But who? Marjorie Kelly has written a brilliant book
called The Divine Right of Capital. By divine she
doesn’t mean God-given. She means that, under our
current operating system, the rights of capital trump
everything else. The rights of workers, communities,
nature, and future generations — all play second
fiddle to capital’s prerogative to maximize
short-term gain. This hierarchy isn’t the doing of
God or some inexorable law of nature. Rather, it’s
a result of political choice.
The question of who gets the top right in any society
is always an interesting one. Invariably, the top dogs in
any era assert that there’s no alternative. Kings
said it three hundred years ago; capital owners say it
today. They hire priests and economists to add moral or
pseudoscientific credence to their claims. The truth,
though, is that societies choose their top right holders,
and we can change our minds if we wish.
Kelly locates many places where capital’s
supremacy is written into our codes. Corporate directors,
for example, are bound by law to put shareholders’
financial gain first. If a raider offers a higher price
for a publicly traded company than its current market
value, directors have little choice but to sell,
regardless of the consequences for workers, communities,
or nature. Similarly, it’s the fiduciary duty of
mutual funds, pension funds, and other institutional
investors to seek the highest returns for their
shareholders or beneficiaries. This duty is embodied,
among other places, in the Employee Retirement Income
Security Act of 1974. Although the language of the act
sounds innocent enough — a pension fund manager,
like any trustee, “shall discharge his duties . . .
solely in the interest of the participants and
beneficiaries” — it results, ironically, in
the financing of many workers’ retirements by
investing in companies that shift other workers’
jobs overseas. Throw in the WTO and NAFTA, and the rights
of capital stand comfortably astride everyone
else’s.
What’s wrong here? It’s not that
businesses pursue profit; that’s what they’re
designed to do and what we want them to do. The problem
is that private capital rides in the front of the bus
while everyone else rides in the back. ...
Trusts are centuries-old institutions devised to hold
and manage property for beneficiaries. The essence of a
trust is a fiduciary relationship. Neither trusts nor
their trustees may ever act in their own self-interest;
they’re legally obligated to act solely on behalf
of beneficiaries.
Trusts are bound by numerous rules, including the
following:
* Managers must act with undivided loyalty to
beneficiaries.
* Unless authorized to act otherwise, managers must
preserve the corpus of the trust. It’s okay to
spend income, but not to diminish principal.
* Managers must ensure transparency by making timely
financial information available to beneficiaries.
These rules are enforceable. The basic enforcement
mechanism is that an aggrieved beneficiary or a state
attorney general can bring suit against a trustee. When
that happens, the trustee must prove she acted prudently;
if there’s any doubt, the trustee is fined or
fired. As Supreme Court Justice Benjamin Cardozo once put
it: “A trustee is held to something stricter than
the morals of the marketplace. Not honesty alone, but the
punctilio of an honor the most sensitive, is the standard
of behavior.”
A trustee isn’t the same thing as a steward.
Stewards care for an asset, but their obligations are
voluntary and vague. By contrast, trustees’
obligations are mandatory and quite specific. Trusteeship
is thus a more formal and rigorous responsibility than
stewardship.
Trusts can be in charge of financial as well as
physical assets. In this chapter, my concern is natural
assets — gifts we inherit from creation. One of my
premises is that each generation has a contract to pass
on such gifts, undiminished, to those not yet born. If we
are to keep this contract, someone must act as trustee of
nature’s gifts, or at least of the most endangered
of them. The question is, who?
The candidates are government, corporations, and
trusts. I argued earlier that neither corporations nor
government can fulfill this function; they’re both
too bound to short-term private interests. That leaves
trusts.
Common Property Trusts
The Trebah Garden Trust isn’t a rarity. Across
Britain, the National Trust — a nongovernmental
charity founded in 1895 — owns over six hundred
thousand acres of countryside, six hundred miles of
coastline, and two hundred historic buildings and
gardens. It has over three million members who elect half
of its fifty-two-person governing council (the other half
are appointed by nonprofit organizations that share the
trust’s goals). In the United States, there are now
over fifteen hundred Trebah-like trusts, protecting over
nine million acres. On top of that, the
fifty-five-year-old Nature Conservancy protects more than
fifteen million acres.
Let’s posit, then, a generic institution, the
common property trust. It’s a special kind of trust
that manages assets that come from the commons and are
meant to be preserved as commons. Common property trusts
manage these assets first and foremost on behalf of
future generations. They may have secondary
beneficiaries, such as public education or residents of a
particular locale, but such living beneficiaries take
backseats to the yet-to-be-born. These trusts carry out
their missions by owning and managing bundles of property
rights. Here are two examples from my own backyard: the
Marin Agricultural Land Trust (MALT) and the Pacific
Forest Trust (PFT). The demise of family farms and the
loss of open space around cities are seemingly
unstoppable trends. Yet in Marin County, just north of
San Francisco, family-owned dairy, sheep, and cattle
ranches have survived. A big reason is that ranchers
there have an option: selling conservation easements to
MALT.
A conservation easement is a voluntary agreement
between a landowner and a trust that permanently limits
uses of the land. The owner continues to own and use the
land and may sell it or pass it on to her heirs. However,
the owner gives up some of the rights associated with the
land — for example, the right to build additional
houses on it or to clear-cut trees. The trust that
acquires the easement makes sure its terms are followed
by the current as well as future owners.
In Marin County, MALT has preserved nearly forty
thousand acres of farmland by buying conservation
easements from ranchers. This represents about a third of
the land currently farmed. The ranchers receive the
difference between what the land would be worth if
developed and what it’s worth as a working farm. In
effect, they’re paid to be land stewards and to
forgo future capital gains.
Most of MALT’s money comes from public sources.
What the public receives isn’t an old-fashioned
commons of shared pasturage, but a lasting pastoral
landscape and a viable agricultural economy. That’s
not a bad alternative to suburban sprawl.
In much the same way, the Pacific Forest Trust
acquires what it calls working forest conservation
easements from private woodlands owners. Some of the
easements are purchased, others are donated by owners in
exchange for tax benefits. Here again, owners keep their
land but agree to forgo nonforest development and to
harvest trees sustainably.
PFT’s goal is to protect not only forests
themselves but the many species that live in them, as
well as the ecosystem services — such as clean
water and carbon absorption — that forests provide.
As with MALT, some of PFT’s money comes from public
sources. In return, the public gets healthy forests for
considerably less than it would cost to buy and manage
them outright.
Valves and Their Keepers
One job of common property trusts is to preserve
habitat and landscapes, but such trusts can also play
another role — controlling the flow of pollution
into ecosystems. In this case, what they’d be
managing isn’t the ecosystems themselves, but human
economic activity around the ecosystems. In that sense,
they’d be more like the Federal Reserve than the
Nature Conservancy.
Let me back up here a bit. When I was in college, my
economics professors talked of fiscal and monetary
“levers” that wise policymakers could use to
fine-tune the economy. This was in the early 1960s, still
the heyday of Keynesianism. I imagined an economic
control room full of gauges and valves, staffed by tweedy
academics. Handsome, brainy men (it was still mainly men
in those days) would scan readouts, puff on their pipes,
and twist a few dials. Others would murmur praise. All
would remain calm.
As I grew older, I learned the world is more chaotic
than that. In reality, there’s no economic control
room. There’s only one big valve — the money
supply — and one person (with a few helpers) who
turns it: the chair of the Federal Reserve. That valve
has some effect on economy activity — when
it’s loose, interest rates fall and economic
activity perks up; when it’s tight, interest rates
rise and economic activity ebbs. But the Fed’s
valve doesn’t control everything our economic
engine does. In particular, it has little impact on the
rate at which we pour pollutants into surrounding
ecosystems. To address this problem, we need more
valves.
Think, for example, about carbon. At present, our
economic engine is emitting far too much carbon dioxide
into the atmosphere; this is destabilizing the climate.
We desperately need a valve that can crank the carbon
flow down. Let’s assume we can design and install
such a valve. (I explained how this can be done in my
previous book, Who Owns the Sky? It involves selling a
limited quantity of “upstream” permits to
companies that bring fossil fuels into the economy.) The
question then is, who should control the valve?
Unfettered markets can’t be given that
responsibility; as we’ve seen, they have no ability
to limit polluting. So we’re left with two options:
government or trusts. Government is a political creature;
its time horizon is short, and future generations have no
clout in it. Common property trusts, by contrast, are
fiduciary institutions. They have long time horizons and
a legal responsibility to future generations. Given the
choice, I’d designate a common property trust to be
keeper of the carbon valve, based on peer-reviewed advice
from scientists. Its trustees could make hard decisions
without committing political suicide. They might be
appointed by the president, like governors of the Fed,
but they wouldn’t be obedient to him the way
cabinet members are. Once appointed, they’d be
legally accountable to future generations.
Now imagine a goodly number of valves at the local,
regional, and national levels, not just for carbon (which
requires only one national valve) but for a variety of
pollutants. Imagine also that the valve keepers are
trusts accountable to future generations. They’d
have the power to reduce some of the negative
externalities — the illth — that corporations
shift to the commons. They’d also have the power to
auction limited pollution rights to the highest bidders,
and to divide the resulting income among commons owners.
That’s something neither the Fed nor the EPA can
do.
These trusts would fundamentally change our economic
operating system. What are now unpriced externalities
would become property rights under accountable
management. If a corporation wanted to pollute, it
couldn’t just do so; it would have to buy the
rights from a commons trust. The price of pollution would
go up; corporate illth creation would go down. Ecosystems
would be protected for future generations. More income
would flow to ordinary citizens. Nonhuman species would
flourish; human inequality would diminish. And government
wouldn’t be enlarged — our economic engine
would do these things on its own.
One final point about valves. It’s not too
critical where we set them initially. It’s far more
important to install them in the right places, and to put
the right people in charge. Then they can adjust the
settings.
A Second Set of Books
Mental models begin with assumptions. Most economists
today assume there are only two kinds of property,
private (that is, corporate or individual) and state.
There are no shared assets, no inter- or
intragenerational obligations, and no nonhumans other
than those we eat.
Yet as we’ve seen, many things are missing here.
The most obvious omission is the great economy of nature
within which the human enterprise operates. We’re
borrowing prodigiously from that economy, but not
recording the loans. Equally absent are future
generations, from whom we’re borrowing just as
wantonly and surreptitiously. In a proper bookkeeping
system, every loan shows up on two balance sheets, the
borrower’s and the lender’s. One
entity’s liability is another entity’s asset.
But this isn’t true in contemporary economics. When
the human economy grows, assets on corporate and
individual balance sheets go up, but nowhere is there a
debit. In fact, there aren’t any accounts that
could be debited. There’s only good growth on one
side of the ledger, and on the other, a void in which
illth and debt accumulate, uncounted and unnoticed.
In recent years, economists have added a few bits to
this stripped-down model. For example, they now recognize
public goods and ecosystem services as contributors of
economic value. Public goods are services like national
defense, education, and flood control, which benefit
everyone but can’t easily be sold at a profit.
Because markets don’t adequately supply them,
governments step in and do so. Economists sometimes
debate whether the value of these public goods exceeds
the “burden” they impose on taxpayers, but
they don’t see the expenditures as adding value to
any account, or to any asset owned by anyone.
Similarly, many economists now recognize ecosystem
services as valuable inputs to the economy. However, the
ecosystems that produce these services have no owners or
balance sheets. They’re just there, floating in
space, with no connection to humans. What I’m
suggesting is that economists treat them as if they were
common property held in trust. This simple supposition
would not only put ecosystems on the books, enabling us
to track them better; it would also pave the way to
real-world property rights that actually protect those
ecosystems.
Beyond Coase’s Supposes
“Let us suppose,” economist Ronald Coase
wrote in 1960, “that a farmer and a cattle-raiser
are operating on neighboring properties.” He went
on to suppose further that the cattle-raiser’s
animals wander onto the farmer’s land and damage
his crops. From this hypothetical starting point Coase
examined the problem of externalities and proposed a
solution — the creation of rights to pollute or not
be polluted upon. Today, pollution rights are used
throughout the world. In effect, Coase conjured into
existence a class of property rights that didn’t
exist before, and his leap of imagination eventually
reduced real pollution.
“Let us suppose” is a wonderful way for
anyone, economists included, to begin thinking. It lets
us adjust old assumptions and see what might happen. And
it lets us imagine things that don’t exist but
could, and sometimes, because we imagined them, later
do.
Coase supposed that a single polluter or his
neighboring pollutee possessed a right to pollute or not
be polluted upon. He further supposed that the
transaction costs involved in negotiations between the
two neighbors were negligible. He made these suppositions
half a century ago, at a time when aggregate pollution
wasn’t planet-threatening, as it now is. Given
today’s altered reality, it might be worth updating
Coase’s suppositions to make them relevant to this
aggregate problem. Here, in my mind, are the appropriate
new suppositions:
* Instead of one polluter, there are many, and instead
of one pollutee, there are millions — including
many not yet born.
* The pollutees (including future generations) are
collectively represented by trusts.
* The initial pollution rights are assigned by government
to these trusts.
* In deciding how many pollution permits to sell, the
trustees’ duty isn’t to maximize revenue but
to preserve an ecosystem for future generations. The
trusts therefore establish safe levels of pollution and
gradually reduce the number of permits they sell until
those levels are reached.
* Revenue from the sale of pollution permits is divided
50 percent for per capita dividends (like the Alaska
Permanent Fund) and 50 percent for public goods such as
education and ecological restoration.
If we make these suppositions, what then happens? We
have, first of all, an economic model with a second set
of books. Not all, but many externalities show up on
these new ledgers. More importantly, we begin to imagine
a world in which nature and future generations are
represented in real-time transactions, corporations
internalize previously externalized costs, prices of
illth-causing goods rise, and everyone receives some
property income.
Here’s what such a world could look like:
* Degradation of key ecosystems is gradually reduced
to sustainable levels because the trustees who set
commons usage levels are accountable to future
generations, not living shareholders or voters. When they
fail to protect their beneficiaries, they are sued.
* Thanks to per capita dividends, income is recycled from
overusers of key ecosystems to underusers, creating both
incentives to conserve and greater equity.
* Clean energy and organic farming are competitive
because prices of fossil fuels and agricultural chemicals
are appropriately high.
* Investment in new technologies soars and new domestic
jobs are created because higher fuel and waste disposal
prices boost demand for clean energy and waste recycling
systems.
* Public goods are enhanced by permit revenue.
What has happened here? We’ve gone from a
realistic set of assumptions about how the world is
— multiple polluters and pollutees, zero cost of
pollution, dangerous cumulative levels of pollution
— to a reasonable set of expectations about how the
world could be if certain kinds of property rights are
introduced. These property rights go beyond
Coase’s, but are entirely compatible with market
principles. The results of this thought experiment show
that the introduction of common property trusts can
produce a significant and long-lasting shift in economic
outcomes without further government intervention.
Commons Rent
It shouldn’t be thought that the commons is, or
ought to be, a money-free zone. In fact, an important
subject for economists (and the rest of us) to understand
is commons rent.
By this I don’t mean the monthly check you send
to a landlord. In economics, rent has a more precise
meaning: it’s money paid because of scarcity. If
you’re not an economist, that may sound puzzling,
but consider this. A city has available a million
apartments. In absolute terms, that means apartments
aren’t scarce. But the city is confined
geographically and demand for apartments is intense. In
this economic sense, apartments are scarce. Now think
back to that check you pay your landlord, or the mortgage
you pay the bank. Part of it represents the
landlord’s operating costs or the bank’s cost
of money, but part of it is pure rent — that is,
money paid for scarcity. That’s why New Yorkers and
San Franciscans write such large checks to landlords and
banks, while people in Nebraska don’t.
Rent rises when an increase in demand bumps into a
limit in supply. Rent due to such bumping isn’t
good or bad; it just is.We can (and should) debate the
distribution of that rent, but the rent itself arises
automatically. And it’s important that it does so,
because this helps the larger economy allocate scarce
resources efficiently. Other methods of allocation are
possible. We can distribute scarce things on a first
come, first served basis, or by lottery, political power,
seniority, or race. Experience has shown, though, that
selling scarce resources in open markets is usually the
best approach, and such selling inevitably creates
rent.
Rent was of great interest to the early economists
— Adam Smith, David Ricardo, and John Stuart Mill,
among others — because it constituted most of the
money earned by landowners, and land was then a major
cost of production. The supply of land, these economists
noted, is limited, but demand for it steadily increases.
So, therefore, does its rent. Thus, landowners benefit
from what Mill called the unearned increment — the
rise in land value attributable not to any effort of the
owner, but purely to a socially created increase in
demand bumping into a limited supply of good land.
The underappreciated American economist Henry George
went further. Seeing both the riches and the miseries of
the Gilded Age, he asked a logical question: Why does
poverty persist despite economic growth? The answer, he
believed, was the appropriation of rent by landowners.
Even as the economy grew, the property rights system and
the scarcity of land diverted almost all the gains to a
landowning minority. Whereas competition limited the
gains of working people, nothing kept down the
landowners’ gains. As Mill had noted, the value of
their land just kept rising. To fix the problem, George
advocated a steep tax on land and the abolition of other
taxes. His bestselling book Progress and Poverty
catapulted him to fame in the 1880s, but mainstream
economists never took him seriously.
By the twentieth century, economists had largely lost
interest in rent; it seemed a trivial factor in wealth
production compared to capital and labor. But the
twenty-first century ecological crisis brings rent back
to center-stage. Now it’s not just land
that’s scarce, but clean water, undisturbed
habitat, biological diversity, waste absorption capacity,
and entire ecosystems.
This brings us back to common property rights. The
definition and allocation of property rights are the
primary factors in determining who pays whom for what.
If, in the case of pollution rights, pollution rights are
given free to past polluters, the rent from the polluted
ecosystem will also go to them. That’s because
prices for pollution-laden products will rise as
pollution is limited (remember, if demand is constant, a
reduction in supply causes prices to go up), and those
higher prices will flow to producers (which is to say,
polluters).
By contrast, if pollution rights are assigned to
trusts representing pollutees and future generations, and
if these trusts then sell these rights to polluters, the
trusts rather than the polluters will capture the commons
rent. If the trusts split this money between per capita
dividends and expenditures on public goods, everyone
benefits.
At this moment, based on pollution rights allocated so
far, polluting corporations are getting most of the
commons rent. But the case for trusts getting the rent in
the future is compelling. If this is done, consumers will
pay commons rent not to corporations or government, but
to themselves as beneficiaries of commons trusts. Each
citizen’s dividend will be the same, but his
payments will depend on his purchases of pollution-laden
products. The more he pollutes, the more rent he’ll
pay. High polluters will get back less than they put in,
while low polluters will get back more. The microeconomic
incentives, in other words, will be perfect. (See figure
6.1.)
What’s equally significant, though less obvious,
is that the macroeconomic incentives will be perfect too.
That is, it will be in everyone’s interest to
reduce the total level of pollution. Remember how rent
for scarce things works: the lower the supply, the higher
the rent. Now, imagine you’re a trustee of an
ecosystem, and leaving aside (for the sake of argument)
your responsibility to preserve the asset for future
generations, you want to increase dividends. Do you raise
the number of pollution permits you sell, or lower it?
The correct, if counterintuitive answer is: you lower the
number of permits.
This macroeconomic phenomenon — that less
pollution yields more income for citizens — is the
ultimate knockout punch for commons trusts. It aligns the
interests of future generations with, rather than
against, those of living citizens. By so doing, it lets
us chart a transition to sustainability in which the
political pressure is for faster pollution reduction
rather than slower.
There’s one further argument for recycling
commons rent through trusts. As rent is recycled from
overusers of the commons to underusers, income is shifted
from rich to poor. That’s because rich households,
on average, use the commons more than poor households.
They drive SUVs, fly in jets, and have large homes to
heat and cool — thus they dump more waste into the
biosphere. Studies by Congress and independent economists
have shown that only a rent recycling system like the one
just described can protect the poor. Absent such a
system, the poor will pay commons rent and get nothing
back. In other words, they’ll get poorer.
As always, there are a few caveats.
* First, to the extent commons rent is used for public
goods rather than per capita dividends, the income
recycling effects are diminished. This is offset,
however, by the fact that public goods benefit
everyone.
* Second, the less-pollution-equals-more-dividends
formula doesn’t work indefinitely. At some point
after less polluting technologies have been widely
deployed, the demand for pollution absorption will become
elastic. Then, lowering the number of pollution permits
sold will decrease income to citizens. But that time is
far in the future, and when it comes, the world will be a
healthier place. And even then, trustees won’t be
able to increase the number of pollution permits without
violating their responsibility to future generations.
...
Accountability and Democracy
The question I’m most often asked about commons
trusteeship is: How can we be sure trustees won’t
succumb to corporate influence, just as politicians have?
My answer is that, while there can be no guarantees, the
odds of escaping corporate capture are much better with
trustees than with elected officials.
The key reason is accountability. In the world of
corporations, accountability is quite clear: directors
must be loyal to shareholders. In the world of
government, accountability is less clear. Elected
officials must uphold the Constitution, but that’s
about it. If there are conflicts between workers and
employers, polluters and pollutees, voters and donors, or
future generations and current ones, whose side should
politicians be on? There are no requirements or even
guidelines. Elected officials, as sovereign political
actors, are free to do as they please.
The fact that politicians operate this way is no
accident; it’s what the Founders had in mind. The
job of democratic government isn’t to take,
consistently, one side or another. Rather, it’s to
resolve disputes among factions peaceably, without
trampling minorities. James Madison made this plain in
the Federalist Papers. Voters can “fire”
elected officials at regular intervals if a majority so
chooses, but they can’t expect loyalty to any
particular constituency between elections. It’s
this absence of built-in loyalty that opens the door to
corporate influence, a force the Founders didn’t
— and couldn’t — foresee.
The decision-making of judges, it should be noted,
isn’t as untethered as that of legislators and
executive officeholders. Their duty is to uphold not just
the skeletal bones of the Constitution but the full flesh
and blood of the law, with its thousands of pages and
interpretations. They may, on occasion, interpret anew,
but unless they’re among a Supreme Court majority,
all such reinterpretations are subject to review.
Trustees are in the same boat as judges, rather than
the wide-open waters in which politicians swim. Their
hands are constrained both by the law and by their
fiduciary duty to beneficiaries. This isn’t to say
they have no room to wiggle: equally loyal trustees may
differ over what’s in the best interest of
beneficiaries. Still, they are subject to court review,
and they can’t betray their beneficiaries too
brazenly.
The tricky thing here is that the beneficiaries to
whom we want commons trustees to be loyal — future
generations, nonhumans, and ecosystems — are
voiceless and powerless. We must therefore take extra
care when we set up commons trusts. For example, we
should install strict conflict-of-interest rules for
trustees and managers. We should require that all
relevant information about the trusts — including
audited financial reports — are freely available on
the Internet. We should ensure that, if a commons trust
fails, its assets are transferred to a similar trust
rather than privatized. We should build in internal
watchdogs and ombudsmen. And we should authorize external
advocates, such as nonprofit organizations, to represent
nonliving beneficiaries who, by their very nature,
can’t take trustees to court. Most states assign
this function to their attorneys general, but this is
insufficient given the political pressures attorneys
general are subject to.
With regard to the manner of selecting trustees,
there’s no single method. Trustees might be
elected, appointed by outsiders, or be self-perpetuating
like the boards of many nonprofits. This is as it should
be; we don’t live in a one-size-fits-all world. The
important thing is that, once selected, trustees should
have secure tenure, and — like judges —
lengthy terms. Indeed, trustees should be like judges in
other ways: professional, impeccably honest,
well-compensated, and honored. Being a commons trustee
should be a distinguished and attractive calling.
It might be argued that, by shielding trustees from
direct political influence, we’d make them —
and commons trusts generally — undemocratic. The
same could be said, however, for our courts. The fact is,
there are certain decisions, both economic and judicial,
that should be shielded from politics and markets.
Moreover, neither government nor corporations represent
the needs of future generations, ecosystems, and nonhuman
species. Commons trusts can do this. In that sense,
they’d expand rather than constrict the boundaries
of democracy. ...
read the whole chapter