WE HONOR LIBERTY in name and in form. We set up
her statues and sound her praises. But we have not fully
trusted her. And with our growth so grow her demands. She
will have no half service! Liberty! it is a word to
conjure with, not to vex the ear in empty boastings. For
Liberty means Justice, and Justice is the natural law
— the law of health and symmetry and strength, of
fraternity and co-operation. ...
They who look upon Liberty as having accomplished
her mission when she has abolished hereditary privileges
and given men the ballot, who think of her as having no
further relations to the everyday affairs of life, have
not seen her real grandeur — to them the poets who
have sung of her must seem rhapsodists, and her martyrs
fools! ...
It is not for an abstraction that men have toiled
and died; that in every age the witnesses of Liberty have
stood forth, and the martyrs of Liberty have
suffered.
We speak of Liberty
as one thing, and of virtue, wealth, knowledge, invention,
national strength and national independence as other
things. But, of all these, Liberty is the source, the
mother, the necessary condition. She is to virtue
what light is to color; to wealth what sunshine is to
grain; to knowledge what eyes are to sight. She is the
genius of invention, the brawn of national strength, the
spirit of national independence. Where Liberty rises, there
virtue grows, wealth increases, knowledge expands,
invention multiplies human powers, and in strength and
spirit the freer nation rises among her neighbors as Saul
amid his brethren — taller and fairer. Where Liberty
sinks, there virtue fades, wealth diminishes, knowledge is
forgotten, invention ceases, and empires once mighty in
arms and arts become a helpless prey to freer
barbarians!
Liberty came to a race of slaves crouching under
Egyptian whips, and led them forth from the House of
Bondage. She hardened them in the desert and made of them
a race of conquerors. The free spirit of the Mosaic law
took their thinkers up to heights where they beheld the
unity of God, and inspired their poets with strains that
yet phrase the highest exaltations of thought. ...
read
the whole speech
Henry George: Moses, Apostle of
Freedom (1878 speech)
Each recurring year brings a day on which, in
every land, there are men who, gathering about them their
families, and attired as if for a journey, eat with
solemnity a hurried meal. Before the walls of Rome were
traced, before Homer sung, this feast was kept, and the
event to which it points was even then centuries
old. That event signals the entrance
upon the historic stage of a people on many accounts
remarkable – a people:
- who, though they never founded a great empire
nor built a great metropolis, have exercised upon a large
portion of humankind an influence, widespread, potent,
and continuous;
- who have for nearly two thousand years been
without country or organised nationality, yet have
preserved their identity and faith through all
vicissitudes of time and fortune;
- who have been overthrown, crushed, scattered;
who have been ground, as it were, to very dust, and flung
to the four winds of heaven;
- yet who, though thrones have fallen, and
empires have perished, and creeds have changed, and
living tongues have become dead, still exist with a
vitality seemingly unimpaired.
- They are a people who unite the strangest
contradictions; and whose annals now blaze with glory,
now sound the depths of shame and woe.
The advent of such a people marks an epoch in
the history of the world. But it is not of that advent as
much as of the central and colossal figure around which its
traditions cluster that I propose to speak.
Three great religions place
the leader of the Exodus upon the highest plane they
allot to humankind. To Christendom and to Islam,
as well as to Judaism, Moses is the mouthpiece and
lawgiver of the Most High; the medium, clothed with
supernatural powers, through which the divine will has
spoken. ...
No matter how clearly the descendants
of the kinsfolk, who came into Egypt, at the invitation of
the boy-slave become prime minister, maintained the
distinction of race and the traditions of a freer life,
they must have been powerfully affected by such a
civilisation; and just as the Hebrews of today are Polish
in Poland, German in Germany, and American in the United
States, so, but far more clearly and strongly, the Hebrews
of the Exodus must have been essentially
Egyptian.
It is not remarkable, therefore, that
the ancient Hebrew institutions show in so many points the
influence of Egyptian ideas and customs. What is remarkable
is the dissimilarity. To the unreflecting nothing may seem
more natural than that a people, in turning their backs
upon a land where they had been long oppressed, should
discard its ideas and institutions. But the student of
history, the observer of politics, knows that nothing is
more unnatural. Habits of thought are even more tyrannous
than habits of the body. They make for the masses of people
a mental atmosphere out of which they can no more rise than
out of the physical atmosphere. A people long used to
despotism may rebel against a tyrant; they may break his
statutes and repeal his laws, cover with odium that which
he loved, and honour that which he hated; but they will
hasten to set up another tyrant in his place. A people used
to superstition may embrace a purer faith, but it will be
only to degrade it to their old ideas. A people used to
persecution may flee from it, but only to persecute in
their turn when they get power.
...
The outlines that the record gives us
of the character of Moses – the brief relations that
wherever the Hebrew scriptures are read have hung the
chambers of the imagination with vivid pictures – are
in every way consistent with this idea. What we know of the
life illustrates what we know of the work. What we know of
the work illumines the life.
It was not an empire such as had
reached full development in Egypt, or existed in
rudimentary patriarchal form in the tribes around, that
Moses aimed to found. Nor was it a republic where the
freedom of the citizen rested on the servitude of the
helot, and the individual was sacrificed to the
state.
It was a commonwealth based upon
the individual – a commonwealth whose ideal
it was that every man should sit under his own vine and
fig tree, with none to vex him or make him afraid. It was
a commonwealth:
- in which none should be condemned to ceaseless
toil; in which, for even the bond slave, there should be
hope; and
- in which, for even the beast of burden, there
should be rest.
- A commonwealth in which, in the absence of
deep poverty, the many virtues that spring from personal
independence should harden into a national
character–
- a commonwealth in which the family affections
might knit their tendrils around each member, binding
with links stronger than steel the various parts into the
living whole.
It is not the
protection of property, but the protection of humanity,
that is the aim of the Mosaic code. Its sanctions
are not directed to securing the strong in heaping up
wealth as much as to preventing the weak from being crowded
to the wall. At every point it interposes
its barriers to the selfish greed that, if left unchecked,
will surely differentiate men into landlord and serf,
capitalist and working person, millionaire and tramp, ruler
and ruled.
- Its Sabbath day and Sabbath year secure, even
to the lowliest, rest and leisure.
- With the blast of the Jubilee trumpets the
slave goes free, the debt that cannot be paid is
cancelled, and a re-division of the land secures again to
the poorest their fair share in the bounty of the common
Creator.
- The reaper must leave something for the
gleaner;
- even the ox cannot be muzzled as he treadeth
out the corn.
Everywhere, in everything, the dominant idea is
that of our homely phrase: "Live and let
live!"...
Its lessons have never tended to the essential
selfishness of asceticism, which is so prominent a
feature in Brahmanism and Buddhism, and from which
Christianity and Islamism have not been exempt. Its
injunction has never been "Leave the world to itself that
you may save your own soul" but rather: "Do your duty in
the world that you may be happier and the world be
better." It has disdained no sanitary regulation that
might secure the health of the body. Its promise has been
of peace and plenty and length of days, of stalwart sons
and comely daughters. ...
In the full blaze of the nineteenth
century, when every child in our schools may know as common
truths things of which the Egyptian sages never dreamed;
when the earth has been mapped and the stars have been
weighed; when steam and electricity have been pressed into
our service, and science is wresting from nature secret
after secret – it is but natural to look back upon
the wisdom of three thousand years ago as an adult looks
back upon the learning of a child.
And yet, for all this wonderful
increase of knowledge, for all this enormous gain of
productive power, where is the country in the civilised
world in which today there is not want and suffering
– where the masses are not condemned to toil that
gives no leisure, and all classes are not pursued by a
greed of gain that makes life an ignoble struggle to get
and to keep? Three thousands years of advances, and still
the moan goes up: "They have made our lives bitter with
hard bondage, in mortar and in brick, and in all manner of
service!" Three thousand years of advances! and the piteous
voices of little children are in the moan.
...
Over ocean wastes far wider than the
Syrian desert we have sought our promised land – no
narrow strip between the mountains and the sea, but a wide
and virgin continent. Here, in greater freedom, with vaster
knowledge and fuller experience, we are building up a
nation that leads the van of modern progress. And yet while
we prate of the rights of humanity there are already many
among us thousands who find it difficult to assert the
first of natural rights – the right to earn an honest
living; thousands who from time to time must accept of
degrading charity or starve.
We boast of equality before the law;
yet notoriously justice is deaf to the call of those who
have no gold and blind to the sin of those who
have.
We pride ourselves upon our common
schools; yet after our boys and girls are educated we
vainly ask: "What shall we do with them?" And about our
colleges children are growing up in vice and crime, because
from their homes poverty has driven all refining
influences. We pin our faith to universal suffrage; yet
with all power in the hands of the people, the control of
public affairs is passing into the hands of a class of
professional politicians, and our governments are, in many
cases, becoming but a means for robbery of the
people.
We have prohibited hereditary
distinctions, we have forbidden titles of nobility; yet
there is growing up an aristocracy of wealth as powerful
and merciless as any that ever held sway.
We progress and we progress; we girdle continents
with iron roads and knit cities together with the mesh of
telegraph wires; each day brings some new invention, each
year marks a fresh advance – the power of
production increased, and the avenues of exchange cleared
and broadened. Yet the complaint of "hard times" is
louder and louder; everywhere are people harassed by
care, and haunted by the fear of want. With swift, steady
strides and prodigious leaps, the power of human hands to
satisfy human wants advances and advances, is multiplied
and multiplied. Yet the struggle for mere existence is
more and more intense, and human labour is becoming the
cheapest of commodities. Beside glutted warehouses human
beings grow faint with hunger and shiver with cold; under
the shadow of churches festers the vice that is born of
want.
Trace to its roots the cause that is
producing want in the midst of plenty, ignorance in the
midst of intelligence, aristocracy in democracy, weakness
in strength – that is giving to our civilisation a
one-sided and unstable development – and you will
find it something which this Hebrew statesman three
thousand years ago perceived and guarded
against.
Moses saw that the real cause of
the enslavement of the masses of Egypt was – what
has everywhere produced enslavement – the
possession by a class of land upon which and from which
the whole people must live. He saw that to permit
in land the same unqualified private ownership that by
natural right attaches to the things produced by labour,
would be inevitably to separate the people into the very
rich and the very poor, inevitably to enslave labour
– to make the few the masters of the many, no
matter what the political forms, to bring vice and
degradation no matter what the religion.
...
The life of Moses, like the institutions of Moses,
is a protest against that blasphemous doctrine current
now as it was three thousand years ago, preached oft
times even from Christian pulpits – that the want
and suffering of the masses of humankind flow from a
mysterious dispensation of providence, which we may
lament, but can neither quarrel with nor alter. Let those
who hug that doctrine themselves, those to whom it seems
that the squalor and brutishness with which the very
centres of our civilisation abound are not their affair,
turn to the example of that life. For to them who will
look, yet burns the bush; and to them who will hear,
again comes the voice: "The people suffer: who will lead
them forth?"
Adopted into the immediate family of
the supreme monarch and earthly god; standing almost at the
apex of the social pyramid which had for its base those
toiling millions; priest and prince in a land where prince
and priest might revel in all delights – everything
that life could offer to gratify the senses or engage the
intellect was open to him.
What to him the wail of those who beneath the fierce
sun toiled under the whips of relentless masters? Heard
from granite colonnade or beneath cool linen awning, it
was mellowed by distance to monotonous music. Why should
he question the Sphinx of Fate, or quarrel with destinies
the high gods had decreed? So had it always been, for
ages and ages; so must it ever be. The beetle rends the
smaller insect, and the hawk preys on the beetle; order
on order, life rises from death and carnage, and higher
pleasures from lower agonies. Shall the human be better
than nature? Soothing and restful flows the Nile, though
underneath its placid surface finny tribes wage cruel
war, and the stronger eats the weaker. Shall the gazer
who would read the secrets of the stars turn because
under his feet a worm may writhe? ... read the whole
speech
Henry George: The Condition of Labor
— An Open Letter to Pope Leo XIII in response to
Rerum Novarum (1891)
Your use, in so many passages of your Encyclical, of
the inclusive term “property” or
“private” property, of which in morals
nothing can be either affirmed or denied, makes your
meaning, if we take isolated sentences, in many places
ambiguous. But reading it as a whole, there can be no
doubt of your intention that private property in land
shall be understood when you speak merely of private
property. With this interpretation, I find that the
reasons you urge for private property in land are
eight. Let us consider them in order of presentation.
You urge:
1. That what is bought with rightful property is
rightful property. (RN, paragraph 5) ...
2. That private property in land proceeds from
man’s gift of reason. (RN, paragraphs 6-7.)
...
3. That private property in land deprives no one of the
use of land. (RN, paragraph 8.) ...
4. That Industry expended on land gives ownership in
the land itself. (RN, paragraphs 9-10.) ...
5. That private property in land has the support of the
common opinion of mankind, and has conduced to peace
and tranquillity, and that it is sanctioned by Divine
Law. (RN, paragraph 11.) ...
6. That fathers should provide for their children and
that private property in land is necessary to enable
them to do so. (RN, paragraphs 14-17.) ...
7. That the private ownership of land stimulates
industry, increases wealth, and attaches men to the
soil and to their country. (RN, paragraph 51.)
...
8. That the right to possess private property in land
is from nature, not from man; that the state has no
right to abolish it, and that to take the value of
landownership in taxation would be unjust and cruel to
the private owner. (RN, paragraph 51.)
5. That private property in land has the support of
the common opinion of mankind, and has conduced to
peace and tranquillity, and that it is sanctioned by
Divine Law. (11.)
Even were it true that the common opinion of mankind
has sanctioned private property in land, this would no
more prove its justice than the once universal practice
of the known world would have proved the justice of
slavery.
But it is not true. Examination will show that
wherever we can trace them the first perceptions of
mankind have always recognized the equality of right to
land, and that when individual possession became
necessary to secure the right of ownership in things
produced by labor some method of securing equality,
sufficient in the existing state of social development,
was adopted. Thus, among some peoples, land used for
cultivation was periodically divided, land used for
pasturage and wood being held in common. Among others,
every family was permitted to hold what land it needed
for a dwelling and for cultivation, but the moment that
such use and cultivation stopped any one else could
step in and take it on like tenure. Of the same nature
were the land laws of the Mosaic code. The land, first
fairly divided among the people, was made inalienable
by the provision of the jubilee, under which, if sold,
it reverted every fiftieth year to the children of its
original possessors.
Private property in land as we know it, the
attaching to land of the same right of ownership that
justly attaches to the products of labor, has never
grown up anywhere save by usurpation or force. Like
slavery, it is the result of war. It comes to us of the
modern world from your ancestors, the Romans, whose
civilization it corrupted and whose empire it
destroyed.
It made with the freer spirit of the northern
peoples the combination of the feudal system, in which,
though subordination was substituted for equality,
there was still a rough recognition of the principle of
common rights in land. A fief was a trust, and to
enjoyment was annexed some obligation. The sovereign,
the representative of the whole people, was the only
owner of land. Of him, immediately or mediately, held
tenants, whose possession involved duties or payments,
which, though rudely and imperfectly, embodied the idea
that we would carry out in the single tax, of taking
land values for public uses. The crown lands maintained
the sovereign and the civil list; the church lands
defrayed the cost of public worship and instruction, of
the relief of the sick, the destitute and the wayworn;
while the military tenures provided for public defense
and bore the costs of war. A fourth and very large
portion of the land remained in common, the people of
the neighborhood being free to pasture it, cut wood on
it, or put it to other common uses.
In this partial yet substantial recognition of
common rights to land is to be found the reason why, in
a time when the industrial arts were rude, wars
frequent, and the great discoveries and inventions of
our time unthought of, the condition of the laborer was
devoid of that grinding poverty which despite our
marvelous advances now exists. Speaking of England, the
highest authority on such subjects, the late Professor
Therold Rogers, declares that in the thirteenth century
there was no class so poor, so helpless, so pressed and
degraded as are millions of Englishmen in our boasted
nineteenth century; and that, save in times of actual
famine, there was no laborer so poor as to fear that
his wife and children might come to want even were he
taken from them. Dark and rude in many respects as they
were, these were the times when the cathedrals and
churches and religious houses whose ruins yet excite
our admiration were built; the times when England had
no national debt, no poor law, no standing army, no
hereditary paupers, no thousands and thousands of human
beings rising in the morning without knowing where they
might lay their heads at night.
With the decay of the feudal system, the system of
private property in land that had destroyed Rome was
extended. As to England, it may briefly be said that
the crown lands were for the most part given away to
favorites; that the church lands were parceled among
his courtiers by Henry VIII., and in Scotland grasped
by the nobles; that the military dues were finally
remitted in the seventeenth century, and taxation on
consumption substituted; and that by a process
beginning with the Tudors and extending to our own time
all but a mere fraction of the commons were inclosed by
the greater landowners; while the same private
ownership of land was extended over Ireland and the
Scottish Highlands, partly by the sword and partly by
bribery of the chiefs. Even the military dues, had they
been commuted, not remitted, would today have more than
sufficed to pay all public expenses without one penny
of other taxation.
Of the New World, whose institutions but continue
those of Europe, it is only necessary to say that to
the parceling out of land in great tracts is due the
backwardness and turbulence of Spanish America; that to
the large plantations of the Southern States of the
Union was due the persistence of slavery there, and
that the more northern settlements showed the earlier
English feeling, land being fairly well divided and the
attempts to establish manorial estates coming to little
or nothing. In this lies the secret of the more
vigorous growth of the Northern States. But the idea
that land was to be treated as private property had
been thoroughly established in English thought before
the colonial period ended, and it has been so treated
by the United States and by the several States. And
though land was at first sold cheaply, and then given
to actual settlers, it was also sold in large
quantities to speculators, given away in great tracts
for railroads and other purposes, until now the public
domain of the United States, which a generation ago
seemed illimitable, has practically gone. And this, as
the experience of other countries shows, is the natural
result in a growing community of making land private
property. When the possession of land means the gain of
unearned wealth, the strong and unscrupulous will
secure it. But when, as we propose, economic rent, the
“unearned increment of wealth,” is taken by
the state for the use of the community, then land will
pass into the hands of users and remain there, since no
matter how great its value, its possession will be
profitable only to users.
As to private property in land having conduced to
the peace and tranquillity of human life, it is not
necessary more than to allude to the notorious fact
that the struggle for land has been the prolific source
of wars and of lawsuits, while it is the poverty
engendered by private property in land that makes the
prison and the workhouse the unfailing attributes of
what we call Christian civilization.
Your Holiness intimates that the Divine Law gives
its sanction to the private ownership of land, quoting
from Deuteronomy, “Thou shalt not covet thy
neighbor’s wife, nor his house, nor his field,
nor his man-servant, nor his maid-servant, nor his ox,
nor his ass, nor anything which is his.”
If, as your Holiness conveys, this inclusion of the
words, “nor his field,” is to be taken as
sanctioning private property in land as it exists
today, then, but with far greater force, must the
words, “his man-servant, nor his
maid-servant,” be taken to sanction chattel
slavery; for it is evident from other provisions of the
same code that these terms referred both to bondsmen
for a term of years and to perpetual slaves. But the
word “field” involves the idea of use and
improvement, to which the right of possession and
ownership does attach without recognition of property
in the land itself. And that this reference to
the “field” is not a sanction of private
property in land as it exists today is proved by the
fact that the Mosaic code expressly denied such
unqualified ownership in land, and with the
declaration, “the land also shall not be sold
forever, because it is mine, and you are strangers and
sojourners with me,” provided for its reversion
every fiftieth year; thus, in a way adapted to the
primitive industrial conditions of the time, securing
to all of the chosen people a foothold in the
soil.
Nowhere in fact throughout the Scriptures can the
slightest justification be found for the attaching to
land of the same right of property that justly attaches
to the things produced by labor. Everywhere is
it treated as the free bounty of God, “the land
which the Lord thy God giveth thee.” ...
read the
whole letter
Robert Andelson and James Dawsey: From Wasteland to
Promised Land (synopsis)
In the book of Joshua, we find that although
the Promised Land is a gift from God, it is a gift that has
to be claimed. Even before the actual conquest of the
Promised Land, the Mosaic Law prescribed a method whereby
possession of land was to be rendered pleasing in God's
sight. The Canaanites' claim was forfeited by their
idolatry, with human sacrifice and temple prostitution, and
by their exploitive, monopolistic social order. By
contrast, Israel, to make good its claim,
had to institute a social order that would guard against
the desecration, pollution, and injustices of which its
predecessors were guilty, and would secure to each family
and to every generation within the Hebrew commonwealth the
equal right to the use of the land, of which the Lord was
recognized as the sole absolute owner.
They began with a census of the tribes and families before
the conquest (Num. 26:1-51). Every tribe, excepting Levi,
and within each tribe every family, was to receive its
proportionate share, according to size (Num. 26:55-56), and
ultimately, to ensure fairness, by lot (Num. 34:16-29). The
actual distribution, according to these provisions, was
concluded at Shiloh (Josh. 19:51). According to ancient historian Josephus, the territory
was not divided into shares of equal size but of equal
agricultural value. The landmarks that protected these
allotments were protected by the public and solemn
denunciation of a curse against anyone who should
dishonestly tamper with them (Deut. 27:11-16;
19:14).
As discovered again in our own century, it
is easier to devise a one-time fair apportionment of land
that it is to keep the system from falling apart. This is
why the ancient law established the Jubilee year. At the
end of every fifty years, any alienated lands -- given
away, sold, or lost from unpaid debts -- would be restored
to the original families. Temporary possessors were
to be compensated for any unexhausted improvements they may
have made on the land. Concentrated landownership, and the
division of society into landed and landless classes, was
thereby prevented from creeping into the system.
The Jubilee effectively took the profit
out of landholding as such, leaving no incentive for
speculation. When it was observed -- and historical records
indicate that it was observed for long periods -- the
Jubilee system successfully removed the root cause of
poverty from the Jewish society.
The influence of the Jubilee idea upon early Pennsylvania colonists is evidenced by
the inscription on the Liberty Bell of the biblical words
enjoining the Jubilee year: "Proclaim Liberty throughout
all the land unto all the inhabitants thereof." (Lev.
25:10) The founder of Pennsylvania, William Penn, advocated
that all men be "tenants to the public", and to defray
public expenses instituted a tax on land.
Environmental concern also goes back to
biblical land laws. To prevent the exhaustion of the
soil, a periodic fallow was ordered. "During one year in
every seven, the soil, left to the influences of sun and
frost, wind and rain, was to be allowed to 're-create'
itself after six years' cropping, exactly as the tiller of
the soil renewed his strength, after six days' work, by his
Sabbath day's rest."
As noted, the tribe of Levi did not share
in the equal division of the land, since it was charged
with carrying out religious and public duties. Its
members were entitled to an indemnity from the eleven
tribes who received the land that otherwise would have gone
to them. This indemnity was the tithe --
one-tenth of the product from the land occupied by the
eleven other tribes.
Here, in principle, is the formula for a
just land system in almost any time or place. The
compensation to the Levites maintained the substance of
equal rights to land, alongside of and compatible with
unequal physical division of the land itself. As
Frederick Verinder pointed out in his book My Neighbour's Landmark, joint heirs of a
house may share it equally by occupying it equally or
unequally but "paying the rental into a common fund, from
which each draws an equal share; or they may let the whole
house to someone else and divide the rent equally."
So it is with land. Sharing equally in
the economic rent or value of land through the application
of that value to common uses from which all benefit,
renders private ownership and unequal partition of land
morally and pragmatically benign.
The modern equivalent of removing one's
neighbor's landmark is thus not the private ownership of
land per se, but rather the private appropriation of land
value. "The profit of the earth is for all" (Eccles.
5:9). The Old Testament ethic, to assure everyone the same
natural opportunity, asserts that all people have an equal
right to economic rent, and the Levite tithe demonstrates
that the socialization of rent offsets the ethical and
practical harm resulting from private land ownership. But
there is another basis for its advocacy: Rent should be taken by society because it is a social
product. Rent arises in large measure from two societal
phenomena: the mere presence of population, and community
activity in a particular area. More people means
more demand for space on which to live and work. Community
activities such as roads, schools, protection, parks,
sewage, utilities and other public services, as well as the
totality of private commercial and cultural operations, all
make land more productive or desirable. It follows that a
community which funds such improvements out of its rent
fund will be provided with a stable and growing fund with
which to maintain and improve them. And unlike conventional
taxes, the collection of this fund will enhance, not
penalize, the production of wealth.
Individuals, in their bare capacity as
landowners, do nothing to produce land value. By
withholding sites from use, whether for speculation or for
other reasons, they may generate scarcity, artificially
inflating rent, but this does not reflect any positive
contribution to production on the part of
landowners. ... read the whole
synopsis
James Kiefer: James Huntington and the
ideas of Henry George
Henry George, author of Progress and Poverty, argued
that, while some forms of wealth are produced by human
activity, and are rightly the property of the producers
(or those who have obtained them from the previous owners
by voluntary gift or exchange), land and natural
resources are bestowed by God on the human race, and that
every one of the N inhabitants of the earth has a claim
to 1/Nth of the coal beds, 1/Nth of the oil wells, 1/Nth
of the mines, and 1/Nth of the fertile soil. God wills a
society where everyone may sit in peace under his own
vine and his own fig tree.
The Law of Moses undertook to implement this by making
the ownership of land hereditary, with a man's land
divided among his sons (or, in the absence of sons, his
daughters), and prohibiting the permanent sale of land.
(See Leviticus 25:13-17,23.) The most a man might do with
his land is sell the use of it until the next Jubilee
year, an amnesty declared once every fifty years, when
all debts were cancelled and all land returned to its
hereditary owner.
Henry George's proposed implementation is to tax all
land at about 99.99% of its rental value, leaving the
owner of record enough to cover his bookkeeping expenses.
The resulting revenues would be divided equally among the
natural owners of the land, viz. the people of the
country, with everyone receiving a dividend check
regularly for the use of his share of the earth (here I
am anticipating what I think George would have suggested
if he had written in the 1990's rather than the
1870's).
This procedure would have the effect of making the
sale price of a piece of land, not including the price of
buildings and other improvements on it, practically zero.
The cost of being a landholder would be, not the original
sale price, but the tax, equivalent to rent. A man who
chose to hold his "fair share," or 1/Nth of all the land,
would pay a land tax about equal to his dividend check,
and so would break even. By 1/Nth of the land is meant
land with a value equal to 1/Nth of the value of all the
land in the country.
Naturally, an acre in the business district of a great
city would be worth as much as many square miles in the
open country. Some would prefer to hold more than one
N'th of the land and pay for the privilege. Some would
prefer to hold less land, or no land at all, and get a
small annual check representing the dividend on their
inheritance from their father Adam.
Note that, at least for the able-bodied, this solves
the problem of poverty at a stroke. If the total land and
total labor of the world are enough to feed and clothe
the existing population, then 1/Nth of the land and 1/Nth
of the labor are enough to feed and clothe 1/Nth of the
population. A family of 4 occupying 4/Nths of the land
(which is what their dividend checks will enable them to
pay the tax on) will find that their labor applied to
that land is enough to enable them to feed and clothe
themselves. Of course, they may prefer to apply their
labor elsewhere more profitably, but the situation from
which we start is one in which everyone has his own plot
of ground from which to wrest a living by the strength of
his own back, and any deviation from this is the result
of voluntary exchanges agreed to by the parties directly
involved, who judge themselves to be better off as the
result of the exchanges.
Some readers may think this a very radical proposal.
In fact, it is extremely conservative, in the sense of
being in agreement with historic ideas about land
ownership as opposed to ownership of, say, tools or
vehicles or gold or domestic animals or other movables.
The laws of English-speaking countries uniformly
distinguish between real property (land) and personal
property (everything else). In this context, "real" is
not the opposite of "imaginary." It is a form of the word
"royal," and means that the ultimate owner of the land is
the king, as symbol of the people. Note that
English-derived law does not recognize "landowners." The
term is "landholders." The concept of eminent domain is
that the landholder may be forced to surrender his
landholdings to the government for a public purpose.
Historically, eminent domain does not apply to property
other than land, although complications arise when there
are buildings on the land that is being seized.
I will mention in passing that the proposals of Henry
George have attracted support from persons as diverse as
Felix Morley, Aldous
Huxley, Woodrow Wilson, Helen Keller, Winston Churchill, Leo Tolstoy, William F Buckley Jr, and Sun
Yat-sen. To the Five Nobel Prizes authorized by Alfred
Nobel himself there has been added a sixth, in Economics,
and the Henry George Foundation claims eight of the Economics
Laureates as supporters, in whole or in part, of the
proposals of Henry George (Paul Samuelson, 1970; Milton Friedman, 1976; Herbert A
Simon, 1978; James Tobin, 1981; Franco Modigliani, 1985;
James M Buchanan, 1986; Robert M Solow, 1987; William S Vickrey, 1996).
The immediate concrete proposal favored by most
Georgists today is that cities shall tax land within
their boundaries at a higher rate than they tax buildings
and other improvements on the land. (In case anyone is
about to ask, "How can we possibly distinguish between
the value of the land and the value of the buildings on
it?" let me assure you that real estate assessors do it
all the time. It is standard practice to make the two
assessments separately, and a parcel of land in the
business district of a large city very often has a
different owner from the building on it.) Many cities
have moved to a system of taxing land more heavily than
improvements, and most have been pleased with the
results, finding that landholders are more likely to use
their land productively -- to their own benefit and that
of the public -- if their taxes do not automatically go
up when they improve their land by constructing or
maintaining buildings on it.
An advantage of this proposal in the eyes of many is
that it is a Fabian proposal, "evolution, not
revolution," that it is incremental and reversible. If a
city or other jurisdiction does not like the results of a
two-level tax system, it can repeal the arrangement or
reduce the difference in levels with no great upheaval.
It is not like some other proposals of the form,
"Distribute all wealth justly, and make me absolute
dictator of the world so that I can supervise the
distribution, and if it doesn't work, I promise to
resign." The problem is that absolute dictators seldom
resign. ... read
the whole article
|
To share this page with a friend:
right click, choose "send," and add your
comments.
|
|
Red links have not been
visited; .
Green links are pages you've seen
|
Essential Documents pertinent
to this theme:
|
|