The galleys that carried Caesar to Britain, the
accoutrements of his legionaries, the baggage that they
carried, the arms that they bore, the buildings that they
erected; the scythed chariots of the ancient Britons, the
horses that drew them, their wicker boats and wattled
houses–where are they now? But the land for which
Roman and Briton fought, there it is still. That British
soil is yet as fresh and as new as it was in the days of
the Romans. Generation after generation has lived on it
since, and generation after generation will live on it
yet. Now, here is a very great difference. The right to
possess and to pass on the ownership of things that in
their nature decay and soon cease to be is a very
different thing from the right to possess and to pass on
the ownership of that which does not decay, but from
which each successive generation must live.
To show how this difference between land and such
other species of property as are properly styled wealth
bears upon the argument for the vested rights of
landholders, let me illustrate again.
Captain Kidd was a pirate. He made a business of
sailing the seas, capturing merchantmen, making their
crews walk the plank, and appropriating their cargoes. In
this way he accumulated much wealth, which he is thought
to have buried. But let us suppose, for the sake of the
illustration, that he did not bury his wealth, but left
it to his legal heirs, and they to their heirs and so on,
until at the present day this wealth or a part of it has
come to a great-great-grandson of Captain Kidd. Now, let
us suppose that some one – say a
great-great-grandson of one of the shipmasters whom
Captain Kidd plundered, makes complaint, and says: "This
man's great-great-grandfather plundered my
great-great-grandfather of certain things or certain
sums, which have been transmitted to him, whereas but for
this wrongful act they would have been transmitted to me;
therefore, I demand that he be made to restore them."
What would society answer?
Society, speaking by its proper tribunals, and in
accordance with principles recognized among all civilized
nations, would say: "We cannot entertain such a demand.
It may be true that Mr. Kidd's great-great-grandfather
robbed your great-great-grandfather, and that as the
result of this wrong he has got things that otherwise
might have come to you. But we cannot inquire into
occurrences that happened so long ago. Each generation
has enough to do to attend to its own affairs. If we go
to righting the wrongs and reopening the controversies of
our great-great-grandfathers, there will be endless
disputes and pretexts for dispute. What you say may be
true, but somewhere we must draw the line, and have an
end to strife. Though this man's great-great-grandfather
may have robbed your great-great-grandfather, he has not
robbed you. He came into possession of these things
peacefully, and has held them peacefully, and we must
take this peaceful possession, when it has been continued
for a certain time, as absolute evidence of just title;
for, were we not to do that, there would be no end to
dispute and no secure possession of anything."
Now, it is this common-sense principle that is
expressed in the statute of limitations – in the
doctrine of vested rights. This is the
reason why it is held – and as to most things held
justly – that peaceable possession for
a certain time cures all defects of title.
But let us pursue the illustration a little
further:
Let us suppose that Captain Kidd, having established a
large and profitable piratical business, left it to his
son, and he to his son, and so on, until the
great-great-grandson, who now pursues it, has come to
consider it the most natural thing in the world that his
ships should roam the sea, capturing peaceful
merchantmen, making their crews walk the plank, and
bringing home to him much plunder, whereby he is enabled,
though he does no work at all, to live in very great
luxury, and look down with contempt upon people who have
to work. But at last, let us suppose, the merchants get
tired of having their ships sunk and their goods taken,
and sailors get tired of trembling for their lives every
time a sail lifts above the horizon, and they demand of
society that piracy be stopped.
Now, what should society say if Mr. Kidd got
indignant, appealed to the doctrine of vested rights, and
asserted that society was bound to prevent any
interference with the business that he had inherited, and
that, if it wanted him to stop, it must buy him out,
paying him all that his business was worth–that is
to say, at least as much as he could make in twenty
years' successful pirating, so that if he stopped
pirating he could still continue to live in luxury off of
the profits of the merchants and the earnings of the
sailors?
What ought society to say to such a claim as this?
There will be but one answer. We will all say that
society should tell Mr. Kidd that his was a business to
which the statute of limitations and the doctrine of
vested rights did not apply; that because his father, and
his grandfather, and his great- and
great-great-grandfather pursued the business of capturing
ships and making their crews walk the plank, was no
reason why lie should be permitted to pursue it. Society,
we will all agree, ought to say he would have to stop
piracy and stop it at once, and that without getting a
cent for stopping.
Or supposing it had happened that Mr. Kidd had sold
out his piratical business to Smith, Jones, or Robinson,
we will all agree that society ought to say that their
purchase of the business gave them no greater right than
Mr. Kidd had.
We will all agree that that is what society ought to
say. Observe, I do not ask what society would say.
For, ridiculous and preposterous as it may appear, I
am satisfied that, under the circumstances I have
supposed, society would not for a long time say what we
have agreed it ought to say. Not only would all the Kidds
loudly claim that to make them give up their business
without full recompense would be a wicked interference
with vested rights, but the justice of this claim would
at first be assumed as a matter of course by all or
nearly all the influential classes–the great
lawyers, the able journalists, the writers for the
magazines, the eloquent clergymen, and the principal
professors in the principal universities. Nay, even the
merchants and sailors, when they first began to complain,
would be so tyrannized and browbeaten by this public
opinion that they would hardly think of more than of
buying out the Kidds, and, wherever here and there any
one dared to raise his voice in favor of stopping piracy
at once and without compensation, he would only do so
under penalty of being stigmatized as a reckless
disturber and wicked foe of social order.
If any one denies this, if any one says mankind are
not such fools, then I appeal to universal history to
bear me witness. I appeal to the facts of today.
Show me a wrong, no matter how monstrous, that ever
yet, among any people, became ingrafted in the social
system, and I will prove to you the truth of what I say.
...
What is the slave-trade but piracy of the worst kind?
Yet it is not long since the slave-trade was looked upon
as a perfectly respectable business, affording as
legitimate an opening for the investment of capital and
the display of enterprise as any other. The proposition
to prohibit it was first looked upon as ridiculous, then
as fanatical, then as wicked. It was only slowly and by
hard fighting that the truth in regard to it gained
ground. Does not our very Constitution bear witness to
what I say? Does not the fundamental law of the nation,
adopted twelve years after the enunciation of the
Declaration of Independence, declare that for twenty
years the slave-trade shall not be prohibited nor
restricted? Such dominion had the idea of vested
interests over the minds of those who had already
proclaimed the inalienable right of man to life, liberty,
and the pursuit of happiness! ... read
the whole article