1
2
3
Wealth and Want | |||||||
... because democracy alone is not enough to produce widely shared prosperity. | |||||||
Home | Essential Documents | Themes | All Documents | Authors | Glossary | Links | Contact Us |
Henry George Theorem Joseph Stiglitz: October, 2002, interview
Fred E. Foldvary — The Ultimate Tax Reform: Public Revenue from Land Rent
Nic Tideman: The Morality of Taxation: The Local Case From a moral perspective, taxation is dubious or worse. We tell our fellow citizens that if they do not pay taxes that we say they owe, their property will be seized or they will be sent to prison. Why do we treat people this way? Is there a justification? The dubiousness of taxation increases when we consider its origins. Government seems to have originated as roving bandits who learned that total destruction was less profitable than protecting their victims from other bandits and allowing them to keep a fraction of what they produced (Olson, 1993). In time, scheduled partial plunder evolved into taxation. Over the centuries, regimes that started as tyrannies evolved into democracies. The public sector evolved from an apparatus for implementing the will of despots into a mechanism for carrying out democratic decisions. But public finance continues to rely on the power of tax collectors, developed under early tyrants, to coerce citizen to pay taxes. The wrath that citizens feel toward tax collectors is probably the strongest antagonistic feeling that citizens have toward a governmental institution. Why do we allow ourselves to do this to one another? There is a gentler side of taxation that provides some explanation of our tolerance of this coercion. Taxation can be the way that people achieve their common purposes. People may agree to be taxed so that there will be money to pay for public services that they want. From this perspective, taxation may be considered no more than the dues for belonging to a club that provides people with things that they would rather pay their share of than do without. However, to make this "voluntary exchange" theory of taxation relevant, people must be able to choose freely whether or not to "join the club," to be a citizen of the taxing jurisdiction. With all land claimed by some taxing jurisdiction, the choice isn't exactly free. The problem of morality in taxation is the following:
we would probably have a much more efficient
public sector if every public expenditure required
two-thirds approval in legislative bodies.
But to make taxation truly voluntary, the option to leave must be viable. If people could move costlessly from one jurisdiction to another, taking all of their belongings with them, then competition among jurisdictions would tend to eliminate oppressive taxation. This would leave only the fees that people were prepared to pay to have public services (Tiebout, 1956). Of course, moving will always have some costs, so the ideal will not be attainable. But what can be imagined is a system in which all taxes were local taxes. Then people would not have to move nearly as far to escape from taxes that they regarded as oppressive. Higher levels of government would not need to disappear; if the services that they provide are desired, they could be financed by levies on lower levels of government. ...
...Thus communities would not be able to raise
much revenue from income tax or taxes on capital
before they would drive residents and investment
away. It might seem that there would be no way that
localities could finance themselves.
Such a conclusion would be unwarranted, because there is a very significant source of public revenue that can survive when localities compete for mobile residents. This source is land. When people are taxed in proportion to the land they possess, no land moves to another locality where taxes are lower. Thus two questions arise:
Consider first the question of adequacy of revenue. There is a theorem in economics, known as the Henry George Theorem, that addresses this question (Arnott and Stiglitz, 1979). One of the simpler versions of this theorem is: If the following three conditions are met: 1. Public expenditures provide benefits only over a limited area, then for any public service that is worth at least as much as it costs to those who receive it, the increase in the rental value of land that results from providing the service exceeds the net cost of the service. The Henry George Theorem is true because people who can move costlessly will bid up the rental value of land to reflect the value of public services that are not available elsewhere. The assumption that the number of bidders exceeds the number of people who can benefit from the public service guarantees that the upward movement of rents will not end until all the benefits of the public service are reflected in these rents. If some people who receive a public service value it more highly than others, then they will receive a surplus in addition to the rent they pay for land, and some worthwhile increments of public services will not add quite enough to rent to pay for themselves (Tideman 1993). But rent increments will go a very long way toward paying for worthwhile local public services. ...Read the whole articleFred Foldvary: Geo-Rent: A Plea to Public Economists
Textbooks in public finance and urban
economics sometimes contain a topic known as the
“Henry George Theorem.” It states that
the public revenue that provides for the collective
goods of an optimally-sized community equals the land
rent of that community. As presented in Atkinson and
Stiglitz (1987, 523-5), the representative
agent’s utility function is U(G,X), where G is
a collective and X a private good. Output Y is a
function of N workers:
Y = f(N) = XN + G.
X = {f(N)-G} / N The wage is the marginal product of labor: ∂f/∂N = X Therefore, ∂f/∂N = {(f(N)-G)/N} G = f(N) - Nf’(N) With land and labor the ultimate and original factors of production, rent (R) is the difference between total product Y and total wages:
R = f(N) - Nf'(N)
Therefore,
R = G.
The Henry George Theorem is so named because
it echoes Henry George's (1879) single-tax proposal,
that not only should land rent be the only general
tax, but that it will be adequate to finance public
goods. The theorem is accepted in public finance, but
it is not applied. In upper-level public-economics
textbooks such as Atkinson and Stiglitz (1987), it is
presented, yet not invoked in policy discussions, and
it is ignored in scholarly treatments of optimal
taxation, tax reform, and public
policy.
Edwin Mills (1998) goes further and constructs a comparative static model of a metropolis using a Cobb-Douglas production function with three factors, the third being land, which is a refreshing change from the usual two-factor analysis that tucks land into capital and then forgets that it’s there. One theorem of the model is that a land-value tax has no effect on resource allocation. Yet he concludes (47) that despite is theoretical attractiveness a significant taxing of geo-rent would deprive the owners of their beneficial uses, and would require compensation, leaving the tax “practically almost worthless” (47, 41). Thomas Nechyba (1998) also has a model with land, calibrated to U.S. parameters. He shows that replacing taxes on capital with taxes on land can actually increase land values, despite the downward capitalization caused by the tax, because of the greater increase in capital and rent. According to the model (p. 196), with an elasticity of substitution between capital and land of 0.5, which is within the estimated range, a revenue-neutral tax shift to land value increases capital goods by 122 percent and raises output by 89 percent. Read the entire article Richard Arnott, Kenneth Arrow, Anthony B. Atkinson and Jacques H. Dreze, editors, Public Economics: Selected Papers by William Vickrey. Cambridge University Press, 1994.
Henry George: The Condition of Labor — An Open Letter to Pope Leo XIII in response to Rerum Novarum (1891)
Nic Tideman: The Structure of an
Inquiry into the Attractiveness of A Social Order
Inspired by the Ideas of Henry George
A. People own themselves and therefore own
what they produce. II. Ethical
QuestionsB. People have obligations to share equally the opportunities that are provided by nature. C. People are free to interact with other competent adults on whatever terms are mutually agreed. D. People have obligations to pay the costs that their intrusive behaviors impose on others.
A. What is the relationship between justice
(as embodied in the ethical principles) and community
(or peace or harmony)? III. Efficiency
QuestionsB. How are the weak to be provided for? C. How should natural opportunities be shared? D. Who should be included in the group among whom rent should be shared equally? E. Is there an obligation to compensate those whose presently recognized titles to land and other exclusive natural opportunities will lose value when rent is shared equally? F. Can a person who is occupying a per capita share of land reasonably ask to be left undisturbed indefinitely on that land? G. What is the moral status of "intellectual property?" H. What standards of environmental respect can people reasonably require of others? I. What forms of land use control are consistent with the philosophy of Henry George?
A. Would public collection of the rent of land
provide enough revenue for an appropriate public
sector?
B. How much revenue could public collection of rent raise? C. Is it possible to assess land with sufficient accuracy? D. How much growth can a community expect if it shifts taxes from improvements to land? E. To what extent does the benefit that one community receives from shifting taxes from buildings to land come at the expense of other communities? F. What is the impact of land taxes on land speculation? G. How, if at all, does the impact of shifting the source of public revenue to land change if it is a whole nation rather than just a community that makes the shift? H. Is there a danger that the application of Henry George's ideas would lead to a world of over-development? I. How would natural resources be managed appropriately if they were regarded as the common heritage of humanity? Read the whole article
|
|
to email this page to a friend: right click, choose
"send"
|
||||||
Wealth and Want
|
www.wealthandwant.com
|
|||||
... because democracy alone hasn't yet led to a society
in which all can prosper
|