
play it.
Imagine, for example, a twenty-player version of
Monopoly in which one player starts with half the
property. The player with half the property would win
almost every time, and other players would fold almost
immediately. Yet that, in a nutshell, is U.S. capitalism
today: the top 5 percent of the population owns more
property than the remaining 95 percent.
Now imagine, if you will, a set of rules for
capitalism closer to the actual rules of Monopoly. In
this version, every player receives, not an equal amount
of start-up capital, but enough to choose among several
decent careers. Every player also receives dividends once
a year, and simple, affordable health insurance. This
version of capitalism produces more happiness for more
people than our current version, without ruining the game
in any way. Indeed, by reducing lopsided starting
conditions and relieving employers of health insurance
costs, it makes our economy more competitive and
productive.
If you doubt the preceding proposition, consider the
economic operating systems of professional baseball,
football, and basketball. Each league shifts money from
the richest teams to the poorest, and gives losing teams
first crack at new players. Even George Will, the
conservative columnist, sees the logic in this:
“The aim is not to guarantee teams equal revenues,
but revenues sufficient to give each team periodic
chances of winning if each uses its revenues
intelligently.” Absent such revenue sharing, Will
explains, teams in twenty of the thirty major-league
cities would have no chance of winning, fans would drift
away, and even the wealthy teams would suffer. Too much
inequality, in other words, is bad for everyone. ...
read the whole chapter
|
To share this page with a friend:
right click, choose "send," and add your
comments.
|
|
Red links have not been
visited; .
Green links are pages you've seen
|
Essential Documents pertinent
to this theme:
|
|