Henry George — A
Perplexed Philosopher
Part III—Recantation
(continued)
Chapter IV — The Idea Of Justice In The
Synthetic Philosophy
As the culminating development of his evolutionary or
Synthetic Philosophy, Mr. Spencer now comes to treat of
those social-economic questions that involve the idea of
justice, in a book which he entitles Justice.
But what is justice?
It is the rendering to each his due. It presupposes a
moral law, and its corollaries, natural rights which are
self-evident. But where in a philosophy that denies spirit,
that ignores will, that derives all the qualities and
attributes of man from the integration of matter and the
dissipation of motion, can we find any basis for the idea
of justice?
"Justice," says Montesquieu, "is a relation of congruity
which really subsists between two things. This relation is
always the same, whatever being considers it, whether it be
God, or an angel, or lastly a man." This, too, in
Social Statics, was Mr. Spencer's conception.
Justice he tells us there means equalness — that is
to say, a relation of congruity or equality which is always
the same, and always apprehensible by men, no matter what
be their condition of development or degree of knowledge.
As the basis of all his reasoning he postulates an inherent
moral sense, which "none but those committed to a
preconceived theory can fail to recognize" — a
perception that bears to morality the same relationship
that the perception of the primary laws of quantity bears
to mathematics; and which enables us to recognize an
"eternal law of things," a "Divine order," in which, and
not in any notions of what is expedient either for the
individual or for all individuals, we may find a sure guide
of conduct, the apprehension of right and wrong. And this
it seems to me is necessarily and universally involved in
the idea of Justice, so that when a man, whatever
be his theories, thinks of right or wrong, just or unjust,
he thinks of a relation, like that of odd and even, or more
and less, which is always and everywhere to be seen by
whoever will look.
But this self-evidence of natural rights the Synthetic
Philosophy denies. It admits the existence of natural
rights — that is to say, rights which pertain to the
individual man as man, and are consequently equal; but it
derives the genesis of these rights, or at least their
apprehension by man, from this process of his gradual
evolution, by virtue of which they evolve, or he becomes
conscious of them, after a certain amount of "social
discipline," and not before. If such rights exist before,
it must be potentially, or in some such way as the Platonic
ideas. But as this would involve an appointed order; and
hence intelligent will, to which we must attribute equity;
and hence God; it seems inconsistent with Mr. Spencer's
present view—not necessarily with that part which
derives our physical constitutions from lower animals and
primarily from the integrations of matter and motion for
this is a mere matter of external form, and that our bodies
come, somehow, "from the dust of the earth" as the
Scriptures put it, is as clear as that ice comes from water
but with that part which gives to the ego the same genesis,
and accounts for our mental and moral qualities by
variation, survival of the fittest, the pressure of
conditions, social discipline and heredity of acquired
characteristics.
Mr. Spencer realizes this inconsistency, for, abandoning
altogether his original derivation and explanation of
justice, he proceeds in Justice to make another derivation
and explanation in accordance with his new philosophy,
devoting to this the first eight chapters, or something
more than a fifth of the book. With its validity or
invalidity, its coherency or incoherency, I am not here
concerned; my object being merely to show how he arrives at
the conception of justice and what it is, so that we may
judge the teachings of Justice from its own avowed
standpoint.
To present Mr. Spencer's argument as intelligibly as I
can, I will make a synopsis of the first eight chapters of
Justice, as far as possible in his own words, but
without quotationmarks, employing smaller type where the
exact words can be used at some length.
These chapters are
1.—Animal Ethics.
During immaturity, benefits received must be inversely
proportioned to capacities possessed. After maturity,
benefits must vary directly as worth, measured by fitness
for the conditions of existence. The ill-fitted must
suffer the evils of unfitness, and the well-fitted prove
their fitness.
2.—Sub-Human
Justice.
The law of sub-human justice is that each individual
shall receive the benefits and the evils of its own
nature and its consequent conduct.
3.—Human Justice.
Each individual ought to receive the benefits and the
evils of his own nature and consequent conduct, neither
being prevented from having whatever good his actions
normally bring him, nor allowed to shoulder off this evil
on other persons.
4.—The Sentiment of
Justice.
Our feeling that we ourselves ought to have freedom to
receive the results of our own nature and consequent
actions, and which prompts maintenance of the sphere for
this free play, results from inheritances of
modifications produced by habit, or from more numerous
survivals of individuals having nervous structures which
have varied in fit ways, and from the tendency of groups
formed of members having this adaptation to survive and
spread. Recognition of the similar freedom of others is
evolved from the fear of retaliation, from the punishment
of interference prompted by the interests of the chief,
from fear of the dead chief's ghost, and from fear of
God, when dead-chief-ghost worship grows into God
worship, and, finally, by the sympathy evolved by
gregariousness.
5.—The Idea of
Justice.
It emerges and becomes definite from experiences,
generation after generation, which provoke resentment and
reactive pains, until finally there arises a conception
of a limit to each kind of activity up to which there is
freedom to act. But it is a long time before the general
nature of the limit common to all cases can be conceived.
On the one hand there is the positive element, implied by
each man's recognition of his claims to unimpeded
activities and the benefits they bring; on the other hand
there is the negative element implied by the
consciousness of limits which the presence of other men
having like claims necessitates. Inequality is suggested
by the one, for if each is to receive the benefits due
his own nature and consequent conduct, then, since men
differ in their powers, there must be differences in the
results. Equality is suggested by the other, since bounds
must be set to the doings of each to avoid quarrels, and
experience shows that these bounds are on the average the
same for all. Unbalanced appreciation of the one is
fostered by war, and tends to social organization of the
militant type, where inequality is established by
authority, an inequality referring, not to the natural
achievement of greater rewards by greater merits, but to
the artificial apportionment of greater rewards to
greater merits. Unbalanced appreciation of the other
tends to such theories as Bentham's greatest happiness
principle, and to communism and socialism. The true
conception is to be obtained by noting that the equality
concerns the mutually limited spheres of action which
must be maintained if associated men are to co-operate
harmoniously, while the inequality concerns the results
which each may achieve by carrying on his actions within
the implied limits. The two may be and must be
simultaneously asserted.
6.—The Formula Of
Justice.
It must be positive in so far as it asserts for each
that, since he is to receive and suffer the good and evil
of his own actions, he must be allowed to act. And it
must be negative in so far as, by asserting this of every
one, it implies that each can be allowed to act only
under the restraint imposed by the presence of others
having like claims to act. Evidently, the positive
element is that which expresses a prerequisite to life in
general, and the negative element is that which qualifies
this prerequisite in the way required, when, instead of
one life carried on alone, there are many lives carried
on together.
Hence, that which we have to express in a precise way
is the liberty of each limited only by the like liberties
of all. This we do by saying, Every man is free to do
what he wills, provided he infringes not the equal
freedom of any other man.
7.—The Authority of this
Formula.
The reigning school of politics and morals has a
contempt for doctrines that imply restraint on the doings
of immediate expediency. But if causation be universal,
it must hold throughout the actions of incorporated men.
Evolution implies that a distinct conception of justice
can have arisen but gradually. It has gone on more
rapidly under peaceful relations, and been held back by
war. Nevertheless, where the conditions have allowed, it
has evolved slowly to some extent, and formed for itself
approximately true expressions, as shown in the Hebrew
Commandments, and without distinction between generosity
and Justice, in the Christian Golden Rule, and in modern
forms in the rule of Kant. It is also shown on the legal
side, in the maxims of lawyers as to natural law,
admitted inferentially even by the despotically minded
Austin.
These, it will be objected, are a priori beliefs. The
doctrine of evolution teaches that a priori beliefs
entertained by men at large must have arisen, if not from
the experiences of each individual, then from the
experiences of the race. Fixed intuitions must have been
established by that intercourse with things which
throughout an enormous past has directly and indirectly
determined the organization of the nervous system, and
certain resulting necessities of thought. Thus had the
law of equal freedom no other than a priori derivations,
it would still be rational to regard it as an adumbration
of a truth, if not still literally true. And the
inductive school, including Bentham and Mill, are, on
analysis, driven to the basis of a priori cognitions.
But the principle of natural equity, expressed in the
freedom of each, limited only by the like freedom of all,
is not exclusively an a priori belief.
Examination of the facts has shown it to
be a fundamental law by conformity to which life has
evolved from its lowest up to its highest forms, that
each adult individual shall take the consequences of
its own nature and actions: survival of the fittest
being the result. And the necessary implication is an
assertion of that full liberty to act which forms the
positive element in the formula of justice; since,
without full liberty to act, the relation between
conduct and consequence cannot be maintained. Various
examples have made clear the conclusion manifest in
theory, that among gregarious creatures this freedom of
each to act has to be restricted; since if it is
unrestricted there must arise such clashing of actions
as prevents the gregariousness. And the fact that,
relatively unintelligent though they are, inferior
gregarious creatures inflict penalties for breaches of
the needful restrictions, shows how regard for them has
come to be unconsciously established as a condition to
persistent social life.
These two laws, holding, the one of all
creatures and the other of social creatures, and the
display of which is clearer in proportion as the
evolution is higher, find their last and fullest sphere
of manifestation in human societies. We have recently
seen that along with the growth of peaceful
co-operation there has been an increasing conformity to
this compound law under both its positive and negative
aspects; and we have also seen that there has gone on
simultaneously an increase of emotional regard for it,
and intellectual apprehension of it.
So that we have not only the reasons
above given for concluding that this a priori belief
has its origin in the experiences of the race, but we
are enabled to affiliate it on the experiences of
living creatures at large, and to perceive that it is
but a conscious response to certain necessary relations
in the order of nature.
No higher warrant can be imagined; and
now, accepting the law of equal freedom as an ultimate
ethical principle, having an authority transcending
every other, we may proceed with our inquiry.
8.—Its
Corollaries.
That the general formula of justice may serve for
guidance, deductions must be drawn severally applicable
to special classes of cases. The several particular
freedoms deducible from the laws of equal freedom may
fitly be called, as they commonly are called, rights.
Rights truly so called are corollaries from the law of
equal freedom, and what are falsely called rights are not
deducible from it.
It is not worth while to examine this argument. It is
sufficient for our purpose to see that in
Justice Mr. Spencer re-asserts the same
principle from which in Social Statics he condemned
private property in land.
Previous
chapter • Next chapter •
Table of Contents
|
To share this page with a friend:
right click, choose "send," and add your
comments.
|
themes:
see_also
|
Red links have not been
visited; .
Green links are pages you've seen
|
|