Henry George — A
Perplexed Philosopher
Part III—Recantation
(continued)
Chapter XII —
Justice—"The Land Question"
While Justice shows no decadence of
intellectual power, and those who have seen the utterances
of a great thinker in preceding volumes of the Synthetic
Philosophy will doubtless have as high an opinion of this,
there is in it everywhere, as compared with Social
Statics, the evidence of moral decadence, and of that
perplexity which is the penalty of deliberate sacrifice of
intellectual honesty. But it were wearying, and for our
purpose needless, to review the subsequent chapters of
Justice, and to show the contradictions and
confusions into which Mr. Spencer falls at every turn,25
and the manner in which he recants his previously expressed
opinions on such subjects as the political rights of women,
and even the equal political rights of men. To complete the
examination of that cross-section of his teachings which in
the beginning I proposed, let us proceed to the
consideration of his very last word on the land question,
the note to which he refers the reader at the close of the
chapter on 'The Rights to the Uses of Natural Media.'
This note is to be found among the appendices to
Justice, which consist of Appendix A, "The Kantian
Idea of Rights," before referred to (-Chapter IX-);
Appendix B, "The Land Question"; Appendix C, "The Moral
Motive," a reply to a criticism by the Rev. J. Llewellyn
Davis; and Appendix D, "Conscience in Animals," which is a
collection of dog stories.
The idea that for the genesis of all there is in man,
even his moral perceptions, we must look down, not up,
permeates the Synthetic Philosophy, seeking to obliterate
the gulf between man and other animals by greedily
swallowing every traveler's tale that tends to degrade man
and every wonder-monger's story that ascribes human
faculties to brutes. Thus Justice begins with
"Animal Ethics" and ends with dog stories, the appendix
devoted to them being twice as large as that devoted to
"The Land Question" and illustrated with
diagrams.26
26 The dog stories which close this
crowning book of the Synthetic Philosophy are sent to Mr.
Spencer by Mr. T. Mann Jones, of Devon, with this
introduction:
"DEAR Sir: The following careful observations on animals
other than man, may be of interest to you as supporting
your idea that the idea of 'duty' or 'ought' (owe it) may
be of 'non-supernatural' origin. 'Supernatural' is used
in the usual sense, without committing the writer to any
opinion."
These "careful observations" are indorsed by Mr. Spencer
as highly remarkable and instructive, and as supporting
his own conclusion, and he tells us, apparently on the
faith of them, that Mr. Jones is a careful, critical and
trustworthy observer. To give a sample, here is one of
the observations, which as it has no diagrams, I may
quote as printed:
"The 'ought' may be established as an obligation to a
higher mind in opposition to the promptings of the
strongest feelings of the animal; e.g.—
"A bitch I had many years ago showed great pleasure at
the attentions of male dogs, when in season. I checked
her repeatedly, by voice only. This set up the 'ought' so
thoroughly, that though never tied up at such times, she
died a virgin at thirteen and a half years old."
These dog stories are, however, fit companions to the
savage stories with which, by the assistance of a corps of
readers, the volumes of the Synthetic Philosophy are
profusely embellished. The wooden literalness with which,
to suit himself, Mr. Spencer interprets the imagery and
metaphor of which the language of all peoples who come
close to nature is full, is perhaps the most comical thing
in this unconsciously comic collection. I hesitate to give
an instance, such is the embarrassment of riches; but here,
to quote at random, is one. It is from the chapter on 'The
Religious Idea' in Principles of Sociology. Mr. Spencer has
been showing to his own satisfaction, and doubtless to that
of the gentlemen who regard him as greater than Aristotle,
how from the adoption of such family names as Wolf, and the
habit of speaking of a strong man as "a bear," the less
civilized peoples, whom he generically lumps as "savages,"
have come to believe that their ancestors passed into
animals. He goes on to show "how naturally the
identification of stars with persons may occur." Recalling
first, what he declares to be "the belief of some North
Americans that the brighter stars in the Milky Way are
camp-fires made by the dead on their way to the other
world," this is the fashion in which he does it:
When a sportsman, hearing a shot in the
adjacent wood, exclaims, "That's Jones!" he is not
supposed to mean that Jones is the sound; he is known to
mean that Jones made the sound. But when a savage,
pointing to a particular star originally thought of as
the camp-fire of such or such a departed man, says,
"There he is," the children he is instructing naturally
suppose him to mean that the star itself is the departed
man; especially when receiving the statement through an
undeveloped language.—Principles of Sociology, Vol.
II, p. 685.
"Lo, the poor Indian!"
What would happen to the beliefs of savage children if
their undeveloped language enabled them to receive such
information as is often conveyed through our developed
language — such, for instance, as "She's a daisy!" or
"He's a brick!" or "You would have to use a pickaxe to get
a joke through his head"?
But I am keeping the reader from "The Land Question."
This is, for our purpose at least, the most important
utterance of what its author deems the most important book
of the great Synthetic Evolutionary Philosophy — a
book that begins with "Animal Ethics," and ends with dog
stories. I quote this appendix in full:
APPENDIX B — THE LAND QUESTION
The course of Nature, "red in tooth and
claw," has been, on a higher plane, the course of
civilization. Through "blood and iron" small clusters of
men have been consolidated into larger ones, and these
again into still larger ones, until nations have been
formed. This process, carried on everywhere and always by
brute force, has resulted in a history of wrongs upon
wrongs: savage tribes have been slowly welded together by
savage means. We could not, if we tried, trace back the
acts of unscrupulous violence committed during these
thousands of years; and could we trace them back we could
not rectify their evil results.
Landownership was established during this
process; and if the genesis of landownership was full of
iniquities, they were iniquities committed not by the
ancestors of any one class of existing men but by the
ancestors of all existing men. The remote forefathers of
living Englishmen were robbers, who stole the lands of
men who were themselves robbers, who behaved in like
manner to the robbers who preceded them. The usurpation
by the Normans, here complete and there partial, was of
lands which, centuries before, had been seized, some by
piratical Danes and Norsemen, and some at an earlier time
by hordes of invading Frisians or old English. And then
the Celtic owners, expelled or enslaved by these had in
bygone ages themselves expropriated the people who lived
in the underground houses here and there still traceable.
What would happen if we tried to restore lands
inequitably taken if Normans had to give them back to
Danes and Norse and Frisians, and these again to Celts,
and these again to the men who lived in caves and used
flint implements? The only imaginable form of the
transaction would be a restoration of Great Britain
bodily to the Welsh and the Highlanders; and if the Welsh
and the Highlanders did not make a kindred restoration,
it could only be on the ground that, having not only
taken the land of the aborigines but killed them, they
had thus justified their ownership!
The wish now expressed by many that
landownership should be conformed to the requirements of
pure equity, is in itself commendable; and is in some men
prompted by conscientious feeling. One would, however,
like to hear from such the demand that not only here but
in the various regions we are peopling, the requirements
of pure equity should be conformed to. As it is, the
indignation against wrongful appropriations of land, made
in the past at home, is not accompanied by any
indignation against the more wrongful appropriations made
at present abroad. Alike as holders of the predominant
political power and as furnishing the rank and file of
our armies, the masses of the people are responsible for
those nefarious doings all over the world which end in
the seizing of new territories and expropriation of their
inhabitants. The filibustering
expeditions of the old English are repeated, on a vastly
larger scale, in the filibustering expeditions of the new
English. Yet those who execrate ancient usurpations utter
no word of protest against these far greater modern
usurpations — nay, are aiders and abetters in them.
Remaining as they do passive and silent while there is
going on this universal land-grabbing which their votes
could stop; and supplying as they do the soldiers who
effect it; they are responsible for it. By deputy they
are committing in this matter grosser and more numerous
injustices than were committed against their
forefathers.
That the masses of landless men should
regard private landownership as having been wrongfully
established, is natural and, as we have seen, they are
not without warrant. But if we entertain the thought of
rectification, there arises in the first place the
question — Which are the wronged and which are the
wrongers? Passing over the primary fact that the
ancestors of existing Englishmen, landed and landless,
were, as a body, men who took the land by violence from
previous owners; and thinking only of the force and fraud
by which certain of these ancestors obtained possession
of the land while others of them lost possession; the
preliminary question is — Which are the descendants
of the one and of the other? It is tacitly assumed that
those who now own lands are the posterity of the
usurpers, and that those who now have no lands are the
posterity of those who lands were usurped. But this is
far from being the case. The fact that among the nobility
there are very few whose titles go back to the days when
the last usurpations took place, and none to the days
when there took place the original usurpations; joined
with the fact that among existing landowners there are
many whose names imply artisan ancestors; show that we
have not now to deal with descendants of those who
unjustly appropriated the land. While, conversely, the
numbers of the landless whose names prove that their
forefathers belonged to the higher ranks (numbers which
must be doubled to take account of intermarriages with
female descendents) show that among those who are now
without land, many inherit the blood of the
land-usurpers. Hence, that bitter feeling toward the
landed which contemplation of the past generates in many
of the landless, is in great measure misplaced. They are
themselves to a considerable extent descendants of the
sinners; while those they scowl at are to a considerable
extent descendants of the sinned-against.
But granting all that is said about past
iniquities, and leaving aside all other obstacles in the
way of an equitable arrangement, there is an obstacle
which seems to have been overlooked. Even supposing that
the English as a race gained possession of the land
equitably, which they did not; and even supposing that
existing landowners are the posterity of those who
spoiled their fellows, which in large part they are not;
and even supposing that the existing landless are the
posterity of the despoiled, which in large part they are
not; there would still have to be recognized a
transaction that goes far to prevent rectification of
injustices. If we are to go back upon the past at all, we
must go back upon the past wholly, and take account not
only of that which the people at large have lost by
private appropriation of land, but also that which they
have received in the form of a share of the returns
— we must take account, that is, of Poor-Law
relief. Mr. T. Mackay, author of The English Poor, has
kindly furnished me with the following memoranda, showing
something like the total amount of this since the 43d
Elizabeth (1601) in England and Wales.
"Sir G. Nicholls (History of Poor Law,
appendix to Vol. II) ventures no estimate till 1688. At
that date he puts the poor rate at nearly £700,000 a
year. Till the beginning of this century the amounts are
based more or less on estimate.
1601-1630. say 3 millions.
1631-1700. (1688 Nicholls puts at 700,000.) 30 "
1701-1720. (1701 Nicholls puts at 900,000.) 20 "
1721-1760. 1760 Nicholls says 11 millions.) 40 "
1761-1775. (17 75 put at 11 millions.) 22 "
1776-1800. (1784 2 millions.) 50 "
1801-1812. (1803 4 millions; 1813 6 millions.) 65 "
1813-1840. (based on exact figures given by Sir G.
Nicholls.) 170 "
1841-1890. (based on Mulhall's Diet. of Statistics and
Statistical Abstract.) 334 "
734 millions"
The above represents the amount expended in
relief of the poor. Under the general term "poor-rate,"
moneys have always been collected for other purposes
— county, borough, police rates, etc. The following
table shows the annual amounts of these in connection
with the annual amounts expended on the poor:
Total levied Expended on poor Other
purposes
Sir G. Nicholls In 1803 5,348,000 4,077,000
1,271,000
In 1813 6,656,106 1,990,735
In 1853 4,939,064 1,583,341
Total spent Sum spent
StatisticalAbstract
In 1875 12,694,208 7,488,481 5,205,727
In 1889 15,970,126 8,366,477 7,603,649
In addition, therefore, to
sums set out in the first table, there is a further sum,
rising during the century from 11 to 71 millions per
annum, 'for other purposes.'
"Mulhall, on whom I relied for figures
between 1853 and 1875, does not give 'other
expenditure'."
Of course of the £734,000,000 given to
the poorer members of the landless class during three
centuries, a part has arisen from rates on houses; only
such portion of which as is chargeable against
ground-rents, being rightly included in the sum the land
has contributed. From a landowner, who is at the same
time a Queen's Counsel, frequently employed
professionally to arbitrate in questions of local
taxation, I have received the opinion that if, out of the
total sum received by the poor, £500,000,000 is
credited to the land, this will be an underestimate. Thus
even if we ignore the fact that this amount, gradually
contributed, would, if otherwise gradually invested, have
yielded in returns of one or other kind a far larger sum,
it is manifest that against the claim of the landless may
be set off a large claim of the landed — perhaps a
larger claim.
For now observe that the landless have not
an equitable claim to the land in its present state
cleared, drained, fenced, fertilized, and furnished with
farm-buildings, etc. — but only to the land in its
primitive state, here stony and there marshy, covered
with forest, gorse, heather, etc.; this only, it is,
which belongs to the community. Hence, therefore, the
question arises — What is the relation between the
original "prairie value" of the land, and the amount
which the poorer among the landless have received during
these three centuries? Probably the landowners would
contend that for the land in its primitive, unsubdued
state, furnishing nothing but wild animals and wild
fruits, £500,000,000 would be a high price.
When, in Social Statics, published
in 1850, I drew from the law of equal freedom the
corollary that the land could not equitably be alienated
from the community, and argued that, after compensating
its existing holders, it should be reappropriated by the
community, I overlooked the foregoing considerations.
Moreover, I did not clearly see what would be implied by
the giving of compensation for all that value which the
labor of ages has given to the land. While, as shown in
Chapter Xl, I adhere to the inference originally drawn,
that the aggregate of men forming the community are the
supreme owners of the land — an inference
harmonizing with legal doctrine and daily acted upon in
legislation — a fuller consideration of the matter
has led me to the conclusion that individual ownership,
subject to state suzerainty, should be maintained.
Even were it possible to rectify the
inequitable doings which have gone on during past
thousands of years, and by some balancing of claims and
counter-claims, past and present, to make a rearrangement
equitable in the abstract, the resulting state of things
would be a less desirable one than the present. Setting
aside all financial objections to nationalization (which
of themselves negative the transaction, since, if
equitably effected, it would be a losing one), it
suffices to remember the inferiority of public
administration to private administration, to see that
ownership by the state would work ill. Under the existing
system of ownership, those who manage the land,
experience a direct connection between effort and
benefit; while, were it under state ownership, those who
managed it would experience no such direct connection.
The vices of officialism would inevitably entail immense
evils.
Was ever philosopher so perplexed before?
Mr. Spencer started out in 1850 to tell us what are our
rights to land. And, excepting that he fell into some
confusion by carelessly transforming equal rights into
joint rights, he clearly did so. But now, in 1892, and in
the climax of the Spencerian Synthetic Philosophy, he has
got himself into a maze, in which the living and the dead
— Normans, Danes, Norsemen, Frisians, Celts, Saxons,
Welsh, and Highlanders; old English and new English;
plebeians with aristocratic names, and aristocrats with
plebeian names, and female descendants who have changed
their names; ancient filibusters and modern filibusters
— are all so whirling round that, in sheer despair,
he springs for guidance to "a landowner who is at the same
time a Queen's Counsel," and is led by him plump into the
English poor law and a long array of figures.
Yet, in the mad whirl he still pretends to consistency.
"I adhere," he says, "to the inference originally drawn,
that the aggregate of men forming the community are the
supreme owners of the land."
Here is that inference in his own words — the
inference originally drawn in Social Statics:
Given a race of beings having like claims to pursue the
objects of their desires — given a world adapted to
the gratification of those desires — a world into
which such beings are similarly born, and it unavoidably
follows that they have equal rights to the use of this
world … Equity, therefore, does not permit property
in land … The right of mankind at large to the
earth's surface is still valid; all deeds, customs, and
laws notwithstanding.
What is it that Mr. Spencer here asserts? Not that men
derive their rights to the use of the earth by gift,
bequest or inheritance, from their ancestors, or from any
previous men, but that they derive them from the fact of
their own existence. Who lived on the earth before them, or
what such predecessors did, has nothing whatever to do with
the matter. The equal right to the use of land belongs to
each man as man. It begins with his birth; it continues
till his death. It can be destroyed or superseded by no
human action whatever.
And this is the ground on which, without exception,
stand all who demand the resumption of equal rights to
land. Where there has been any reference on their part to
the wrongfulness of past appropriations of land, it has
merely been — as in the case of Mr. Spencer himself
in Social Statics — by way of illustrating
the origin of private property in land, not by way of
basing the demand for the rights of living men on the proof
of wrongs done to dead men.27 Neither Mr. Spencer in his
"straight" days, nor any one else who has stood for equal
rights in land, ever dreamed of such a stultifying
proposition as that the right to the use of land must be
drawn from some dispossessed generation, for this would be
to assert what he so ridiculed, that "God has given one
charter of privilege to one generation and another to the
next."
27 I, for instance, have
uniformly asserted that it made no difference whatever
whether land has been made private property by force or
by consent; that the equal right to its use is a natural
and inalienable right of the living, and that this is the
ground, and the only ground, on which the resumption of
those rights should be demanded. Thus in The Irish
Land Question, in 1881, I said:
"The indictment which really lies against
the Irish landlords is not that their ancestors or the
ancestors of their grantors robbed the ancestors of the
Irish people. That makes no difference. 'Let the dead
bury their dead.' The indictment that truly lies is,
that here and now, they rob the Irish people …
The greatest enemy of the people's cause is he who
appeals to national passions and excites old hatreds.
He is its best friend who does his utmost to bury them
out of sight."
Yet, now, this same Herbert Spencer actually assumes
that the only question of moral right as to land is, who
robbed whom, in days whereof the very memory has perished,
and when, according to him, everybody was engaged in
robbing everybody else. He not only eats his own words,
denies his own perceptions, and endeavors to confuse the
truth he once bore witness to, but he assumes that the
whole great movement for the recognition of equal rights to
land, that is beginning to show its force wherever the
English tongue is spoken, has for its object only
rectification of past injustices — the ridiculous
search, in which he pretends to engage, as to what ancestor
robbed what ancestor — and that until that is
discovered, those who now hold as their private property
the inalienable heritage of all may hold it still. And in
the course of this "argument," this advocate of the rich
against the poor, of the strong against the weak, declares
that the toiling masses of England, made ignorant and
brutal and powerless by their disinheritance, have lost
their natural rights by serving as food for powder and
payers of taxes in foreign wars waged by the ruling
classes.
This is bad enough; but more follows. Mr. Spencer
discovers a new meaning in the English poor laws.
In Social Statics, be it remembered, he
declared that the equal right to the use of land is the
natural, direct, inalienable right of all men, having its
derivation in the fact of their existence, and of which
they can in no possible way be equitably deprived. He
declared, that equity does not permit private property in
land, and that it is impossible to discover any mode by
which land can become private property. He scouted the idea
that force can give right, or that sale or bequest or
prescription can make invalid claims valid; saying that,
"though nothing be multiplied forever, it will not produce
one"; asking, "How long does it take for what was
originally wrong to grow into a right? and at what rate per
annum do invalid claims become valid?" He declared that
neither use nor improvement, nor even the free consent of
all existing men, could give private ownership in land, or
bar the equal right of the next child born. And he,
moreover, proved that land nationalization, which he then
proposed as the only equitable treatment of land, did not
involve state administration.
Not one of the arguments of Social Statics is
answered in Justice — not even the showing
that land nationalization merely involves a change in the
receivers of rent, and not the governmental occupation and
use of land. There are two things, and two things only,
that Mr. Spencer admits that he overlooked — the
relation of the poor law to the claims of landowners, and
the amount of compensation which the landless must give to
the landed "for all that value which the labor of ages has
given to the land."
Mr. Spencer has discussed the poor law before. One of
the longest of the chapters of Social Statics,
from which I have already quoted,28 is devoted to it;
and in recent writings he has again referred to it. In
Social Statics he declares that the excuse made
for a poor law — that it is a compensation to the
disinherited for the deprivation of their birthright
— has much plausibility; but he objects, not only
that the true remedy is to restore equal rights to land,
but that the poor law does not give compensation, insisting
that poor-rates are in the main paid by non-landowners, and
that it is only here and there that one of those kept out
of their inheritance gets any part of them.
28 pp. 64-65.
In 1884, in "The Coming Slavery," he repeats the
assertion that non-landowners get no benefit from the poor
law, saying —
The amount which under the old poor law the
half-pauperised laborer received from the parish to eke
out his weekly income was not really, as it appeared, a
bonus, for it was accompanied by a substantially
equivalent decrease of his wages, as was quickly proved
when the system was abolished and the wages rose.
In "The Sins of Legislators," he repeats that instead of
being paid by landowners, the poor-rates really fall on
nonlandowners, saying —
As, under the old poor law, the diligent
and provident laborer had to pay that the
good-for-nothings might not suffer, until frequently,
under this extra burden, he broke down and himself took
refuge in the workhouse — as, at present, it is
admitted that the total rates levied in large towns for
all public purposes, have now reached such a height that
they "cannot be exceeded without inflicting great
hardship on the small shopkeepers and artisans, who
already find it difficult enough to keep themselves free
from pauper taint."
But in Appendix B Mr. Spencer ignores all this. He
assumes that landowners have been the real payers and the
disinherited the real receivers of the poor-rates; and,
adding together all that the landowners have paid in
poor-rates since the time of Queen Elizabeth, he puts the
whole sum to their credit in a ledger account between
existing landlords and existing landless.
He begins this account at 1601. He credits the landlords
and charges the landless with all that has been collected
from land for poor-rates between 1601 and 1890. Now, if
this is done, what is to be put on the other side of the
ledger? We must take the same date, the ordinary
book-keeper would say, and charge the landlords and credit
the landless with all the ground-rents the landowners have
received from 1601 to 1890. To this we must add all that
the landowners have received from the produce of general
taxes between 1601 and 1890, by virtue of their political
power as landlords.29 And to this we
must again add the selling value in 1890 of the land of
England, exclusive of improvements. The difference will
show what, if we are to go back to 1601, and no further,
existing landlords now owe to existing landless.
29 The Financial Reform Almanac
has given some idea of what enormous sums the British
landowners have received from the offices, pensions and
sinecures they have secured for them-selves and from
their habit of providing for younger sons and poorer
relatives in the army, navy, church and civil
administration.
This would be the way of ordinary, every-day bookkeeping
if it were undertaken to make up such a debtor and creditor
account from 1601 to 1890. But this is not the way of
Spencerian synthetic book-keeping. What Mr. Spencer does,
after crediting landlords and charging the landless with
the amount collected from land for poor-rates between 1601
and 1890, is, omitting all reference to mesne profits, to
credit the landless and charge the landlords with the value
of the land of England, not as it is, but "in its
primitive, unsubdued state, furnishing nothing but wild
animals and wild fruits" — that is, before there were
any men. This — though by what sort of synthetic
calculus he gets at it he does not tell us — Mr.
Spencer estimates at £500,000,000, a sum that will
about square the account, with some little balance on the
side of the landlords!
Generous to the poor landless is Mr. Accountant Spencer!
— so generous that he ought to make a note of it in
writing Part VI of his Principles of Ethics — The
Ethics of Social Life: Positive Beneficence. For is it not
positive beneficence to those who are to be credited with
it to say that £500,000,000 would be a high estimate
of the value of England when there was nothing there but
wild animals and wild fruit? To one of less wide
magnificence two and threepence would seem to be rather
more than a high estimate of the value of the land of
England before man came.
Previous
chapter • Next chapter •
Table of Contents
|
To share this page with a friend:
right click, choose "send," and add your
comments.
|
themes:
see_also
|
Red links have not been
visited; .
Green links are pages you've seen
|
|