Contractarianism
Nic Tideman: Peace,
Justice and Economic Reform
Suppose first that voters vote on the basis of their
selfish personal interests. Then voting is incoherent as
a basis for justice. If voters always vote selfishly,
then at any time when you might think that the voting was
over, there will always be some measure that can be
proposed that will benefit a majority at the expense of a
minority, which could therefore be adopted by selfish
voting. The process of deciding by voting will never end
if any proposal can be advanced at any time and people
always vote selfishly. Selfish voting can be used to
decide between any two proposals. And it can be used in
more general settings if there is some more or less
arbitrary stopping rule to keep the process from going on
indefinitely. But selfish voting as a general mechanism
for determining what is just is incoherent.
Now suppose that voters behave as unselfish,
disinterested judges of what is best. In this case,
voting as a mechanism for determining what is just is
incomplete, because it leaves unanswered the question of
what is meant by "best." Does "best" mean "creates the
greatest total utility" or "comes closest to preserving
the expectations of the status quo" or "maximizes the
rate of growth of the population" or something else? How
would you know what best means? If the Supreme Court
knows that what is best is what comes closest to
preserving the expectations that have developed from our
Constitution and traditions, then the justices can employ
voting to decide cases and establish new precedents. But
to say that what is just is what is voted to be best by
unselfish, disinterested judges without specifying what
best means is to decline to answer the question of what
justice is. Thus neither selfish voting nor unselfish
voting serves to define justice, although there can be an
element of voting in our efforts to resolve disagreements
about what an agreed definition of justice requires in
particular circumstances.
If voting cannot be used to define justice, one might
entertain the possibility of using a contractarian
formulation: What is just is the rules to which people
would have agreed if they did not know their personal
circumstances. In his 1958 paper, "Justice
as Fairness," John Rawls said,
[Suppose that a group lets] each
person propose the principles upon which he wishes his
complaints to be tried with the understanding that, if
acknowledged, the complaints of others will be
similarly tried, and that no complaints will be heard
at all until everyone is roughly of one mind as to how
the complaints are to be judged. . . . each person will
propose principles of a general kind which will, to a
large degree, gain their sense from the various
applications to be made of them, the particular
circumstances of which being as yet
unknown.[3]
This is a reasonable recipe for implementing the
Golden Rule and a fine idea for seeking agreement about
the principles by which complaints shall be judged. If
people were to follow this suggestion and achieve the
agreement that is described, they would achieve
fairness.
However, this does not make Rawls's suggestion a good
way to identify justice. The critical difficulty with his
suggestion is that those who mete out justice cannot
afford the luxury of securing complete agreement on
principles. They must bring their judgement to bear on
those who have not agreed on principles. In this context,
the closest that a person can come to Rawls' suggestion
is to ask himself, "Are the principles that I
propose to apply ones that I would agree to if I did not
know how I would personally be affected by
them?"
In later writings, Rawls claims that in the original
position, people would choose the rules that maximized
the well-being of the representative member of the least
advantaged class.[4] John Harsanyi, on the other
hand, has said that in the original position people would
choose the rules that maximized average
utility.[5]
Someone else might say that in the original position
people would choose the rules that provided the greatest
stability. How can we know what people would choose?
No matter how a contractarian answers this question,
there will be the difficulty raised by Ackerman, in
Social Justice in the Liberal State.
Describing the attempt to apply the Rawlsian criterion,
Ackerman says:
Despite my best efforts, I shall be defenseless . .
. the moment I try to make it clear to another person
why it is right that I, rather than he, should
establish a claim over a disputed thing: I: When I look
into myself, I am sure that I would have insisted upon
this right as a condition for entering society with
you. YOU: You haven't the slightest idea what you would
have insisted on in a presocial state. You're simply
using the idea of a potential entrant as a screen upon
which to project the deepest desires of your socialized
self. But I too have desires; why should mine be
sacrificed to yours? And if you insist, it is possible
that I too may delve deep into my psyche and find a
transcendent grounding for my
desires.[6]
The sword of justice is too momentous to be
constrained by only the requirement that those who judge
be able to convince themselves that their judgements
satisfy principles to which they would have agreed, if
they had not known how they would be affected by those
principles. The contractarian approach may be a good way
to seek consensus. It may be a good guideline for those
who are called upon by disputants to arbitrate between
them. But it is not a good way to define justice.
read the whole
essay
Nic Tideman: The Ethics of Coercion
in Public Finance
A second common way of coping with
the lack of disinterested parties is through
Contractarianism. This is the axiom that it is just to
coerce people to abide by rules to which they would have
agreed before they knew how they would be personally
affected by the rules.
There are several theories of justice
that employ the Contractarian axiom. In The
Calculus of Consent (1962), Buchanan and
Tullock develop a theory of democratic principles growing
out of a "constitutional setting." In this setting people
are presumed to reach a consensus on rules with the
greatest aggregate value, because they do not know what
their roles will be in conflicts to which the rules will be
applied.
The most famous modern application of
Contractarianism is John Rawls' 1971 book, A
Theory of Justice. Rawls argues that behind a "veil of
ignorance" regarding one's personal characteristics, a
person would want the rules that maximized the well-being
of the representative member of the least advantaged class.
To most economists, Rawls' specification of what would
concern people behind a veil of ignorance sounds completely
arbitrary and unfounded. If people are going to be
overwhelmingly concerned about losing in the lottery of
life, why would they focus on the representative member of
the least advantaged class and not on the worst possible
individual outcome? Why would people be unwilling to trade
a minute loss by the least advantaged class for a
substantial gain by the second-least advantaged
class?
John Harsanyi (1975) argues that
behind Rawls' veil of ignorance, people would not be
concerned exclusively with the well-being of the
representative member of the least advantaged class.
Rather, they would recognize that they had equal chances of
being all persons, and therefore, to maximize their
expected utility, they would choose the rules that
maximized the sum of individual utilities. The Buchanan and
Tullock framework is consistent with Harsanyi's
claim.
Another theory that applies the
Contractarian axiom is Ronald Dworkin's (1981) theory of
justice as equality of resources. Dworkin
justifies an income tax as the expression of an insurance
policy that people would desire before they knew their
talents.
The fact that people using the basic
idea of Contractarianism could come to conclusions as
different as those of Rawls and Harsanyi is a reflection of
a limitation of the axiom. Even if one of them has it wrong
and the other right, the disagreement suggests that the
Contractarian axiom is inevitably too vague and too subject
to self-serving or idiosyncratic interpretations to serve
as a basis for achieving consensus.3
To put the difficulty with
Contractarianism in a somewhat different light, suppose
that a person asks, "Why is it just for you to use your
power to deprive me of what I want?" The Contractarian
exercising power responds, "Because you would have agreed
to the rule that deprives you, before you knew what your
role in this dispute would be." The deprived person can
respond, "No, not me. I never would have agreed to that."
To justify the deprivation, the Contractarian must declare
that the deprived person is mistaken or deceitful about
that to which he would have agreed. Anything that the
deprived person says about who he is or what has happened
in his life can be declared to be irrelevant to the
question of what rules he would actually have favored in a
properly constructed contractual setting. The
flesh-and-blood person asking for a justification of power
goes unanswered.
Contractarianism does have potential
value as an organizing principle for seeking to resolve
disputes, because sometimes it will be possible to persuade
a person involved in a dispute that what he seeks is
inconsistent with a rule to which he would have agreed
before he knew his personal role in the particular dispute.
But Contractarianism is dangerously vague as limit on what
people with power accord to themselves. It is too easy to
convince oneself that people would have agreed to whatever
you like in the hypothetical contractual setting....
Read the whole article
Nic Tideman:
Improving Efficiency and Preventing Exploitation in Taxing
and Spending Decisions
Rawls sets his proposals in the framework of a fourth
possible principle of public action, the contractarian suggestion that it is just to
coerce people to abide by the rules that they would have
agreed to if they had had a chance, before they knew
their individual circumstances. One difficulty with this
rule is that it is so hard to know what it is that people
would have agreed to in these circumstances. Rawls is
convinced that people would have agreed to a lexical
ordering of maximum individual liberty and the maximin
principle. John Harsanyi offers a strong argument for the
proposition that they would have agreed to the rules that
would maximize total (or, equivalently, average) utility.
This has some strange implications. For example, if it is
possible to separate individuals into ascetics and
sybarites, then the maximization of total utility
requires that the ascetics be forced to work very hard,
with the resulting output used for the benefit of the
sybarites. And if one of your kidneys (or your eyes)
would provide me with more utility than it provides you,
then the state is justified in extracting it from you and
giving it to me. Utilitarianism does not accommodate
individual rights.
The disagreements among contractarians about what
contractarianism implies provide a hint of a difficulty
that Bruce Ackerman elaborates in Social
Justice in the Liberal State: Contractarianism offers
so little defense against people with power who delude
themselves about the undeniability of their beliefs about
what people would agree to before they knew their
personal circumstances. The person who feels oppressed
says "I never would have agreed to these rules before I
knew my personal circumstances." Those with power reply,
"It's obvious to us that you would have. Stop your
griping." The scope for further dialogue is small, and
the potential for abuse is great.
Another possible framework for the
justification of government action is that those with
power are simply elitists: They may believe that their
exercise of power is justified by their superior
understanding of the nature of the good. While it
is not unreasonable to suggest that there are some
persons who do have superior understanding of the nature
of the good, it is extremely dangerous for people to
justify the exercise of political power by self
identification as members of the elite who have superior
understanding of the nature of the good. It was thinking
of that sort that gave the world Stalinism. The general
thrust of Western political thinking has been that
elitism is simply unacceptable as a justification for the
exercise of political power.
On the basis of the arguments given,
I reject conservatism, majoritarianism, egalitarianism,
contractarianism, and elitism as justifications for
coercive taxing and spending. A framework for just
social arrangements that does make sense to me is
classical liberalism, which asserts that it is just to
coerce people to accord others the maximum individual
liberty that all can have. This means that people have
rights to their bodies, their talents, the products of
their labor, and the returns to their savings. Anything
produced by human effort belong to the producer, or to
the producer's successor in title through gift and
exchange. ...
read the whole article
|
To share this page with a friend:
right click, choose "send," and add your
comments.
|
|
Red links have not been
visited; .
Green links are pages you've seen
|
Essential Documents pertinent
to this theme:
|
|