Production
Production includes distribution. And services, be
they rendered by highly educated and trained
professionals or people who have not completed high
school, are part of production.
Henry George:
Progress & Poverty:
The Current Doctrine of Wages — Its
Insufficiency
But the fundamental truth, that in all
economic reasoning must be firmly grasped, and never let
go, is that society in its most highly developed form is
but an elaboration of society in its rudest beginnings,
and that principles obvious in the simpler relations of
men are merely disguised and not abrogated or reversed by
the more intricate relations that result from the
division of labor and the use of complex tools and
methods. The steam grist mill, with its complicated
machinery exhibiting every diversity of motion, is simply
what the rude stone mortar dug up from an ancient river
bed was in its day — an instrument for grinding
corn. And every man engaged in it, whether tossing wood
into the furnace, running the engine, dressing stones,
printing sacks or keeping books, is really devoting his
labor to the same purpose that the prehistoric savage did
when he used his mortar — the preparation of grain
for human food.
And so, if we reduce to their lowest terms all the
complex operations of modern production, we see that each
individual who takes part in this infinitely subdivided
and intricate network of production and exchange is
really doing what the primeval man did when he climbed
the trees for fruit or followed the receding tide for
shellfish — endeavoring to obtain
from nature by the exertion of his powers the
satisfaction of his desires. If we keep this firmly
in mind, if we look upon production as a whole — as
the co-operation of all embraced in any of its great
groups to satisfy the various desires of each, we plainly
see that the reward each obtains for his exertions comes
as truly and as directly from nature as the result of
that exertion, as did that of the first man.
To illustrate: in the simplest state of which we can
conceive, each man digs his own bait and catches his own
fish. The advantages of the division of labor soon
become apparent, and one digs bait while the others fish.
Yet evidently the one who digs bait is in reality doing
as much toward the catching of fish as any of those who
actually take the fish. So when the advantages of canoes
are discovered, and instead of all going a-fishing, one
stays behind and makes and repairs canoes, the
canoe-maker is in reality devoting his labor to the
taking of fish as much as the actual fishermen, and the
fish which he eats at night when the fishermen come home
are as truly the product of his labor as of theirs. And
thus when the division of labor is fairly inaugurated,
and instead of each attempting to satisfy all of his
wants by direct resort to nature, one fishes, another
hunts, a third picks berries, a fourth gathers fruit, a
fifth makes tools, a sixth builds huts, and a seventh
prepares clothing -- each one is to the extent he
exchanges the direct product of his own labor for the
direct product of the labor of others really applying his
own labor to the production of the things be uses -- is
in effect satisfying his particular desires by the
exertion of his particular powers; that is to say, what
be receives be in reality produces. If he digs roots and
exchanges them for venison, he is in effect as truly the
procurer of the venison as though be had gone in chase of
the deer and left the huntsman to dig his own roots.
The common expression, "I made so and so," signifying
"I earned so and so," or "I earned money with which I
purchased so and so," is, economically speaking, not
metaphorically but literally true. Earning is
making.
Now, if we follow these principles, obvious enough in
a simpler state of society, through the complexities of
the state we call civilized, we shall see clearly that in
every case in which labor is exchanged for commodities,
production really precedes enjoyment; that wages are the
earnings -- that is to say, the makings of labor —
not the advances of capital, and that the laborer who
receives his wages in money (coined or printed, it may
be, before his labor commenced) really receives in return
for the addition his labor has made to the general stock
of wealth, a draft upon that general stock, which he may
utilize in any particular form of wealth that will best
satisfy his desires; and that neither the money, which is
but the draft, nor the particular form of wealth which he
uses it to call for, represents advances of capital for
his maintenance, but on the contrary represents the
wealth, or a portion of the wealth, his labor has already
added to the general stock.
Keeping these principles in view we see that
- the draughtsman, who, shut up in some dingy office
on the banks of the Thames, is drawing the plans for a
great marine engine, is in reality devoting his labor
to the production of bread and meat as truly as though
he were garnering the grain in California or swinging a
lariat on a La Plata pampa; that he is as truly making
his own clothing as though he were shearing sheep in
Australia or weaving cloth in Paisley, and just as
effectually producing the claret he drinks at dinner as
though he gathered the grapes on the banks of the
Garonne.
- The miner who, two thousand feet under ground in
the heart of the Comstock, is digging out silver ore,
is, in effect, by virtue of a thousand exchanges,
harvesting crops in valleys five thousand feet nearer
the earth's center; chasing the whale through Arctic
icefields; plucking tobacco leaves in Virginia; picking
coffee berries in Honduras; cutting sugar cane on the
Hawaiian Islands; gathering cotton in Georgia or
weaving it in Manchester or Lowell; making quaint
wooden toys for his children in the Hartz Mountains; or
plucking amid the green and gold of Los Angeles
orchards the oranges which, when his shift is relieved,
he will take home to his sick wife.
The wages which he receives on Saturday night at the
mouth of the shaft, what are they but the certificate to
all the world that he has done these things -- the
primary exchange in the long series which transmutes his
labor into the things he has really been laboring for?
...
read the entire chapter
Rev. A. C. Auchmuty: Gems from George, a themed
collection of excerpts from the writings of Henry
George (with links to sources)
LET us try to trace the genesis of civilization.
Gifted alone with the power of relating cause and effect,
man is among all animals the only producer in the true
sense of the term. . . . But the same quality of reason
which makes him the producer, also, wherever exchange
becomes possible, makes him the exchanger. And it is
along this line of exchanging that the body economic is
evolved and develops, and that all the advances of
civilization are primarily made. . . . With the beginning
of exchange or trade among men this body economic begins
to form, and in its beginning civilization begins. . . .
To find an utterly uncivilized people, we must find a
people among whom there is no exchange or trade. Such a
people does not exist, and, as far as our knowledge goes,
never did. To find a fully civilized people, we must find
a people among whom exchange or trade is absolutely free,
and has reached the fullest development to which human
desires can carry it. There is, as yet, unfortunately, no
such people. — The Science of Political
Economy —
unabridged: Book I, Chapter 5, The Meaning of Political
Economy: The Origin and Genesis of Civilization
• abridged:
Chapter 4, The Origin and Genesis of
Civilization
WHEN we, come to analyze production, we find it to fall
into three modes, viz::
ADAPTING, or changing natural products either in form or
in place so as to fit them for the satisfaction of human
desire.
GROWING, or utilizing the vital forces of nature, as by
raising vegetables or animals.
EXCHANGING, or utilizing, so as to add to the general sum
of wealth, the higher powers of those natural forces
which vary with locality, or of those human forces which
vary with situation, occupation, or character. —
Progress & Poverty
— Book III, Chapter 3, The Laws of Distribution: of
Interest and the Cause of Interest
THESE modes seem to appear and to assume importance, in
the development of human society, much in the order here
given. They originate from the increase of the desires of
men with the increase of the means of satisfying them,
under pressure of the fundamental law of political
economy, that men seek to satisfy their desires with the
least exertion. In the primitive stage of human life the
readiest way of satisfying desires is by adapting to
human use what is found in existence. In a later and more
settled stage it is discovered that certain desires can
be more easily and more fully satisfied by utilizing the
principle of growth and reproduction, as by cultivating
vegetables and breeding animals. And in a still later
period of development, it becomes obvious that certain
desires can be better and more easily satisfied by
exchange, which brings out the principle of co-operation
more fully and powerfully than could obtain among
unexchanging economic units. — The Science of
Political Economy
unabridged: Book III, Chapter 2, The Production of
Wealth: The Three Modes of Production •
abridged: Part III, Chapter 2, The Production of Wealth:
The Three Modes of Production
IN the economic meaning of the term production, the
transporter or exchanger, or anyone engaged in any
subdivision of those functions, is as truly engaged in
production as is the primary extractor or maker. A
newspaper-carrier or the keeper of a news-stand would,
for instance, in common speech be styled a distributor.
But in economic terminology he is not a distributor of
wealth, but a producer of wealth. Although his part in
the process of producing the newspaper to the final
receiver comes last, not first, he is as much a producer
as the paper-maker or type-founder, the editor, or
compositor, or press-man. For the object of production is
the satisfaction of human desires, that is to say, it is
consumption; and this object is not made capable of
attainment, that is to say, production is not really
complete, until wealth is brought to the place where it
is to be consumed and put at the disposal of him whose
desire it is to satisfy. — The Science of
Political Economy
unabridged: Book III, Chapter 1, The Production of
Wealth: The Meaning of Production • abridged:
Part III, Chapter 1, The Production of Wealth: The
Meaning of Production
PRODUCTION and distribution are not separate things, but
two mentally distinguishable parts of one thing —
the exertion of human labor in the satisfaction of human
desire. Though materially distinguishable, they are as
closely related as the two arms of the syphon. And as it
is the outflow of water at the longer end of the syphon
that is the cause of the inflow of water at the shorter
end, so it is that distribution is really the cause of
production, not production the cause of distribution. In
the ordinary course, things are not distributed because
they have been produced, but are produced in order that
they may be distributed. Thus interference with the
distribution of wealth is interference with the
production of wealth, and shows its effect in lessened
production. — The Science of Political
Economy —
unabridged Book IV, Chapter 2, The Distribution of
Wealth: The Nature of Distribution • abridged
Part IV, Chapter 2, The Distribution of Wealth: The
Nature of Distribution
OUR inquiry into the laws of the distribution of wealth
is not an inquiry into the municipal laws or human
enactments which either here and now, or in any other
time and place, prescribe or have prescribed how wealth
shall be divided among men. With them we have no concern,
unless it may be for purposes of illustration. What we
have to seek are those laws of the distribution of wealth
which belong to the natural order — laws which are
a part of that system or arrangement which constitutes
the social organism or body economic, as distinguished
from the body politic or state, the Greater Leviathan
which makes its appearance with civilization and develops
with its advance. These natural laws are in all times and
places the same, and though they may be crossed by human
enactment, can never be annulled or swerved by it. It is
more needful to call this to mind, because, in what have
passed for systematic treatises on political economy, the
fact that it is with natural laws, not human laws, that
the science of political economy is concerned, has, in
treating of the distribution of wealth, been utterly
ignored, and even flatly denied. — The Science
of Political Economy —
unabridged: Part IV, Chapter 1, The Distribution of
Wealth: The Meaning of Distribution • abridged:
Part IV, Chapter 1, The Distribution of Wealth: The
Meaning of Distribution
THE distinction between the laws of production and the
laws of distribution is not, as is erroneously taught in
the scholastic political economy, that the one set of
laws are natural laws and the other human laws. Both sets
of laws are laws of nature. The real distinction is that
the natural laws of production are physical laws and the
natural laws of distribution are moral laws. . . . The
moment we turn from a consideration of the laws of the
production of wealth to a consideration of the laws of
the distribution of wealth, the idea of ought or duty
becomes primary. All consideration of distribution
involves the ethical principle, is necessarily a
consideration of ought or duty — a consideration in
which the idea of right or justice is from the very first
involved. — The Science of Political
Economy —
unabridged: Book IV, Chapter 4, The Distribution of
Wealth: The Real Difference Between Laws of Production
and of Distribution • abridged:
Part IV, Chapter 3: The Distribution of Wealth: Physical
and Moral Laws
Co-operation — its Two
Modes
ALL increase in the productive power of man over that
with which nature endows the individual comes from the
co-operation of individuals. But there are two ways in
which this co-operation may take place. 1. By the
combination of effort. In this way individuals may
accomplish what exceeds the full power of the individual.
2. By the separation of effort. In this way the
individual may accomplish for more than one what does not
require the full power of the individual. . . . To
illustrate: The first way of co-operation, the
combination of labor, enables a number of men to remove a
rock or to raise a log that would be too heavy for them
separately. In this way men conjoin themselves, as it
were, into one stronger man. Or, to take an example so
common in the early days of American settlement that
"log-rolling" has become a term for legislative
combination: Tom, Dick, Harry and Jim are building near
each other their rude houses in the clearings. Each hews
his own trees, but the logs are too heavy for one man to
get into place. So the four unite their efforts, first
rolling one man's logs into place and then another's,
until, the logs of all four having been placed, the
result is the same as if each had been enabled to
concentrate into one time the force he could exert in
four different times. . . . But, while great advantages
result from the ability of individuals, by the
combination of labor to concentrate themselves, as it
were, into one larger man, there are other times and
other things in which an individual could accomplish more
if he could divide himself, as it were, into a number of
smaller men. . . . What the division of labor does, is to
permit men, as it were, so to divide themselves, thus
enormously increasing their total effectiveness. To
illustrate from the example used before: While at times
Tom, Dick, Harry and Jim might each wish to move logs, at
other times they might each need to get something from a
village distant two days' journey. To satisfy this need
individually would thus require two days' effort on the
part of each. But if Tom alone goes, performing the
errands for all, and the others each do half a days' work
for him, the result is that all get at the expense of
half a day's effort on the part of each what otherwise
would have required two days' effort. — The
Science of Political Economy —
unabridged: Book III, Chapter 9, The Production of
Wealth: Cooperation — Its Two Ways •
abridged:
Part III, Chapter 7, The Production of Wealth:
Co-operation: Its Two Ways
Co-operation — its Two
Kinds
WE have seen that there are two ways or modes in which
co-operation increases productive power. If we ask how
co-operation is itself brought about, we see that there
is in this also a distinction, and that co-operation is
of two essentially different kinds. . .. There is one
kind of co-operation, proceeding, as it were, from
without, which results from the conscious direction of a
controlling will to a definite end. This we may call
directed or conscious co-operation. There is another kind
of co-operation, proceeding, as it were, from within,
which results from a correlation in the actions of
independent wills, each seeking but its own immediate
purpose, and careless, if not indeed ignorant, of the
general result. This we may call spontaneous or
unconscious co-operation. The movement of a great army is
a good type of co-operation of the one kind. Here the
actions of many individuals are subordinated to, and
directed by, one conscious will, they becoming, as it
were, its body and executing its thought. The providing
of a great city with all the manifold things which are
constantly needed by its inhabitants is a good type of
co-operation of the other kind. This kind of co-operation
is far wider, far finer, far more strongly and delicately
organized, than the kind of co-operation involved in the
movements of an army, yet it is brought about not by
subordination to the direction of one conscious will,
which knows the general result at which it aims, but by
the correlation of actions originating in many
independent wills, each aiming at its own small purpose
without care for, or thought of; the general result. The
one kind of co-operation seems to have its analogue in
those related movements of our body which we are able
consciously to direct. The other kind of co-operation
seems to have its analogue in the correlation of the
innumerable movement, of which we are unconscious, that
maintain the bodily frame — motions which in their
complexity, delicacy and precision far transcend our
powers of conscious direction, yet by whose perfect
adjustment to each other and to the purpose of the whole,
that co-operation of part and function, that makes up the
human body and keeps it in life and vigor, is brought
about and supported. — The Science of Political
Economy —
unabridged: Book III, Chapter 10, The Production of
Wealth: Cooperation — Its Two Kinds •
abridged:
Part III, Chapter 8, Cooperation: Its Two Kinds
To attempt to apply that kind of co-operation which
requires direction from without to the work proper for
that kind of co-operation which requires direction from
within, is like asking the carpenter who can build a
chicken-house to build a chicken also. — The
Science of Political Economy —
unabridged: Book III, Chapter 10, The Production of
Wealth: Cooperation — Its Two Kinds •
abridged:
Part III, Chapter 8, Cooperation: Its Two Kinds
Co-operation and
Competition
MANY if not most of the writers on political economy have
treated exchange as a part of distribution. On the
contrary, it belongs to production. It is by exchange,
and through exchange, that man obtains, and is able to
exert, the power of co-operation which, with the advance
of civilization, so enormously increases his ability to
produce wealth. — The Science of Political
Economy —
unabridged: Book III, Chapter 11, The Production of
Wealth: The Office of Exchange in Production •
unabridged
Chapter 9, The Office of Exchange in Production
THEY who, seeing how men are forced by competition to the
extreme of human wretchedness, jump to the conclusion
that competition should be abolished, are like those who,
seeing a house burn down, would prohibit the use of
fire.
The air we breathe exerts upon every square inch of our
bodies a pressure of fifteen pounds. Were this pressure
exerted only on one side, it would pin us to the ground
and crush us to a jelly. But being exerted on all sides,
we move under it with perfect freedom. It not only does
not inconvenience us, but it serves such indispensable
purposes that, relieved of its pressure, we should
die.
So it is with competition. Where there exists a class
denied all right to the element necessary to life arid
labor, competition is one-sided, and as population
increases must press the lowest class into virtual
slavery, and even starvation. But where the natural
rights of all are secured, then competition, acting on
every hand — between employers as between employed,
between buyers as between sellers — can injure no
one.
On the contrary it becomes the most simple, most
extensive, most elastic, and most refined system of
co-operation that, in the present stage of social
development, and in the domain where it will freely act,
we can rely on for the co-ordination of industry and the
economizing of social forces.
In short, competition plays just such a part in the
social organism as those vital impulses which are beneath
consciousness do in the bodily organism. With it, as with
them, it is only necessary that it should be free. The
line at which the state should come in is that where free
competition becomes impossible — a line analogous
to that which in the individual organism separates the
conscious from the unconscious functions. There is such a
line, though extreme socialists and extreme
individualists both ignore it. The extreme individualist
is like the man who would have his hunger provide him
food; the extreme socialist is like the man who would
have his conscious will direct his stomach how to digest
it. — Protection or Free Trade, chapter 28
econlib
THE mere abolition of protection — the mere
substitution of a revenue tariff for a protective tariff
— is such a lame and timorous application of the
free-trade principle that it is a misnomer to speak of it
as free trade. A revenue tariff is only a somewhat milder
restriction on trade than a protective tariff.
Free trade, in its true meaning, requires not merely the
abolition of protection but the sweeping away of all
tariffs — the abolition of all restrictions (save
those imposed in the interests of public health or
morals) on the bringing of things into a country or the
carrying of things out of a country.
But free trade cannot logically stop with the abolition
of custom-houses. It applies as well to domestic as to
foreign trade, and in its true sense requires the
abolition of all internal taxes that fall on buying,
selling, transporting or exchanging, on the making of any
transaction or the carrying on of any business, save of
course where the motive of the tax is public safety,
health or morals. Thus the adoption of true free trade
involves the abolition of all indirect taxation of
whatever kind, and the resort to direct taxation for all
public revenues.
But this is not all. Trade, as we have seen, is a mode of
production, and the freeing of trade is beneficial
because it is a freeing of production. For the same
reason, therefore, that we ought not to tax anyone for
adding to the wealth of a country by bringing valuable
things into it, we ought not to tax anyone for adding to
the wealth of a country by producing within that country
valuable things. Thus the principle of free trade
requires that we should not merely abolish all indirect
taxes, but that we should abolish as well all direct
taxes on things that are the produce of labor; that we
should, in short, give full play to the natural stimulus
to production — the possession and enjoyment of the
things produced — by imposing no tax whatever upon
the production, accumulation or possession of wealth (the
things produced by labor), leaving everyone free to make
exchange, give, spend or bequeath. —
Protection or Free Trade — Chapter 26:
True Free Trade -
econlib -|- abridged
... go to "Gems from
George"
|
To share this page with a friend:
right click, choose "send," and add your
comments.
|
|
Red links have not been
visited; .
Green links are pages you've seen
|
Essential Documents pertinent
to this theme:
essential_documents
|
|