Taxes' Effects
Henry George: The
Common Sense of Taxation (1881 article)
The true purposes of government are well stated in the
preamble to the Constitution of the United States, as
they are in the Declaration of Independence. To insure
the general peace, to promote the general welfare, to
secure to each individual the inalienable rights to life,
liberty, and the pursuit of happiness — these are
the proper ends of government, and are therefore the ends
which in every scheme of taxation should be kept in
mind.
As to amount of taxation, there is no principle which
imposes any arbitrary limit. Heavy taxation is better for
any community than light taxation, if the increased
revenue be used in doing by public agencies things which
could not be done, or could not be as well and
economically done, by private agencies. Taxes could be
lightened in the city of New York by dispensing with
street-lamps and disbanding the police force. But would a
reduction in taxation gained in this way be for the
benefit of the people of New York and make New York a
more desirable place to live in? Or if it should be found
that heat and light could be conducted through the
streets at public expense and supplied to each house at
but a small fraction of the cost of supplying them by
individual effort, or that the city railroads could be
run at public expense so as to give every one
transportation at very much less than it now costs the
average resident, the increased taxation necessary for
these purposes would not be increased burden, and in
spite of the larger taxation required, New York would
become a more desirable place to live in. It is a mistake
to condemn taxation as bad merely because it is high; it
is a mistake to impose by constitutional provision, as in
many of our States has been advocated, and in some of our
States has been done, any restriction upon the amount of
taxation. A restriction upon the incurring of public
indebtedness is another matter. In nothing is the
far-reaching statesmanship of Jefferson more clearly
shown than in his proposition that all public obligations
should be deemed void after a certain brief term —
a proposition which he grounds upon the self-evident
truth that the earth belongs in usufruct to the living,
and that the dead have no control over it, and can give
no title to any part of it. But restriction upon public
debts is a very different thing from restriction upon the
power of taxation, and reasons which urge the one do not
apply to the other. Nor is increased taxation necessarily
proof of governmental extravagance. Increase in taxation
is in the order of social development, for the reason
that social development tends to the doing of things
collectively that in a ruder state are done individually,
to the giving to government of new functions and the
imposing of new duties. Our public schools and libraries
and parks, our signal service and fish commissions and
agricultural bureaus and grasshopper investigations, are
evidences of this.
But while no limit can be properly fixed for the
amount of taxation, the method of taxation is of supreme
importance. A horse may be anchored by fastening to his
bridle a weight which he will not feel when carried in a
buggy behind him. The best ship may be made utterly
unseaworthy by the bad stowage of a cargo which properly
placed would make her the stiffer and more weatherly. So
enterprise may be palsied, industry crushed, accumulation
prevented, and a prosperous country turned into a desert,
by taxation which rightly levied would hardly be felt.
...
To consider the nature of property of this kind is
again to see a clear distinction. That distinction is
not, as the lawyers have it, between movables and
immovables, between personal property and real estate.
The true distinction is between property which is, and
property which is not, the result of human labor; or, to
use the terms of political economy, between land and
wealth. For, in any precise use of the term, land is not
wealth, any more than labor is wealth. Land and labor are
the factors of production. Wealth is such result of their
union as retains the capacity of ministering to human
desire. A lot and the house which stands upon it are
alike property, alike have a tangible value, and are
alike classed as real estate. But there are between them
the most essential differences. The one is the free gift
of Nature, the other the result of human exertion; the
one exists from generation to generation, while men come
and go; the other is constantly tending to decay, and can
only be preserved by continual exertion. To the one, the
right of exclusive possession, which makes it individual
property, can, like the right of property in slaves, be
traced to nothing but municipal law; to the other, the
right of exclusive property springs clearly from those
natural relations which are among the primary perceptions
of the human mind. Nor are these mere abstract
distinctions. They are distinctions of the first
importance in determining what should and what should not
be taxed.
For, keeping in mind the fact that all wealth is the
result of human exertion, it is clearly seen that, having
in view the promotion of the general prosperity, it is
the height of absurdity to tax wealth for purposes of
revenue while there remains, unexhausted by taxation, any
value attaching to land. We may tax land values as much
as we please, without in the slightest degree lessening
the amount of land, or the capabilities of land, or the
inducement to use land. But we cannot tax wealth without
lessening the inducement to the production of wealth, and
decreasing the amount of wealth. We might take the whole
value of land in taxation, so as to make the ownership of
land worth nothing, and the land would still remain, and
be as useful as before. The effect would be to throw land
open to users free of price, and thus to increase its
capabilities, which are brought out by increased
population. But impose anything like such taxation upon
wealth, and the inducement to the production of wealth
would be gone. Movable wealth would be hidden or carried
off, immovable wealth would be suffered to go to decay,
and where was prosperity would soon be the silence of
desolation.
And the reason of this difference is clear. The
possession of wealth is the inducement to the exertion
necessary to the production and maintenance of wealth.
Men do not work for the pleasure of working, but to get
the things their work will give them. And to tax the
things that are produced by exertion is to lessen the
inducement to exertion. But over and above the benefit to
the possessor, which is the stimulating motive to the
production of wealth, there is a benefit to the
community, for no matter how selfish he may be, it is
utterly impossible for any one to entirely keep to
himself the benefit of any desirable thing he may
possess. These diffused benefits when localized give
value to land, and this may be taxed without in any wise
diminishing the incentive to production.
To illustrate: A man builds a fine house or large
factory in a poorly improved neighborhood. To tax this
building and its adjuncts is to make him pay for his
enterprise and expenditure — to take from him part
of his natural reward. But the improvement thus made has
given new beauty or life to the neighborhood, making it a
more desirable place than before for the erection of
other houses or factories, and additional value is given
to land all about. Now to tax improvements is not only to
deprive of his proper reward the man who has made the
improvement, but it is to deter others from making
similar improvements. But, instead of taxing
improvements, to tax these land values is to leave the
natural inducement to further improvement in full force,
and at the same time to keep down an obstacle to further
improvement, which, under the present system, improvement
itself tends to raise. For the advance of land values
which follows improvement, and even the expectation of
improvement, makes further improvement more costly.
See how unjust and short-sighted is this system. Here
is a man who, gathering what little capital he can, and
taking his family, starts West to find a place where he
can make himself a home. He must travel long distances;
for, though he will pass plenty of land nobody is using,
it is held at prices too high for him. Finally he will go
no further, and selects a place where, since the creation
of the world, the soil, so far as we know, has never felt
a plowshare. But here, too, in nine cases out of ten, he
will find the speculator has been ahead of him, for the
speculator moves quicker, and has superior means of
information to the emigrant. Before he can put this land
to the use for which nature intended it, and to which it
is for the general good that it should be put, he must
make terms with some man who in all probability never saw
the land, and never dreamed of using it, and who, it may
be, resides in some city, thousands of miles away. In
order to get permission to use this land, he must give up
a large part of the little capital which is seed-wheat to
him, and perhaps in addition mortgage his future labor
for years. Still he goes to work: he works himself, and
his wife works, and his children work — work like
horses, and live in the hardest and dreariest manner.
Such a man deserves encouragement, not discouragement;
but on him taxation falls with peculiar severity. Almost
everything that he has to buy — groceries,
clothing, tools — is largely raised in price by a
system of tariff taxation which cannot add to the price
of the grain or hogs or cattle that he has to sell. And
when the assessor comes around he is taxed on the
improvements he has made, although these improvements
have added not only to the value of surrounding land, but
even to the value of land in distant commercial centers.
Not merely this, but, as a general rule, his land,
irrespective of the improvements, will be assessed at a
higher rate than unimproved land around it, on the ground
that "productive property" ought to pay more than
"unproductive property" — a principle just the
reverse of the correct one, for the man who makes land
productive adds to the general prosperity, while the man
who keeps land unproductive stands in the way of the
general prosperity, is but a dog-in-the-manger, who
prevents others from using what he will not use
himself.
Or, take the case of the railroads. That railroads are
a public benefit no one will dispute. We want more
railroads, and want them to reduce their fares and
freight. Why then should we tax them? for taxes upon
railroads deter from railroad building, and compel higher
charges. Instead of taxing the railroads, is it not clear
that we should rather tax the increased value which they
give to land? To tax railroads is to check railroad
building, to reduce profits, and compel higher rates; to
tax the value they give to land is to increase railroad
business and permit lower rates. The elevated railroads,
for instance, have opened to the overcrowded population
of New York the wide, vacant spaces of the upper part of
the island. But this great public benefit is neutralized
by the rise in land values. Because these vacant lots can
be reached more cheaply and quickly, their owners demand
more for them, and so the public gain in one way is
offset in another, while the roads lose the business they
would get were not building checked by the high prices
demanded for lots. The increase of land values, which the
elevated roads have caused, is not merely no advantage to
them — it is an injury; and it is clearly a public
injury. The elevated railroads ought not to be taxed. The
more profit they make, with the better conscience can
they be asked to still further reduce fares. It is the
increased land values which they have created that ought
to be taxed, for taxing them will give the public the
full benefit of cheap fares.
So with railroads everywhere. And so not alone with
railroads, but with all industrial enterprises. So long
as we consider that community most prosperous which
increases most rapidly in wealth, so long is it the
height of absurdity for us to tax wealth in any of its
beneficial forms. We should tax what we want to
repress, not what we want to encourage. We should tax
that which results from the general prosperity, not that
which conduces to it. It is the increase of
population, the extension of cultivation, the manufacture
of goods, the building of houses and ships and railroads,
the accumulation of capital, and the growth of commerce
that add to the value of land — not the increase in
the value of land that induces the increase of population
and increase of wealth. It is not that the land of
Manhattan Island is now worth hundreds of millions where,
in the time of the early Dutch settlers, it was only
worth dollars, that there are on it now so many more
people, and so much more wealth. It is because of the
increase of population and the increase of wealth that
the value of the land has so much increased. Increase of
land values tends of itself to repel population and
prevent improvement. And thus the taxation of land
values, unlike taxation of other property, does not tend
to prevent the increase of wealth, but rather to
stimulate it. It is the taking of the golden egg, not the
choking of the goose that lays it.
Every consideration of policy and ethics squares with
this conclusion. The tax upon land values is the
most economically perfect of all taxes. It does not raise
prices; it maybe collected at least cost, and with the
utmost ease and certainty; it leaves in full strength all
the springs of production; and, above all, it consorts
with the truest equality and the highest justice. For, to
take for the common purposes of the community that value
which results from the growth of the community, and to
free industry and enterprise and thrift from burden and
restraint, is to leave to each that which he fairly
earns, and to assert the first and most comprehensive of
equal rights — the equal right of all to the land
on which, and from which, all must live.
Thus it is that the scheme of taxation which conduces
to the greatest production is also that which conduces to
the fairest distribution, and that in the proper
adjustment of taxation lies not merely the possibility of
enormously increasing the general wealth, but the
solution of these pressing social and political problems
which spring from unnatural inequality in the
distribution of wealth.
"There is," says M. de Laveleye, in concluding that
work in which he shows that the first perceptions of
mankind have everywhere recognized a most vital
distinction between property in land and property which
results from labor, — "there is in human affairs
one system which is the best; it is not that system which
always exists, otherwise why should we desire to change
it; but it is that system which should exist for the
greatest good of humanity. God knows it, and wills it;
man's duty it is to discover and establish it." ...
read the whole
article
Henry George: Why The
Landowner Cannot Shift The Tax on Land Values
(1887)
A VERY common objection to the proposition to
concentrate all taxes on Land Values is that the
landowner would add the increased tax on the value of his
land to the rent that must be paid by his tenants. It is
this notion that increased Taxation of Land Values would
fall upon the users, not upon the owners of land, that
more perhaps than anything else prevents men from seeing
the far-reaching and beneficent effects of doing away
with the taxes that now fall upon labor or the products
of labor, and taking for public use those values that
attach to land by reason of the growth and progress of
society.
That taxes levied upon Land Values, or, to use the
politico-economic term, taxes levied upon rent, do not
fall upon the user of land, and cannot be transferred by
the landlord to the tenant is conceded by all economists
of reputation. However much they may dispute as to other
things, there is no dispute upon this point. Whatever
flimsy reasons any of them may have deemed it expedient
to give why the tax on rent should not be more resorted
to, they all admit that the taxation of rent merely
diminishes the profits of the landowner, cannot be
shifted on the user of land, cannot add to prices, nor
check production. ...
The reason of this will be clear to everyone
who has grasped the accepted theory of rent — that
theory to which the name of Ricardo has been given, and
which, as John Stuart Mill says, has but to be understood
to be proved. And it will be clear to everyone who will
consider a moment, even if he has never before thought of
the cause and nature of rent. The rent of land represents
a return to ownership over and above the return which is
sufficient to induce use — it is a premium paid for
permission to use. To take, in taxation, a part or the
whole of this premium in no way affects the incentive to
use or the return to use; in no way diminishes the amount
of land there is to use, or makes it more difficult to
obtain it for use. Thus there is no way in which a tax
upon rent or Land Values can be transferred to the user.
Whatever the State may demand of this premium simply
diminishes the net amount which ownership can get for the
use of land, or the price it can demand as purchase
money, which is, of course, rent or the expectation of
rent, capitalized. ...
But while the Taxation of Land Values cannot raise
rents, it would, especially in a country like this, where
there is so much valuable land unused, tend strongly to
lower them. In all our cities, and through all the
country, there is much land which is not used, or not put
to its best use, because it is held at high prices by men
who do not want to, or who cannot, use it themselves, but
who are holding it in expectation of profiting by the
increased value which the growth of population will give
to it in the future. Now the effect of the Taxation of
Land Values would be to compel these men to seek tenants
or purchasers. ...
It is also necessary to bear in mind
that the value of land is something totally distinct from
the value of improvements. It is a value which arises not
from the exertion of any particular individual, but from
the growth and progress of the community. A tax on Land
Values, therefore, never lessens the reward of exertion or
accumulation. It simply takes for the whole community that
value which the whole community creates.
While it is not true that a tax on
Land Values or rent falls on the user, and thus distributes
itself through increased prices, it is true that the
greater number of taxes by which our public revenues are
raised do. Thus, speaking
generally, taxes upon capital fall, not upon the owners of
capital, but upon the users of capital, and are by them
transferred to the consumers of whatever the capital is
used to produce; taxes upon buildings or building materials
must ultimately be paid in increased building rents or
prices by the occupiers of buildings; imposts upon
production or duties upon imports must finally fall upon
the consumer of the commodities. This fact is far from
being popularly appreciated, for, if it were, the masses
would never consent to the system by which the greater part
of our revenues is raised. But, nevertheless, it is the
vague apprehension of this that leads by confusion of ideas
to the notion that a tax on Land Values must add to rents.
This notion will disappear if it be considered how it is
that any tax gives to the person first called on to pay it
the power of shifting it upon others by an increase of
price.
A tax on matches, for instance, will,
as we know by experience, enable the manufacturer or dealer
in matches to get a higher price. How? Evidently by adding
to the cost of producing matches for sale, thus checking
the supply of matches that can be offered for sale until
the price rises sufficiently to compensate for the tax. It
is this knowledge that the tax will add to the cost of
production, and thus, below a certain price, check
competition in supply, that enables the dealer to mark up
the price of his stock of matches as soon as the tax is
imposed, or compels him to mark it down as soon as the tax
is remitted.
But a tax on Land Values does not add
to the cost of producing land. Land is not a thing of human
production. Man does not produce land! He finds it already
in existence when he comes into the world. Its price,
therefore, is not fixed by the cost of production, but is
always the highest price that anyone can give for the
privilege of using a particular piece. Land, unlike things
that must be constantly produced by labor, has no normal
value based on the cost of production, but ranges in value
from nothing at all to the enormous values that attach to
choice sites in great cities, or to mineral deposits of
superior richness, when the growth of population causes a
demand for their use.
Hence a tax on Land Values, instead
of enabling the holder of land to charge that much more for
his land, gives him no power to charge an additional penny.
On the contrary, by making it more costly to hold land
idle, it tends to increase the amount of land which owners
must strive to secure tenants or purchasers for. Thus the
effect of a tax on Land Values is not to increase the rent
that the tenant must pay the owner for the use of the land,
but rather to reduce it. And since the tax must be paid out
of what the land will yield the owner, its effect would be
to reduce the price for which the land could be sold
outright. ...
The general principle which
determines the incidence of taxation is this: A tax upon
anything or upon the methods or means of production of
anything, the price of which is kept down by the ability to
produce increased supplies, will, by increasing the cost of
production, check supply, and thus add to the price of that
thing, and ultimately fall on the consumer. But a tax upon
anything of which the supply is fixed or monopolized, and
of which the cost of production is not therefore a
determining element, since it has no effect in checking
supply, does not increase prices, and falls entirely on the
owner.
In view of the efforts that are made to befog the
popular mind on this point, I have deemed it worth while
to show why taxes on Land Values cannot be shifted by
landlords upon their tenants. But the fact that such a
tax cannot be so shifted is realized well enough by
landowners. Else why the opposition to the Single Tax,
and why the cry of “confiscation?” Our
national experience, like the experience of every other
country, proves that those who are called on to pay a tax
that can be shifted on others, seldom or ever oppose it,
but frequently favor it, and that when once imposed, they
generally resist its abolition. But did anyone ever hear
of landlords welcoming a tax on Land Values, or opposing
the abolition of such a tax? read the whole article
Louis Post: Outlines
of Louis F. Post's Lectures, with Illustrative Notes and
Charts (1894)
II. THE SINGLE TAX AS A
FISCAL REFORM
1. DIRECT AND INDIRECT
TAXATION
Taxes are either direct or indirect; or, as they have
been aptly described, "straight" or "crooked." Indirect
taxes are those that may be shifted by the first payer
from himself to others; direct taxes are those that
cannot be shifted.5
5. "Taxes are either direct or indirect.
A direct tax is one which is demanded from the very
persons who, it is intended or desired, should pay it.
Indirect taxes are those which are demanded from one
person in the expectation and intention that he shall
indemnify himself at the expense of another." —
John Stuart Mill's Prin. of Pol. Ec., book v, ch. iii,
sec. I.
"Direct taxes are those which are levied
on the very persons who it is intended or desired
should pay them, and which they cannot put off upon
others by raising the prices of the taxed article.. . .
Indirect taxes on the other hand are those which are
levied on persons who expect to get back the amount of
the tax by raising the price of the taxed article."
— Laughlin's Elements, par. 249.
Taxes are direct "when the payment is
made by the person who is intended to bear the
sacrifice." Indirect taxes are recovered from final
purchasers. — Jevons's Primer, sec. 96.
"Indirect taxes are so called because
they are not paid into the treasury by the person who
really bears the burden. The payer adds the amount of
the tax to the price of the commodity taxed, and thus
the taxation is concealed under the increased price of
some article of luxury or convenience." —
Thompson's Pol. Ec., sec. 175.
The shifting of indirect taxes is accomplished by
means of their tendency to increase the prices of
commodities on which they fall. Their magnitude and
incidence 6 are thereby disguised. It was for this reason
that a great French economist of the last century
denounced them as "a scheme for so plucking geese as to
get the most feathers with the least squawking."7
6. Jevons defines the incidence of a tax
as "the manner in which it falls upon different classes
of the population." — Jevons's Primer, sec.
96.
Sometimes called "repercussion," and refers "to the
real as opposed to the nominal payment of taxes."
— Ely's Taxation, p. 64.
7. Though his language was blunt, the
sentiment does not essentially differ from that of
"statesmen" of our day who meet all the moral and
economic objections to indirect taxation with the one
reply that the people would not consent to pay enough
or the support of government if public revenues were
collected from them directly. This means nothing but
that the people are actually hoodwinked by indirect
taxation into sustaining a government that they would
not support if they knew it was maintained at their
expense; and instead of being a reason for continuing
indirect taxation, would, if true, be one of the
strongest of reasons for abolishing it. It is
consistent neither with the plainest principles of
democracy nor the simplest conceptions of morality.
Indirect taxation costs the real tax-payers much more
than the government receives, partly because the
middlemen through whose hands taxed commodities pass are
able to exact compound profits upon the tax,8 and partly
on account of extraordinary expenses of original
collection;9 it favors corruption in government by
concealing from the people the fact that they contribute
to the support of government; and it tends, by
obstructing production, to crush legitimate industry and
establish monopolies.10 The questions it raises are of
vastly more concern than is indicated by the sum total of
public expenditures.
8. A tax upon shoes, paid in the first
instance by shoe manufacturers, enters into
manufacturers' prices, and, together with the usual
rate of profit upon that amount of investment, is
recovered from wholesalers. The tax and the
manufacturers' profit upon it then constitute part of
the wholesale price and are collected from retailers.
The retailers in turn collect the tax with all
intermediate profits upon it, together with their
:usual rate of profit upon the whole, from final
purchasers -- the consumers of shoes. Thus what appears
on the surface to be a tax upon shoe manufacturers
proves upon examination to be an indirect tax upon shoe
consumers, who pay in an accumulation of profits upon
the tax considerably more than the government
receives.
The effect would be the same if a tax
upon their leather output were imposed upon tanners.
Tanners would add to the price of leather the amount of
the tax, plus their usual rate of profit upon a like
investment, and collect the whole, together with the
cost of hides, of transportation, of tanning and of
selling, from shoe manufacturers, who would collect
with their profit from retailers, who would collect
with their profit from shoe consumers. The principle
applies also when taxes are levied upon the stock or
the sales of merchants, or the money or credits of
bankers; merchants add the tax with the usual profit to
the prices of their goods, and bankers add it to their
interest and discounts.
For example; a tax of $100,000 upon the
output of manufacturers or importers would, at 10 per
cent as the manufacturing profit, cost wholesalers
$110,000; at a profit of 10 per cent to wholesalers it
would cost retailers $121,000, and at 20 percent profit
to retailers it would finally impose a tax burden of
$145,200 — being 45 per cent more than the
government would get. Upon most commodities the number
of profits exceeds three, so that indirect taxes may
frequently cost as much as 100 per cent, even when
imposed only upon what are commercially known as
finished goods; when imposed upon materials also, the
cost of collection might well run far above 200 percent
in addition to the first cost of maintaining the
machinery of taxation.
It must not be supposed, however, that
the recovery of indirect taxes from the ultimate
consumers of taxed goods is arbitrary. When shoe
manufacturers, or tanners, or merchants add taxes to
prices, or bankers add them to interest, it is not
because they might do otherwise but choose to do this;
it is because the exigencies of trade compel them.
Manufacturers, merchants, and other tradesmen who carry
on competitive businesses must on the average sell
their goods at cost plus the ordinary rate of profit,
or go out of business. It follows that any increase in
cost of production tends to increase the price of
products. Now, a tax upon the output of business men,
which they must pay as a condition of doing their
business, is as truly part of the cost of their output
as is the price of the materials they buy or the wages
of the men they hire. Therefore, such a tax upon
business men tends to increase the price of their
products. And this tendency is more or less marked as
the tax is more or less great and competition more or
less keen.
It is true that a moderate tax upon
monopolized products, such as trade-mark goods,
proprietary medicines, patented articles and copyright
publications is not necessarily shifted to consumers.
The monopoly manufacturer whose prices are not checked
by cost of production, and are therefore as a rule
higher than competitive prices would be, may find it
more profitable to bear the burden of a tax that leaves
him some profit, by preserving his entire custom, than
to drive off part of his custom by adding the tax to
his usual prices. This is true also of a moderate
import tax to the extent it falls upon goods that are
more cheaply transported from the place of production
to a foreign market where the import tax is imposed
than to a home market where the goods would be free of
such a tax — products, for instance, of a farm in
Canada near to a New York town, but far away from any
Canadian town. If the tax be less than the difference
in the cost of transportation the producer will bear
the burden of it; otherwise he will not. The ultimate
effect would be a reduction in the value of the
Canadian land. Examples which may be cited in
opposition to the principle that import taxes are
indirect, will upon examination prove to be of the
character here described. Business cannot be carried on
at a loss — not for long.
9. "To collect taxes, to prevent and
punish evasions, to check and countercheck revenue
drawn from so many distinct sources, now make up
probably three-fourths, perhaps seven-eighths, of the
business of government outside of the preservation of
order, the maintenance of the military arm, and the
administration of justice." — Progress and
Poverty, book iv, ch: v
10. For a brief and thorough exposition
of indirect taxation read George's "Protection or Free
Trade," ch. viii, on " Tariffs for Revenue."
Whoever calmly reflects and candidly decides upon the
merits of indirect taxation must reject it in all its
forms. But to do that is to make a great stride toward
accepting the single tax. For the single tax is a form of
direct taxation; it cannot be shifted.11
11. This is usually a stumbling block to
those who, without much experience in economic thought,
consider the single tax for the first time. As soon as
they grasp the idea that taxes upon commodities shift
to consumers they jump to the conclusion that similarly
taxes upon land values would shift to the users. But
this is a mistake, and the explanation is simple. Taxes
upon what men produce make production more difficult
and so tend toward scarcity in the supply, which
stimulates prices; but taxes upon land, provided the
taxes be levied in proportion to value, tend toward
plenty in supply (meaning market supply of course),
because they make it more difficult to hold valuable
land idle, and so depress prices.
"A tax on rent falls wholly on the
landlord. There are no means by which he can shift the
burden upon anyone else. . . A tax on rent, therefore,
has no effect other than its obvious one. It merely
takes so much from the landlord and transfers it to the
state." — John Stuart Mill's Prin. of Pol. Ec.,
book v, ch. iii, sec. 1.
"A tax laid upon rent is borne solely by
the owner of land." — Bascom's Tr., p.159.
"Taxes which are levied on land . . .
really fall on the owner of the land." — Mrs.
Fawcett's Pol. Ec. for Beginners, pp.209, 210.
"A land tax levied in proportion to the
rent of land, and varying with every variation of
rents, . . . will fall wholly on the landlords."
— Walker's Pol. Ec., ed. of¥ 1887, p. 413,
quoting Ricardo.
"The power of transferring a tax from
the person who actually pays it to some other person
varies with the object taxed. A tax on rents cannot be
transferred. A tax on commodities is always transferred
to the consumer." — Thorold Rogers's Pol. Ec.,
ch. xxi, 2d ed., p. 285.
"Though the landlord is in all cases the
real contributor, the tax is commonly advanced by the
tenant, to whom the landlord is obliged to allow it in
payment of the rent." — Adam Smith's Wealth of
Nations, book v, ch. ii, part ii, art. i.
"The way taxes raise prices is by
increasing the cost of production and checking supply.
But land is not a thing of human production, and taxes
upon rent cannot check supply. Therefore, though a tax
upon rent compels land-owners to pay more, it gives
them no power to obtain more for the use of their land,
as it in no way tends to reduce the supply of land. On
the contrary, by compelling those who hold land on
speculation to sell or let for what they can get, a tax
on land values tends to increase the competition
between owners, and thus to reduce the price of land."
— Progress and Poverty, book viii, ch. iii, subd.
i.
Sometimes this point is raised as a
question of shifting the tax in higher rent to the
tenant, and at others as a question of shifting it to
the consumers of goods in higher prices. The principle
is the same. Merchants cannot charge higher prices for
goods than their competitors do, merely because they
pay higher ground rents. A country storekeeper whose
business lot is worth but few dollars charges as much
for sugar, probably more, than a city grocer whose lot
is worth thousands. Quality for quality and quantity
for quantity, goods sell for about the same price
everywhere. Differences in price are altogether in
favor of places where land has a high value. This is
due to the fact that the cost of getting goods to
places of low land value, distant villages for example,
is greater than to centers, which are places of high
land value. Sometimes it is true that prices for some
things are higher where land values are high. Tiffany's
goods, for instance, may be more expensive than goods
of the same quality at a store on a less expensive
site. But that is not due to the higher land value; it
is because the dealer has a reputation for technical
knowledge and honesty (or has become a fad among rich
people), for which his customers are willing to pay
whether his store is on a high priced-lot or a
low-priced one.
Though land value has no effect upon the
price of good, it is easier to sell goods in some
locations than in others. Therefore, though the price
and the profit of each sale be the same, or even less,
in good locations than in poorer ones, aggregate
receipts and aggregate profits are much greater at the
good location. And it is out of his aggregate, and not
out of each profit, that rent is paid, For example: A
cigar store on a thoroughfare supplies a certain
quality of cigar for fifteen cents. On a side street
the same quality of cigar can be bought no cheaper.
Indeed, the cigars there are likely to be poorer, and
therefore really dearer. Yet ground rent on the
thoroughfare is very high compared with ground rent on
the sidestreet. How, then, can the first dealer, he who
pays the high ground rent, afford to sell as good or
better cigars for fifteen cents than his competitor of
the low priced location? Simply because he is able to
make so many more sales with a given outlay of labor
and capital in a given time that his aggregate profit
is greater. This is due to the advantage of his
location, and for that advantage he pays a premium in
higher ground rent. But that premium is not charged to
smokers; the competing dealer of the side street
protects them. It represents the greater ease, the
lower cost, of doing a given volume of business upon
the site for which it is paid; add if the state should
take any of it, even the whole of it, in taxation, the
loss would be finally borne by the owner of the
advantage which attaches to that site — by the
landlord. Any attempt to shift it to tenant or buyer
would be promptly checked by the competition of
neighboring but cheaper land.
"A land-tax, levied in proportion to the
rent of land, and varying with every variation of rent,
is in effect a tax on rent; and as such a tax will not
apply to that land which yields no rent, nor to the
produce of that capital which is employed on the land
with a view to profit merely, and which never pays
rent; it will not in any way affect the price of raw
produce, but will fall wholly on the landlords."
— McCulloch's Ricardo (3d ed.), p. 207
2. THE TWO KINDS OF DIRECT
TAXATION
Direct taxes fall into two general classes: (1) Taxes
that are levied upon men in proportion to their ability
to pay, and (2) taxes that are levied in proportion to
the benefits received by the tax-payer from the public.
Income taxes are the principal ones of the first class,
though probate and inheritance taxes would rank high. The
single tax is the only important one of the second
class.
There should be no difficulty in choosing between the
two. To tax in proportion to ability to pay, regardless
of benefits received, is in accord with no principle of
just government; it is a device of piracy. The single
tax, therefore, as the only important tax in proportion
to benefits, is the ideal tax.
But here we encounter two plausible objections. One
arises from the mistaken but common notion that men are
not taxed in proportion to benefits unless they pay taxes
upon every kind of property they own that comes under the
protection of government; the other is founded in the
assumption that it is impossible to measure the value of
the public benefits that each individual enjoys. Though
the first of these objections ostensibly accepts the
doctrine of taxation according to benefits,12 yet, as it
leads to attempts at taxation in proportion to wealth,
it, like the other, is really a plea for the piratical
doctrine of taxation according to ability to pay. The two
objections stand or fall together.
12. It is often said, for instance, by
its advocates, that house owners should in justice
contribute to the support of the fire departments that
protect them and it is even gravely argued that houses
are more appropriate subjects of taxation than land;
because they need protection, whereas land needs none.
Read note 8.
Let it once be perceived that the value of the service
which government renders to each individual would be
justly measured by the single tax, and neither objection
would any longer have weight. We should then no more
think of taxing people in proportion to their wealth or
ability to pay, regardless of the benefits they receive
from government than an honest merchant would think of
charging his customers in proportion to their wealth or
ability to pay, regardless of the value of the goods they
bought of him." 13
13. Following is an interesting
computation of the cost and loss to the city of
Boston of the present mixed system of taxation as
compared with the single tax; The computation was
made by James R. Carret, Esq., the leading
conveyancer of Boston:
Valuation of Boston, May 1,
1892 Land... ... . ..
... .. ... .. $399,170,175 Buildings ... ... ... ... ..$281,109,700
Total assessed value of real estate
$680,279,875 Assessed
value of personal estate $213,695,829
.... .... ... ... ... ...
... ... .... .... .... ... .... ...
$893,975,704 Rate of
taxation, $12.90 per $1000
Total tax levy, May 1, 1892 $11,805,036
Amount of taxes levied in respect of
the different subjects of taxation and percentages of
the same:
Land .... .... .... .... $5,149,295 43.62%
Buildings .... .... .. $3,626,295 30.72%
Personal estate .. $2,756,676 23.35%
Polls ... .... ... .... .... ...272,750
2.31%
But to ascertain the total cost to the
people of Boston of the present system of taxation
for the taxable year, beginning May 1, 1892, there
should be added to the taxes assessed upon them what
it cost them to pay the owners of the land of Boston
for the use of the land, being the net ground rent,
which I estimate at four per cent on the land
value.
Total tax levy, May 1, 1892 ...
... ... ... .... .... .... .... .... ..... .... ....
.... .... .... .... ..$11,805,036
Net ground rent, four percent, on
the land value ($399,170,175)..... ... ...
...$15,966,807 Total
cost of the present system to the people of Boston
for that year ... $27,771,843
To contrast this with what the single
tax system would have cost the people of Boston for
that year, take the gross ground rent, found by
adding to the net ground rent the taxation on land
values for that year, being $12.90 per $1000, or 1.29
per cent added to 4 per cent = 5.29 per cent.
Total cost of present system as
above .. .... .... .... .... .... .... .... ....
....$27,771,843 Single
tax, or gross ground rent, 5.29 per cent on
$399,170,175 ... ..$21,116,102
Excess cost of present system,
which is the sum of taxes in respect of buildings, personal
property, and polls .... ...... ..
$6,655,741
But the present system not only costs
the people more than the single tax would, but
produces less revenue:
Proceeds of single tax ... ...
... ... ..... .... .... ..... .... .... .... .....
..... .... $21,116,102 Present tax levy ... ... ... ... ... .... ....
.... ..... .... .... .... .... .... .... ....
....$11,805,036 Loss
to public treasury by present system ... .... ....
.... .... .. ..... ..$9,311,066
This, however, is not a complete
contrast between the present system and the single
tax, for large amounts of real estate are exempt from
taxation, being held by the United States, the
Commonwealth, by the city itself, by religious
societies and corporations, and by charitable,
literary, and scientific institutions. The total
amount of the value of land so held as returned by
the assessors for the year 1892 is $60,626,171.
Reasons can be given why all lands
within the city should be assessed for taxation to
secure a just distribution of the public burdens,
which I cannot take the space to enter into here.
There is good reason to believe also that lands in
the city of Boston are assessed to quite an
appreciable extent below their fair market value. As
an indication of this see an editorial in the Boston
Daily Advertiser for October 3, 1893, under
the title, "Their Own Figures."
The vacant lands, marsh lands, and
flats in Boston were valued by the assessors in 1892
(page 3 of their annual report) at $52,712,600. I
believe that this represents not more than fifty per
cent of their true market value.
Taking this and the undervaluation of
improved property and the exemptions above mentioned
into consideration, I think $500,000,000 to be a fair
estimate of the land values of Boston. Making this
the basis of contrast, we have:
Proceeds of single tax 5.29 per
cent on $500,000,000 ... .... .... ....
$26,450,000 Present
tax levy ... .... ... .... .... .... .... .... .....
.... .... .... .... ..... .... ....
..$11,805,036 Loss to
public treasury by present system ... ... ... ...
.... .... .... ....$14,644,974
... read the
book
Weld Carter: An
Introduction to Henry George
Another area in which George applied these
inherent differences between land and products was the
field of taxation. To determine the incidence of
taxation, George had to know what was to be taxed,
products or the value of land. In each case he traced out
the effect from the essential nature of the thing to be
taxed: "...all taxes upon things of unfixed quantity
increase prices, and in the course of exchange are
shifted from seller to buyer, increasing as they go.
...If we impose a tax upon buildings, the users of
buildings must finally pay it, for the erection of
buildings will cease until building rents become high
enough to pay the regular profit and the tax besides.
...In this way all taxes which add to prices are shifted
from hand to hand, increasing as they go, until they
ultimately rest upon consumers, who thus pay much more
than is received by the government. Now, the way taxes
raise prices is by increasing the cost of production, and
checking supply. But land is not a thing of human
production, and taxes upon...[land value] cannot check
supply. Therefore, though a tax on...[land value] compels
the land owners to pay more, it gives them no power to
obtain more for the use of their land, as it in no way
tends to reduce the supply of land. On the contrary, by
compelling those who hold land on speculation to sell or
let for what they can get, a tax on land values tends to
increase the competition between owners, and thus to
reduce the price of land."
...
However, what is the effect on
production of taxes levied on products and of taxes levied
on the value of land?
Of taxes levied on products, George
said: "The present method of taxation operates upon
exchange like artificial deserts and mountains; it costs
more to get goods through a custom house than it does to
carry them around the world. It operates upon energy, and
industry, and skill, and thrift, like a fine upon those
qualities. If I have worked harder and built myself a good
house while you have been contented to live in a hovel, the
taxgatherer now comes annually to make me pay a penalty for
my energy and industry, by taxing me more than you. If I
have saved while you wasted, I am mulct, while you are
exempt. If a man build a ship we make him pay for his
temerity, as though he had done an injury to the state; if
a railroad be opened, down comes the taxcollector upon it,
as though it were a public nuisance; if a manufactory be
erected we levy upon it an annual sum which would go far
toward making a handsome profit. We say we want capital,
but if anyone accumulate it, or bring it among us, we
charge him for it as though we were giving him a privilege.
We punish with a tax the man who covers barren fields with
ripening grain, we fine him who puts up machinery, and him
who drains a swamp. How heavily these taxes burden
production only those realize who have attempted to follow
our system of taxation through its ramifications, for, as I
have before said, the heaviest part of taxation is that
which falls in increased prices" (1879, rpt. 1958, p.
434).
Turning to taxation levied on the
value of land, George went on to say:
For this simple device of placing
all taxes on the value of land would be in effect putting
up the land at auction to whosoever would pay the highest
rent to the state. The demand for land fixes its value,
and hence, if taxes were placed so as very nearly to
consume that value, the man who wished to hold land
without using it would have to pay very nearly what it
would be worth to anyone who wanted to use
it.
And it must be remembered that this
would apply, not merely to agricultural land, but to all
land. Mineral land would be thrown open to use, just as
agricultural land; and in the heart of a city no one
could afford to keep land from its most profitable use,
or on the outskirts to demand more for it than the use to
which it could at the time be put would warrant.
Everywhere that land had attained a value, taxation,
instead of operating, as now, as a fine upon improvement,
would operate to force improvement.
A few pages before this he had told
us that, "It is sufficiently evident that with regard to
production, the tax upon the value of land is the best tax
that can be imposed. Tax manufactures, and the effect is to
check manufacturing; tax improvements, and the effect is to
lessen improvement; tax commerce, and the effect is to
prevent exchange; tax capital, and the effect is to drive
it away. But the whole value of land may be taken in
taxation, and the only effect will be to stimulate
industry, to open new opportunities to capital, and to
increase the production of wealth."
In other words, according to George, taxation of
products checks production, whereas taxation of land
values stimulates production. ... read the
whole article
|
To share this page with a friend:
right click, choose "send," and add your
comments.
|
|
Red links have not been
visited; .
Green links are pages you've seen
|
Essential Documents pertinent
to this theme:
|
|