Free Gifts of Nature
Henry George:
The Common Sense of Taxation (1881 article)
These are truisms. Yet so widespread and persistent is
the notion that all property should be taxed, that they
are generally ignored. Nothing is clearer than that when
a farmer who wants more capital puts a mortgage on his
farm, no new value is thereby created. Yet, in most of
our States, both the farm and the mortgage are taxed;
though so obvious is the double taxation that in some of
them the clumsy expedient of making an exemption to the
debtor is resorted to.
But it is manifest that property of this kind is not a
fit subject for taxation, and ought not to be considered
in making up the assessment rolls. It has, in itself, no
value. It is merely the representative, or token, of
value — the certificate of ownership, or the
obligation to pay value. It either represents other
property, or property yet to be brought into existence.
And, as nothing real can be drawn from that which is not
real, taxation upon property of this kind must ultimately
fall, either upon the property represented, in which case
there is double taxation, or upon those whose obligations
it expresses, in which case men are taxed, not upon what
they own, but upon what they owe; and all cumbrous
devices to prevent the unjust effects of such taxation,
like other complications of the revenue system, simply
give to the stronger and more unscrupulous opportunities
of throwing the burden upon the weaker and more
conscientious. Property of this kind ought not to be
taxed at all. Property in itself valuable is clearly that
with which any wise scheme of taxation should alone
deal.
To consider the nature of property of this kind is
again to see a clear distinction. That distinction is
not, as the lawyers have it, between movables and
immovables, between personal property and real estate.
The true distinction is between property which is, and
property which is not, the result of human labor; or, to
use the terms of political economy, between land and
wealth. For, in any precise use of the term, land is not
wealth, any more than labor is wealth. Land and labor are
the factors of production. Wealth is such result of their
union as retains the capacity of ministering to human
desire. A lot and the house which stands upon it are
alike property, alike have a tangible value, and are
alike classed as real estate. But there are between them
the most essential differences. The one is the
free gift of Nature, the other the result of
human exertion; the one exists from generation to
generation, while men come and go; the other is
constantly tending to decay, and can only be preserved by
continual exertion. To the one, the right of exclusive
possession, which makes it individual property, can, like
the right of property in slaves, be traced to nothing but
municipal law; to the other, the right of exclusive
property springs clearly from those natural relations
which are among the primary perceptions of the human
mind. Nor are these mere abstract distinctions. They are
distinctions of the first importance in determining what
should and what should not be taxed.
For, keeping in mind the fact that all wealth is the
result of human exertion, it is clearly seen that, having
in view the promotion of the general prosperity, it is
the height of absurdity to tax wealth for purposes of
revenue while there remains, unexhausted by taxation, any
value attaching to land. We may tax land values as much
as we please, without in the slightest degree lessening
the amount of land, or the capabilities of land, or the
inducement to use land. But we cannot tax wealth without
lessening the inducement to the production of wealth, and
decreasing the amount of wealth. We might take the whole
value of land in taxation, so as to make the ownership of
land worth nothing, and the land would still remain, and
be as useful as before. The effect would be to throw land
open to users free of price, and thus to increase its
capabilities, which are brought out by increased
population. But impose anything like such taxation upon
wealth, and the inducement to the production of wealth
would be gone. Movable wealth would be hidden or carried
off, immovable wealth would be suffered to go to decay,
and where was prosperity would soon be the silence of
desolation. ...
read the whole article
Peter Barnes:
Capitalism 3.0 — Chapter 6: Trusteeship of Creation
(pages 79-100)
Gifts of creation were produced only once and
are irreplaceable. By contrast, products traded
in markets tend to be mass-produced and highly
disposable. It’s hard to imagine a deity
who’d view such temporal goods as equivalent to his
or her enduring handiwork. The question is whether
creation’s irreplaceable gifts are different enough
to merit different treatment by our economic operating
system. A strong case can be made that they
are.
The case is moral as well as economic. The moral
argument is that we have a duty to preserve irreplaceable
gifts of creation, whereas we have no comparable duty
toward transient commercial goods. The economic argument
is that any society that depletes its natural capital is
bound to become impoverished over time. I find both lines
of argument convincing.
But what’s the reality today? Here we encounter
two disconcerting facts. The first is that there are very
few property rights protecting nature’s gifts. With
the exception of a few set-asides such as parks and
wilderness areas, we subject creation’s gifts to
the same rules as Wal-Mart’s merchandise. The
second is that the right of corporations to profit
dominates all other rights.
It’s time to treat creation’s gifts
differently, to put different “tags” on them
so markets will recognize them and apply different rules
to them. This chapter shows how we can do that.
...
At the moment, there’s one law that does give
preference to creation’s gifts: the Endangered
Species Act, which says a species’ right to survive
trumps capital’s right to short-term gain. The
trouble is, the law comes into play only when a species
has been so devastated it’s on the brink of
extinction. Even then, the courts don’t always
enforce it. Recently, in a very dry year, the government
reduced its delivery of subsidized water to California
farmers because endangered fish needed it to survive.
Some farmers sued, arguing that the government had
unconstitutionally “taken” their property. A
federal court agreed, the Bush administration refused to
appeal, and the farmers collected $13 million in
damages.
It seems to me that, if anything is divine, it
should be gifts of creation. Morally, they’re gifts
we inherit together and must pass on, undiminished, to
future generations. Economically, they’re
irreplaceable and invaluable capital. Protection of these
shared assets should trump transient private gain. Broad
benefit should trump narrow benefit. The commons should
trump capital. This should be written into our economic
operating system and enforced by the courts. ...
A trustee isn’t the same thing as a steward.
Stewards care for an asset, but their obligations are
voluntary and vague. By contrast, trustees’
obligations are mandatory and quite specific. Trusteeship
is thus a more formal and rigorous responsibility than
stewardship.
Trusts can be in charge of financial as well as
physical assets. In this chapter, my concern is natural
assets — gifts we inherit from creation.
One of my premises is that each generation has a
contract to pass on such gifts, undiminished, to those
not yet born. If we are to keep this contract, someone
must act as trustee of nature’s gifts, or at least
of the most endangered of them. The question is,
who?
The candidates are government, corporations, and
trusts. I argued earlier that neither corporations nor
government can fulfill this function; they’re both
too bound to short-term private interests. That leaves
trusts. ...
read the whole chapter
|
To share this page with a friend:
right click, choose "send," and add your
comments.
|
|
Red links have not been
visited; .
Green links are pages you've seen
|
Essential Documents pertinent
to this theme:
|
|